Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking?
Author(s): James T. Kloppenberg
Source:
The Journal of American History,
Vol. 83, No. 1 (Jun., 1996), pp. 100-138
Published by: Organization of American Historians
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2945476 .
Accessed: 27/07/2011 13:56
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oah. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Organization of American Historians is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The Journal of American History.
http://www.jstor.org
Pragmatism: An
Old
Name for
Some
New Ways of Thinking?
James T. Kloppenberg
William
James
was stuck.
Facing the publication of Pragmatism in
1907,
he
had
to decide whether to
stress the novelty
of his
philosophy or its
continuity with
earlier ideas.
James joked that pragmatism would launch
"something quite like
the
protestant reformation" and predicted that it would be "the
philosophy of
the future."
Yet
he
also believed that he and
his
fellow pragmatists
were building
on a
foundation laid
by philosophers from Socrates to the British
empiricists. To
soften
the
blow
he
was about to deliver, James dedicated
Pragmatism to the
memory
of the
venerated
John
Stuart
Mill
and
added
the
subtitle
A
New Name
for
Some
Old
Ways of Thinking, hoping
that such a
pedigree might
restrain those
inclined
to denounce
his
progeny.
As
my inversion of James's
subtitle suggests,
a
historian
seeking
to
analyze and explain the current revival of
pragmatism
confronts
the same
question James
faced: Have
contemporary pragmatists
resur-
rected
the
ideas
of
earlier thinkers
or
rejected everything
but the name?'
The return of
pragmatism
is
something
of
a surprise. When
David
A.
Hollinger
recounted the
career
of
pragmatism
in
the Journal of American
History
in
1980,
he
noted that
pragmatism
had all but
vanished from
American
historiography
during
the
previous
three
decades.
In
1950, Hollinger recalled,
Henry
Steele
Commager
had
proclaimed pragmatism
"almost
the official
philosophy
of
America"; by 1980,
in
Hollinger's judgment, commentators on
American culture
had
learned
to
get along just
fine
without
it. "If
pragmatism
has a
future,"
Hollinger concluded,
"it will
probably
look
very
different from its
past,
and
the
two
may
not
even share
a
name." Yet
pragmatism today
is not
only
alive
and
James T.
Kloppenberg
is associate
professor
of
history
at
Brandeis
University.
For
stimulating
conversation
and
criticism,
I
am
grateful
to Susan
Armeny,
Thomas
Bender, Casey Blake,
David
Depew, John Diggins,
Richard
Fox,
Giles
Gunn,
Peter
Hansen,
David
Hollinger,
Hans
Joas, James
Livingston, Timothy Peltason,
Am6lie
Oksenberg Rorty, Dorothy Ross,
Charlene Haddock
Seigfried,
Richard
Shusterman,
David
Thelen,
Robert
Westbrook,
and
Joan
Williams.
I
am
particularly
indebted
to Richard
J.
Bernstein and Richard
Rorty
for
their
generosity.
'
William
James to
Henry James,
May 4,
1907,
in The Letters
of
William James,
ed.
Henry
James (2
vols.,
New
York, 1920),
II, 279;
William
James to
Theodore Flournoy, Jan. 2, 1907,
in
Ralph
Barton
Perry,
The
Thought
and Character
of
William
James: As
Revealed
in Unpublished
Correspondence and Notes,
Together
with
His Published
Writings
(2 vols.,
Boston,
1935), II,
452-53. James traced pragmatism
to its
ancient roots
in William
James,
Pragmatism:
A New
Name for
Some
Old Ways of
Thinking
(1907; Cambridge,
Mass., 1978),
30-31.
Ibid., 3.
100
The Journal
of
American History
June 1996
Pragmatism: An Old
Name for
Some New
Ways of
Thinking? 101
well,
it
is
ubiquitous.2
References to
pragmatism occur
with
dizzying
frequency
from
philosophy to
social
science, from the
study
of
literature to that of
ethnicity,
from feminism to
legal theory.
As
Hollinger
predicted,
much
of this
pragmatism
looks
very different from the
original version.
Some
postmodernists
are
attracted
to
pragmatism because it offers
a
devastating critique
of
all philosophical
founda-
tions and
justifies
a
wide-ranging linguistic
skepticism against
all claims of
objectiv-
ity,
consensus, and
truth. So
conceived, as a
species of
postmodernism
rather than
as an
updated
version of
the quest
for
truth
that James identified
with Socrates
and
Mill, pragmatism
has indeed become an
old
name
for new
ways
of thinking.
In
this
essay
I
advance three
arguments:
First, the
early pragmatists
emphasized
'experience,"
whereas
some
contemporary
philosophers
and critics who
have taken
"the
linguistic
turn" are
uneasy
with that
concept.
Second,
the
early pragmatists
believed their
philosophical ideas had
particular
ethical
and
political
consequences,
whereas
some
contemporary
thinkers who
call themselves
pragmatists consider it
merely
a
method of
analysis.
Third, the current
controversy about
pragmatism
matters
profoundly
to
historians. At
stake
is
not
merely
the
historical
meaning
of
early-twentieth-century
pragmatism, important as that
issue
is
for
intellectual
history.
Looming
even
larger
for
historians
in
contemporary
debates
about
pragma-
tism
are
implicit
questions
about our practice
of
historical
scholarship. Two rival
camps
are
struggling
over
the
legacy
of
pragmatism.
Early-twentieth-century prag-
matists envisioned a
modernist discourse of
democratic
deliberation
in which
communities
of
inquiry
tested
hypotheses
in
order to solve
problems;
such
contem-
porary
pragmatists
as
RichardJ. Bernstein
and
Hilary
Putnam
sustain that tradition.
Other
contemporaries
such
as Richard
Rorty
and
Stanley
Fish
present
pragmatism
as a
postmodernist
discourse
of
critical
commentary
that denies
that we
can
escape
the
conventions and
contingencies
of
language
in
order to connect
with
a world
of
experience
outside
texts,
let alone
solve
problems
in
that world.
Connecting
with
experience
is
precisely
what we historians
attempt
to do. These controversies
over
pragmatism
old
and new are thus
tied
directly
to the
legitimacy
of our
practice
in
studying
the
past
and to the
claims of our
community
of
inquiry about
the
significance of the
past
for
the
present.
Experience
and
Language
The
early pragmatists
sought
to
reorient
philosophy
away
from
interminable
and
fruitless
debates
by
insisting
that ideas should
be tested
in
practice.
As
part
of
their
overall commitment to
problem solving, their
conception of experience linked
the
philosophies
of
William
James
and John
Dewey,
the
pragmatists who most
powerfully
influenced
American culture
during
the first
half
of the
twentieth
2
David A.
Hollinger,
"The Problem
of
Pragmatism
in
American
History,"Journal of American
History,
67
(June
1980), 88,
107. Five
years later
Hollinger
cheerfully
admitted that his
obituary
had been
premature.
See
David
A.
Hollinger, In the
American
Province:
Studies in the
History
and
Historiography of Ideas
(Bloomington,
1985),
23,
25,
43. A
splendid
survey is
Richard J.
Bernstein,
"The
Resurgence of
Pragmatism,"
Social
Research,
59
(Winter 1992),
813-40.
102
The
Journal of American
History
June 1996
century.3 What
did James and
Dewey mean by
experience?
Both rejected the
dualisms-the
separation
of
the
mind from the
body, and of
the subject from
the
object-that had
divided
idealists from
empiricists since
Rene Descartes and
John
Locke.
They
were
equally
scornful
of
nineteenth-century
idealists' infatuation
with
introspection
and
positivists' reduction of all
philosophical questions to
matter
and motion. Instead
they preferred
other
metaphors such as
"field"
or
"stream"
or
''circuit" to
suggest the
continuity and
meaningfulness of
consciousness that
had eluded both
empiricists and
rationalists; their
"radical
empiricism" rested on
their
revised
concept
of
consciousness. Immediate
experience as
James and Dewey
conceived of it is
always
relational (it never exists in
the abstract
or
in
isolation
from a world
containing both other
persons and
concrete realities, as
did Descartes's
rationalist
cogito), creative (it
never merely
registers sense data
passively, as did
Locke's
empiricist tabula
rasa),
and imbued with
historically specific
cultural values
(it
is
never
"human" or universal,
but always
personal and
particular). Pragmatists
distrusted all forms of
foundationalism,
all
attempts
to
establish
philosophy
on
unchanging
a
priori
postulates. Rather than
grounding values
in
the bedrock
of
timeless
absolutes, they urged
us to
evaluate all of our
beliefs
-philosophical,
scientific,
religious, ethical, and political
-
before the test
they
considered the most
demanding
of all: our
experience as social and
historical beings.4
The
early
pragmatists' conception
of
testing the truth of ideas
in
experience
ignited
a fire
storm
of
controversy
that
continues
to rage.
Philosophers
such
as
Bertrand Russell,
George
Santayana,
Josiah
Royce,
and Arthur
Lovejoy immediately
targeted
James.
Cultural critics such as
Randolph
Bourne,
Van
Wyck
Brooks,
and
Lewis Mumford and
partisans
of natural
law
such
as
(the
erstwhile
pragmatist)
Walter
Lippmann
and Mortimer Adler later
went
after
Dewey,
as did
Marxists
such
as Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer.
All
these critics
charged
pragmatists
with
elevating
expedient, novel,
narrowly
individualistic,
instrumental,
and tech-
nocratic considerations
above truth and
goodness
as revealed
by
philosophy, art,
or
theology.5
3 In this essay
I
will concentrate on
William James and John Dewey instead
of Charles Sanders Peirce for
two reasons. First, Peirce explained
in
1904 that he "invented" pragmatism "to
express a certain maxim of
logic . . . for the analysis of concepts"
rather than "sensation" and grounded it
on "an elaborate study of the
nature of signs." For the precise reason
why Peirce's ideas have influenced analytic philosophers
and semioticians,
his work is less pertinent here. See
H. S. Thayer, Meaning and
Action:
A Critical
History of
Pragmatism
(Indianapolis, 1981), 493-94. Second,
discussing the recent torrent of work on
Peirce is beyond the scope of
this
essay.
For
a fine
introduction,
see James Hoopes, ed., Peirce on Signs:
Writings
on Semiotic
by
Charles
Sanders Peirce
(Chapel Hill, 1991);
on Peirce's
tortured
life see
Joseph Brent,
Charles Sanders Peirce:
A
Life
(Bloomington, 1993); and on his philosophy
of science, see C. F. Delaney, Science,
Knowledge, and Mind: A
Study in the Philosophy of C. S. Peirce
(Notre Dame, 1993).
4
On
James's concept
of
immediate
experience, see James M. Edie, William
James and Phenomenology
(Bloomington, 1987); more comprehensive
are Perry, Thought and Character of
William James; and Gerald
E.
Myers,
William
James:
His
Life
and Thought (New Haven, 1986). On Dewey's
life
and thought,
see
Robert
B.
Westbrook, John Dewey and American
Democracy (Ithaca, 1991); on qualitative
issues
in
Dewey's philosophy,
see James
Gouinlock, John Dewey's
Philosophy of Value (New York, 1972).
s
A
compilation of these criticisms
is in John Patrick Diggins, The Promise of
Pragmatism: Modernism and
the Crisis ofKnowledge andAuthority (Chicago,
1994). James Hoopes, Robert Westbrook,
and
I
are
unpersuaded
by Diggins's interpretation
of
pragmatism.
For our
explanations
and
Diggins's
response,
see
James
Hoopes,
"Peirce's Community of Signs: The Path
Untaken in American Social Thought," Intellectual
History Newsletter,
17 (1995), 3-6; James
T.
Kloppenberg,
"The Authority of Evidence and
the
Boundaries
of
Interpretation,"
Pragmatism:
An Old
Name
for
Some
New
Ways
of Thinking?
103
Much as
such criticism stung,
it
sharpened
James's
and
Dewey's
formulations
of their ideas.
Some of their
best
writing,
notably
James's
The
Meaning
of
Truth
(1909)
and
Dewey's
Experience
and
Nature
(1925),
came
in
response
to
their
critics.
Their clarifications
reveal
why
some
contemporary
postmodernists'
enthusiasm
and
some
contemporary
traditionalists'
scorn
are misdirected
at James
and
Dewey.
In
Pragmatism
James
had tried to head
off some
misunderstandings
in
advance.
Looking
back
at his
argument,
it is
difficult
to
see how
anyone
could
accuse
him
of identifying
truth with
whatever
it
is convenient
to believe.
He specified
"our
duty
to
agree
with
reality"
and
expressed
exasperation
at
his critics' "favorite
formula
for
describing"
pragmatists
-"persons
who
think
that
by saying
whatever
you
find it pleasant
to say
and
calling
it truth
you
fulfil every
pragmatistic
require-
ment."
To the contrary,
James protested:
"Pent
in,
as the
pragmatist
more
than
anyone
else sees
himself to
be,
between
the whole body
of funded truths squeezed
from
the
past
and
the coercions
of the world
of sense about him,
who
so well
as
he
feels the immense
pressure
of
objective
control under which
our minds perform
their
operations?"6
When
his critics continued
to accuse him
of
counseling
his
readers
to
believe
any
fiction
they
might
find
expedient,
James
responded
by
writing
The
Meaning
of
Truth.
There
he
specified
the circumstances
in which
one might
invoke
the
pragmatic
test
of truth
and clarified
the
conditions necessary
for
verifying
any
proposition
pragmatically.
First,
and
fundamentally,
it must correspond
to
what
is
known
from experience
about
the
natural world.
The
following apparently
unambiguous
sentence
has escaped
the attention
of James's
critics
-and
some of
his
contemporary
champions:
"The notion
of a
reality
independent
of .
. .
us,
taken
from
ordinary
social
experience,
lies at the base
of the
pragmatist
definition
of truth."
Calling
himself an
"epistemological
realist,"
James
explained
that
he
simply
took
for
granted
the existence
of that
independent
reality
and did
not
consider
its
independent
existence philosophically
interesting
or
important.
Second,
to
be
judged
pragmatically
true,
a
proposition
must
be
consistent
with
the
individu-
al's
stock of
existing
beliefs,
beliefs
that
had withstood
the severe
test of
experience.
That,
James
felt sure,
would
rule out simpleminded
wishful
thinking.
Finally,
a
statement
may
be
considered
pragmatically
true
if
it
fulfills those two
conditions
and
yields
satisfaction.
Religious
faith
represented
to James
a
perfect
illustration
of the
appropriate
terrain
for
testing
truth
claims
pragmatically:
in the
absence
of
irrefutable
evidence,
James
judged
relevant
the
consequences
of faith
for
believers.7
17
(1995),
3-6;
James
T.
Kloppenberg,
"The
Authority
of Evidence and
the
Boundaries of
Interpretation,"
ibid., 7-15;
Robert Westbrook,
"The Authority
of
Pragmatism,"
ibid., 16-24;
and
John
Patrick
Diggins,
"Pragmatism
and
the
Historians,"
ibid.,
25-30.
On
critics who valued
the
capacities
of
creative
individuals
above
pragmatists'
concerns
with communities
of
discourse
and
social
justice,
see
Casey
Nelson
Blake,
Beloved
Community:
The Cultural
Criticism
of Randolph
Bourne,
Van
Wyck
Brooks,
Waldo Frank,
and Lewis
Mumford
(Chapel
Hill,
1990).
On Walter Lippmann
and
Mortimer
Adler,
see Edward
A. Purcell
Jr.,
The
Crisis
of
Democratic
Theory:
Scientific
Naturalism
andthe
Problem
of
Value (Lexington,
Ky.,
1973).
On
Theodor
Adorno
and Max
Horkheimer,
see
Martin Jay,
The
Dialectical
Imagination:
A History
of
the
Frankfurt
School
and
the
Institute
of Social Research,
1923-1950
(Boston,
1973).
6James,
Pragmatism,
111-12.
7
William James,
The
Meaning
of
Truth
(1909;
Cambridge,
Mass., 1975),
117, 106,
126-28.
104 The
Journal of American History June
1996
Dewey,
whose
prodding had
helped spur James to refine his position,
likewise
argued throughout
his
long
career that we should conceive of all our
knowledge
as
hypotheses to be tested in
experience.
At the core of James's and
Dewey's pragmatism was experience
conceived, not
as
introspection, but as the
intersection of the conscious self with the world.
They
conceived of knowing subjects
as embodiments of reason, emotion, and
values,
and
they emphasized the
inadequacy
of
philosophers' attempts to freeze,
split
apart,
and
compartmentalize
the
dynamic continuities and multiple
dimensions
of life
as we live it. They
conceived of individuals as always enmeshed in
social
conditions, yet selecting what
to attend to from the multiplicity of
conscious
experience, and making history
by making choices. They conceived of
experience
as
intrinsically and irreducibly
meaningful, and they insisted that its
meanings
were
not
predetermined
or
deducible
from
any all-encompassing pattern.
They
argued
that
meanings emerge
as cultures
test their values
in
practice
and that we
encounter expressions of those
meanings
in
the historical record.
Language was
thus
crucial for
understanding the experience of others, but for
James
and
Dewey language
was
only
one
important part
of a
richer, broader
range
that
included
interpersonal,
aesthetic, spiritual, religious, and
other
prelinguistic
or
nonlinguistic
forms of
experience.
Moreover, they
realized that
language
not
only
feeds
the
imagination but
also
places
constraints on
understanding by
specifying
a
particular range
of
meanings.
In
Pragmatism,
James
wrote,
"All
truth
thus
gets
verbally
built
out,
stored
up,
and
made
available
for
everyone. Hence,
we must
talk
consistently, just
as we must
think consistently." Although
James
appreciated
what
is
now characterized as
the
arbitrariness
of
signifiers,
he
drew
the
following
noteworthy conclusion: "Names
are
arbitrary, but
once
understood
they
must
be
kept
to. We mustn't now call
Abel 'Cain'
or
Cain
'Abel.'
If
we
do,
we
ungear
ourselves from the whole
book
of
Genesis,
and
from
all its connexions with
the
universe of
speech and fact down
to the
present
time."
We
cannot test
every
proposition ourselves
or
enter the immediate
experience
of others. Yet
we
never-
theless have access
to
verifiable
historical
knowledge,
even
if
only
indirectly
and
through language.
"As true as
past
time
itself was,
so true
was
Julius
Caesar,
so
true were antediluvian
monsters,
all
in
their
proper
dates
and
settings.
That
past
time itself
was,
is
guaranteed by
its coherence with
everything
that's
present.
True
as the
present
is the
past
was also."8
When
dealing
with
verifiable
data,
whether
about
Caesars
or
about
ceratopsians,
we
place
each
datum
in
the
web
of evidence
we humans have
been spinning
for centuries. Even when
considering
unverifiable
narratives such as
Genesis, we
risk
losing
the coherence that makes
communication
possible
unless
we
preserve
meanings
within
our
web
of cultural
memory.
Dewey
shared that
appreciation
of the
importance
of
symbols
and the
indispens-
ability
of common
understandings.
"All
discourse,
oral
or
written,"
he conceded
in
Experience
and
Nature, "says
things
that
surprise
the
one
that
says
them." But
that makes communication
difficult,
not
impossible.
Conversation understood
as
8
James,
Pragmatism,
102-3.
Pragmatism:
An
Old Name for
Some
New
Ways
of
Thinking?
lOS
. .....
...
.
.
.
. .. is.
......~l
M~~~~~
Wilia
Jaes
in
97,te
ya Pragmtism
a
pbise.Treh
epaized
S~~~cnto
une
whc our1 mind
pefr
thi
operaions,
rrqusite
to
ndraking
soci.a:,,l actio.
Throug langag
"th .r.sult
of con-..
jon
exeiec
are cosidre
an trnmitd
Evnt
cano
bepasdfo
106 The Journal of American History June 1996
one to another, but meanings may be shared by means of signs"; eventually such
sharing
converts "a
conjoining activity into a community of interest and endeavor."
Dewey acknowledged the challenge of such communication: "mutual interest in
shared meanings" does not emerge "all at once or completely." LikeJames, however,
Dewey emphasized that such communication can yield provisional understandings
of the
past,
its
meanings for the present, and its role
in
the formulation of shared
social
aspirations.
For
Dewey, dialogue between individuals
in
community, with
its "direct give and take," provided the model for such communication: "the
winged words
of
conversation
in
immediate intercourse have a vital import lacking
in
the fixed and frozen words of written speech."9
Dewey realized that the concept of experience caused difficulties for many
analytic philosophers, who defined philosophy as the study of language and logic,
but
despite
their
criticism,
he
clung
to it to the end of
his
life.
Dewey toyed
with
exchanging
the
word "experience" for "culture" as late as 1951, but
in
the end
he
refused: "we need a cautionary and directive word,
like
experience, to remind
us that the world which is lived, suffered and enjoyed as well as logically thought
of, has
the
last word
in
all human inquiries and surmises."
10
In short, the pragmatic
sensibility
of
James and Dewey was a profoundly historical sensibility.
Listing some
of
the thinkers who aligned themselves with James and Dewey
suggests
their enormous
impact. Sociologists
such as
George
Herbert
Mead, legal
theorists such as
Oliver Wendell
Holmes
Jr.
and Louis
D.
Brandeis,
economists
such as Richard
T.
Ely, political
theorists such as
Herbert Croly, theologians
such
as Walter Rauschenbusch and Reinhold Niebuhr,
founders
of the
National
Association
for the
Advancement of
Colored People
such as W.
E. B. Du Bois
and William
English Walling,
and feminists such as
Jane
Addams and
Jessie
Taft
all derived
from
pragmatism
a
conception
of
experience
and a
way
of
thinking
about abstract
and
concrete
problems
that oriented
them to
historical
analysis
and
away
from inherited
dogmas.
Those who looked to
philosophy
and social
science
for
solid, permanent principles
found
pragmatism disappointing
and unattractive.
But
many
of those
who shared
the
belief
of
James
and
Dewey
that
the
shift
from
absolutes
to
the test of
experience might encourage independent thinking
and
democratic
decision
making
endorsed
pragmatism
because
it unsettled traditional
ways
of
thinking
without
sinking
into
the
morass
of
subjectivism
that swallowed
some
turn-of-the-century rebels,
such
as
Friedrich
Nietzsche.
The
steadying
lifeline
of
experience prevented pragmatists
from
sliding
into
fantasy, cynicism,
or
self-
indulgence.
As the
ripples pragmatism
sent across American
thought
extended wider and
wider
during
the
early
twentieth
century, they
met -and
eventually
were
sub-
merged by
-more
powerful
waves
coming
from other
directions.
Among
the most
important
of
these was
enthusiasm
for the
certainty widely
attributed
to the
natural
sciences,
which
stood
in
sharp
contrast
to the
pragmatists' forthright
admission
9
John
Dewey, Experience and Nature,
in
John Dewey,
The
Later
Works,
1925-1953,
ed. Jo Ann Boydston
(17 vols., Carbondale, 1981-1990), I,
152; John Dewey, The
Public
and Its Problems,
ibid., II, 330-31.
10
Dewey, Experience and Nature,
appendix 2 (1951), 372.
Pragmatism:
An
Old
Name for
Some
New
Ways
of
Thinking?
107
of
uncertainty.
Behaviorists
in
psychology,
sociology,
and
political
science
adopted
Dewey's enthusiasm
for
testing
hypotheses
but
jettisoned
his
concern with
the
qualitative
dimensions of
experience
and
inquiry
in
the
human
sciences.
"
Philosophers
turned
increasingly
toward the
models
provided
by
mathematics
and
physical
science,
a trend
already
underway before
European
emigres
began
arriving
in
the
United
States
in
the
1930s.
The
emigres'
quest
for
precision
and
their
impatience
with
pragmatism
combined
to
transform
American
philosophy
departments
by
elevating
the
study
of
language
and
logic
and
marginalizingJames's
and
Dewey's
concerns with
epistemology,
ethics,
and
political
philosophy.
A
discipline
scurrying
to
master the
logical positivism of
Rudolf
Carnap,
which
sought
to
rid
philosophy
of
all
questions
that could
not be
answered
through
scientific
verification, had
little
interest
in
the
early
pragmatists'
attachment to
immediate
experience
and their
democratic
reformist
sensibilities.
Dewey
had
described the
writings
that
launched
the
analytic
philosophy
movement,
which
sought
to
reduce
philosophy
to
propositional
logic,
as "an
affront
to
the
common-sense
world of
action,
appreciation,
and affection."
The work of
the
British
philosophers
Bertrand
Russell
and G. E.
Moore,
Dewey
wrote,
threatened to
"land
philosophy
in
a
formalism
like
unto
scholasticism."
James had
urged
Russell to
"say
good-bye
to
mathematical logic
if
you
wish to
preserve
your
relations
with concrete
realities!"
But
many
midcentury
American
philosophers
preferred
Carnap
and Russell to
"common
sense"
and "concrete
realities";
they shared
Russell's
long-standing
con-
tempt
for
pragmatism.
The
new
breed
of
analytic
philosophers
shunned
history,
shifted
toward technical
discourse,
and
judged
meaningless
all
propositions
that
could not
be
verified
by
scientific
procedures.James
wrote
about
religious
experience
and
Dewey
about
aesthetics,
ethics,
and
politics
in
the
hope
of
helping
philosophy
escape
such
a
narrowly
restricted role.'2
Developments
within
the
pragmatist
camp
also
made
it
increasingly vulnerable
to such
attacks.
In
the
1930s
and
1940s
some
champions
of
pragmatism
tried to
popularize
the
ideas
of
James
and
Dewey
by
simplifying
them for
mass
consump-
tion. Whereas
James
and
Dewey
had
urged
their
readers to think
critically
about
their
own
experience
and to take
responsibility
for
shaping
their
culture,
such
writers as
Will
Durant,
Irwin
Edman,
Horace
Kallen,
Max
Otto,
Harry
Overstreet,
John Herman
Randall,
and
Thomas
Vernor Smith made
available versions of
pragmatism
that
simply endorsed the
rough-and-ready
democratic sentiments
of
most
middle-class
Americans.
Such efforts
did
little to
bolster
the
prestige
of
"
On
the
triumph of
scientism in
American social
science,
see
Dorothy
Ross,
The
Origins
of
American
Social
Science
(Cambridge,
Eng.,
1991),
390-470.
12
On the
relation
between
scientism
and
the
transformation
of
philosphy, see
Daniel J.
Wilson,
Science,
Community, and
the
Transformation
of
American
Philosophy,
1860-1930
(Chicago, 1990);
and
Laurence C.
Smith,
Behaviorism and
Logical
Positivism:
A
Reassessment
of
the Alliance
(Stanford,
1986).
For
Dewey's
judgment
of
Bertrand
Russell
and G. E.
Moore,
see
John
Dewey,
Essays in
Experimental
Logic,
in
John
Dewey,
The Middle
Works,
1899-1924, ed. Jo Ann
Boydston (15
vols.,
Carbondale,
1976-1983), X,
357-58.
William
James
to
Bertrand
Russell, Oct.
4, 1908,
inJames,
Meaning of
Truth,
299-300. Russell's
jibe
appeard
in
Bertrand
Russell,
"Dewey's New
Logic,"
in
The
Philosophy
ofJohn
Dewey,
ed. Paul A.
Schilpp
(1939; New
York, 1951),
135-56. On
this
volume, see
Westbrook, John
Dewey and
American
Democracy,
496-500.
108 The Journal
of American History June
1996
pragmatism among professional philosophers or other American intellectuals aspir-
ing
to scientific
precision rather than democratic deliberation.'3
After Dewey died
in
1952, his ideas faded quickly into the background. Even
though one of the most prominent thinkers of the post-World War II period,
Reinhold Niebuhr, shared many of Dewey's, and especially James's, ideas, his
critique
of
Dewey's optimism helped discredit pragmatism as too sunny minded
for
serious intellectuals. As Richard Rorty has put it, pragmatism was crushed
between
"the
upper
and the nether millstones":
a
revived interest
in
theology
or
existentialism for some, the "hard-edged empiricism" of Carnap for others. For
reasons reflecting changes within philosophy and in the broader culture, then,
American intellectuals during the 1950s and 1960s either forgot about pragmatism
or, as Hollinger put it, learned to get along without it. That is no longer true.
Explaining
the
resurgence
of
pragmatism requires sketching
the
complex cultural
changes that cleared the ground and made possible its return.
14
First the claims to objectivity of the natural sciences, which had intimidated
humanists while they inspired philosophers and social scientists, were rocked by
the
historicist analysis
of
Thomas Kuhn, whose significance
in
this transformation
is difficult
to
overestimate. Many
of the schemes
for
social engineering
hatched
by
enthusiasts
for
science led
to
results that
ranged
from
disappointing (the
War
on
Poverty) to disastrous (the war
in
Vietnam), as both the findings of researchers
and their
application
to
social problems
were shown to
be grounded
in
questionable
assumptions and, despite
the scientists' notion of
value
neutrality, susceptible
to
appropriation
for
ideological purposes."1
Then
social scientists
began
to
admit what
pragmatists and such practitioners
of the
Geisteswissenschaften (human sciences)
as
Wilhelm
Dilthey
had
known since the nineteenth
century:
Because human
experi-
ence is
meaningful, understanding
not
only expression
but
also
behavior
requires
interpreting
the
complex
and
shifting systems
of
symbols through
which individuals
encounter the world and with which
they try
to
cope
with
it.
Meanings
and
intentions change
over time
and across cultures;
as
that
realization
spread, hopes
of
finding
a universal
logic
or a
general
science
of
social
organization
faded.
In
their
place emerged hermeneutics,
which relies
on methods
of
interpretation
to
achieve
understanding
of
historical
experience
and
forgoes
efforts
to
generate
rules
of
transhistorical
human
behavior.
13
George
Cotkin, "Middle-Ground
Pragmatists:
The Popularization
of Philosophy
in American
Culture,"
Journal of
the History of Ideas,
55 (April 1994),
2
83-302. On
Will Durant, see Joan Shelley Rubin, The
Making
of Middlebrow
Culture
(Chapel
Hill, 1992).
14
See
Richard Wightman
Fox, Reinhold
Niebuhr:
A
Biography
(New
York, 1985); and
Daniel
F.
Rice,
Reinhold
Niebuhr
andJohn
Dewey: An American
Odyssey (Albany, 1993).
Richard
Rorty, "Pragmatism
without
Method," in
Richard Rorty, Philosophical
Papers,
vol. I:
Objectivity,
Relativism, and
Truth (New
York, 1991),
64. On
the shift of American philosophy departments
away
from pragmatism and toward
analytic
philosophy
and logical
positivism,
see Hilary Putnam, Reason,
Truth, and
History (New York, 1981), 103-26;
Bernstein,
"Resurgence
of Pragmatism,"
815-17; and a
fine overview, David
Depew, "Philosophy,"
in
Encyclopedia
of the
United
States in the Twentieth Century, ed.
Stanley
Kutler
(4
vols.,
New
York, 1996), IV, 1635-63.
1I
Thomas
S. Kuhn, The
Structure of Scientific
Revolutions (Chicago,
1962);
Paul Hoyningen-Huene,
Recon-
structing Scientific
Revolutions:
Thomas S.
Kuhn's
Philosophy
of Science, trans.
Alexander T. Levine
(Chicago,
1993). On the
uses of social science
in
public
policy, see`Ellen
Herman, The Romance
of American
Psychology:
Political
Culture in the Age
of Experts (Berkeley,
1995).
Pragmatism:
An Old
Name for
Some New
Ways of
Thinking?
109
Marching behind
the
banner
of hermeneutics
came an
influential
band
of
scholars
who
challenged
the ideal
of
scientific
objectivity
in
the human
sciences:
Peter
Winch,
Clifford
Geertz,
Charles Taylor,
Anthony
Giddens,
Paul Ricoeur,
Michel Foucault,
Jacques
Derrida,
Hans-Georg
Gadamer,
andJUrgen
Habermas
-
a
new
litany of
saints proclaiming
variations
on a revolutionary
gospel
of interpreta-
tion. They spoke
a
different
language
than
did those
natural scientists,
philosophers,
and social
scientists who sought
to
escape
the clutter
of history. Instead
of
timeless
principles
and truth,
they
referred to revolutionary
paradigm
shifts,
incommensura-
ble
forms of
life,
the
complexities
of thick
description,
competing
communities
of discourse, archaeologies
of
knowledge,
the universal
undecidability
of texts,
the
inescapability
of
prejudices,
and
the colonization
of life worlds
by an
omnivorous
technostructure.
16
Although among
these
thinkers
only
Habermas
explicitly
placed
himself within
the
pragmatic
tradition,
Americans familiar
with James
and Dewey
noted
the
similarities
between
recent historicist
critiques
of
the
sciences and social
sciences
and
those
of the
early
pragmatists.
As
the
work
of these
thinkers,
many
of
whom
were
often
grouped
together
(unhelpfully
and
even
misleadingly)
under
the
rubric
"postmodernist,"
became
increasingly
influential,
many
scholars began
to move
away
from the
model
of the natural
sciences and
toward
forms of
analysis
more
congenial
to hermeneutics and
history,
most
notably
toward pragmatism."7
Despite
the undeniable importance
of those broad
changes
in
American thought,
the
resurgence
of
pragmatism
is largely
due
to the
remarkable
work
done
by
the
Trojan
horse of
analytic
philosophy,
Richard Rorty.
Rorty's
historicism has had
such
explosive
force
because
he attacked the citadel
of
philosophy
from within.
Troubling
as was his
insistence that
philosophy
could
never attain
the scientific
status
analytic
philosophers
yearned
for,
even
more
unnerving
was
Rorty's equally
blunt
judgment
that
the
grail
of
objective
knowledge
would
likewise
continue
to
elude the natural sciences and
the social
sciences.
Rorty
first
established
his
creden-
tials
with
papers
discussing
standard
topics
in the
analytic
tradition.
But
in
his
introduction
to
The
Linguistic
Turn
(1967),
he
suggested
that the conflicts
within
analytic
philosophy
(between
J.
L. Austin's
ordinary-language
philosophy
and
Carnap's logical
positivism,
for
example)
were so fundamental
that
they
could
not be
resolved, thus subtly
challenging
the idea of progress
in
problem
solving
that
analytic philosophers
took for
granted.'8
Over
the
next decade
Rorty
broadened
his focus and
sharpened
his
critique.
Echoing arguments
made
byJames
and
Dewey
but
presenting
them
in
the discourse
of
analytic philosophy,
he insisted
in
Philosophy
and
the Mirror
of
Nature
(1979)
that
problems
such
as
mind-body
dualism,
the
correspondence
theory
of
truth,
16
See
Richard
J.
Bernstein,
The Restructuring
of
Social and
Political
Theory (New
York, 1976);
Fred
R.
Dallmayr
and
Thomas
A. McCarthy,
eds.,
Understanding and Social
Inquiry (Notre Dame, 1977);
and
Quentin
Skinner,
ed.,
The Return
of
Grand
Theory
in the
Human Sciences (Cambridge,
Eng., 1985).
17
On
these
changes
in
philosophy
and
political
theory,
seeJohn Rajchman
and Cornel
West,
eds., Post-Analytic
Philosophy (New
York,
1985);
and David
Held,
ed., Political
Theory Today (Stanford,
1991).
18
Richard
Rorty,
ed., The
Linguistic
Turn: Recent
Essays
in
Philosophical
Method
(Chicago,
1967).
110
The Journal of American History
June
1996
theories of
knowledge and theories of
language, and
ultimately the entire concep-
tion of a
systematic philosophy
devoted to finding foundations
for objective knowl-
edge all
rested on misconceptions.
He urged his fellow
philosophers to move "from
epistemology to hermeneutics"
and to practice "philosophy
without mirrors,"
embracing
interpretation and
surrendering the vain hope that
their writings might
accurately
reflect the
world as
it
really
is.
Systematic
philosophers, such as John
Locke, Immanuel
Kant, and Rudolf
Carnap, who sought a
science of knowledge
that would disclose
objective truth, should
give way
to
"edifying philosophers,"
such
asJames
and
Dewey,
who
would contribute to the
"conversation of the West"
without
promising results
philosophy would never be able to
deliver. Although
others
had
begun
to
offer variations on
this theme of
"historicist undoing," to
use Ian
Hacking's phrase for it,
Rorty's assault seemed
especially dramatic because
it held
out no alternative solutions.19
In
Consequences ofPragmatism
(1982), Rorty defended his
heretical historicism.
We must admit that "there is
nothing deep
down
inside us
except
what
we
have
put
there
ourselves";
our most cherished
standards and
practices
are
merely
conventions.
Science, Rorty
concluded
with the
provocative
bluntness
that has
become
his
trademark,
is
only
"one
genre
of
literature";
all efforts to find
solid,
unchanging knowledge are futile.20
Rorty
himself
realized
that there was little
in
these
claims
that was
completely
new. But
because enthusiasm for science had
overshadowed
the historicism of
earlier
pragmatists,
and
because
Anglo-American
philosophers
in
particular had marched down a road marked "truth"
only
to
find
James and Dewey waiting there
for
them, Rorty's
revival
of
pragmatism
seemed
revolutionary.
Against
critics who assailed
him
as a
relativist, Rorty responded
that
the
notion
of
relativism itself becomes incoherent when we
appreciate
the
contingent
status
of
all
our
knowledge.
From his
perspective,
there is
nothing
for
"truth" to
be
relative to
except
our
tradition,
our
purposes,
and
our
linguistic
conventions.
When
we have
come to
that
realization,
a calm
acceptance
of
our
condition
becomes
possible. While
pragmatism
cannot
offer
objectivity,
neither
does
it threaten the
survival
of
civilization.
Revolutionary
as his
message was, Rorty's
mood
was down-
right upbeat.
He
proclaimed pragmatism
"the
chief
glory
of
our
country's
intellec-
tual
tradition" and noted that
James
and
Dewey, although
asking
us
to
surrender
19
Richard Rorty, Philosophy andthe Mirror of Nature
(Princeton, 1979). See Alan Malachowski, ed., Reading
Rorty:
Critical
Responses
to
Philosophy
and the Mirror
of Nature
(Cambridge, Mass., 1990);
and
Herman
J.
Saatkamp, ed., Rorty and Pragmatism (Nashville, 1995).
Ian Hacking, "Two Kinds of 'New Historicism'
for
Philosophers," in History and. .
.:
Histories within
the Human Sciences, ed. Ralph Cohen and Michael S.
Roth
(Charlottesville, 1995), 296-318.
The
very useful
words "historicism" and "historicist" continue to baffle
some historians, probably due to
their
almost opposite
meanings
in the
work of
the
philosopher
of science
Karl
Popper and in contemporary critical discourse. Popper
used "historicism" to designate (and denigrate) any theory
(such as Marxism) that purports to predict
the future course of human
events
according
to
ostensibly
scientific
laws. More recent commentators understand historicism
as "the theory that social and cultural phenomena are
historically determined and that each period in history
has its own values that are not directly applicable to
other
epochs.
In
philosophy that implies
that
philosophical
issues find their place, importance, and definition
in a specific cultural milieu. That is certainly Rorty's
opinion." Ibid., 298.
20
Rorty, Philosophy and
the
Mirror of Nature, 392;
Richard Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays,
1972-1980 (Minneapolis, 1982), xl,
xliii.
112
The
Journal
of American
History
June
1996
little
about
ideas
or
experiences."
James's
and
Dewey's
talk about
the
relation
between
ideas
and experiences,
in
Rorty's judgment,
"runs
together
sentences
with
experiences
-
linguistic
entities
with introspective
entities."
They
"should
have
dropped
the
term
experience
rather
than
redefined
it."
"My
alternative
Dewey,"
he concludes wistfully,
"would have
said,
we can construe
'thinking'
as
simply
the
use
of
sentences."22
Seeing
the linguistic
turn
as a
step
forward rather
than
a dead
end,
Rorty
dogmatically
refuses to accept
any philosophy
in which
something
other than
language,
namely,
experience
-
understood
not as
introspection
but
as the
intersection
between
the conscious
self
and
the
world
-plays
an
important
part.
As
Rorty
now admits,
James
and Dewey
had
a
very
different
conception
of
philosophy,
and that
difference
continues
to
manifest
itself
in
the contrasting
versions
of
pragmatism
in
contemporary
scholarship.
Given
historians'
strong
com-
mitments
to
referentiality
in
writing
history,
to
the
possibility
of
connecting
the
arguments
we construct
to the
lives we
write about,
and
to testing
those arguments
within
our
scholarly
community,
the
early pragmatists'
emphasis
on
experience
will
remain
for
historians
an attractive
alternative
to
Rorty's
narrow
interest
in sentences.
Rorty's
move away
from James
and
Dewey's
view of
experience
and toward
a
new
cultural
ideal
in
which
poets
and
novelists
would
replace
philosophers
first
became
clear
in his
elegant,
widely
read
Contingency,
Irony,
and Solidarity
(1989).
His shift has
coincided
with the
new
tendency
of some
literary
critics to characterize
themselves
as
pragmatists.
Just
as dissatisfaction
with
prevailing
orthodoxies
has
sparked
novel
approaches
in
philosophy
and the
social sciences,
so many
students
of literature
have
deserted
the New
Criticism
and
structuralism
and turned
toward
pragmatism.
Reversing
the
common
tendency,
stemming
from
the
writings
of
Randolph
Bourne and
Van Wyck
Brooks and
reaching
fruition
in
Lewis
Mumford's
The
Golden
Day (1925),
to contrast
the pragmatists'
supposedly
arid fetish
with
technique
with the
transcendentalists'
celebration
of
imagination,
some
critics
now
invoke
a
refashioned
pragmatism
in
their
constructions
of a
rich,
home-grown
literary
heritage.
For
example,
Richard
Poirier
argues
in
Poetry
and
Pragmatism
(1992)
for a continuous
tradition
of
"linguistic
skepticism"
running
from Ralph
Waldo
Emerson
through
William
James
to
the modernist
poets
Robert
Frost,
Gertrude Stein,
Wallace
Stevens,
and
T. S. Eliot.
Those
poets
share,
according
to
Poirier,
"a
liberating
and
creative
suspicion
as to
the
dependability
of words
and
syntax,
especially
as it relates
to
matters
of
belief."23
22
Richard
Rorty,
"Dewey
between
Hegel
and
Darwin,"
in Modernist
Impulses
in the
Human
Sciences,
1870-
1930,
ed. Dorothy
Ross
(Baltimore,
1994),
46-68.
In
this essay
Rorty
acknowledges
his debt
to
intellectual
historians
for
demonstrating
the difference
between
the
historical
Dewey
and his "hypothetical
version"
but
then
contends
that
the
ideas
of
Dewey's
generation
no longer
make
sense.
23
Richard
Poirier,
Poetry
and Pragmatism
(Cambridge,
Mass., 1992),
5.
On
pragmatism
as the
antithesis
of
literary
theory
and
a rationale
for
critics to focus
on recovering
authors'
intentions,
see
Steven
Knapp
and
Walter
Benn
Michaels,
"Against
Theory,"
Critical Inquiry,
8
(Summer
1982),
723-42.
For
the claim
that
we
must supplement
pragmatism
with
other
value
orientations
(such
as Marxism)
because
the
pragmatic
method
"cannot
help us
do
the social
work
of transformation,"
see Frank Lentricchia,
Criticism
and Social
Change
(Chicago,
1983),
4. Stanley
Fish argues
that
we create
the meaning
of
texts
when
we
interpret
them; trying
to
catch
what
Fish
means
by
pragmatism
is thus
like
trying
to
catch
a fly
with
a fish
net.
See,
for
example,
Stanley
Fish,
Doing
What
Comes
Naturally
(Durham,
1989).
On
one version
of Fish's
pragmatism,
see
the
examination
of
legal
theory
below.
Pragmatism:
An
Old Name
for
Some New
Ways of
Thinking?
113
Poirier
enlists James
to provide
an
American
alternative to
varieties of
post-
structuralism
imported
from
France
and
fashionable
among
contemporary
critics.
He
quotes
a
phrase fromJames's The
Principles
ofPsychology
on "the
re-instatement
of the
vague
to
its
proper place
in
our
mental
life" -a
phrase
consistent
with
James's
portrait
of
the
depth
and richness of
immediate
experience
-
then
draws
an
etymological
line
from
"vague"
to
"extravagance"
and then to
"superfluity."
This tenuous
link
prompts
him
to
assert that
for James,
as for
Emerson,
thinking
involves
punning,
so
that "gains and losses
of
meaning
are in
a
continuous
and
generative
interaction."
Poirier
compares
the
writings
of
Emerson
and James with
those of
Frost, Stein,
Stevens,
and
Eliot,
whom
they
resemble
in
their use
of
metaphor
and their
"allusiveness and
elusiveness
of
phrasing."
Poirier
characterizes
James's
language
as "no
less
'superfluous"'
than
the
language
of modernist
poets,
"subject
to
the same
degree
of
metaphorical
proliferation,
slippage,
and excess."
James's
language
slides
"out
of
bounds,
toward the
margin,
until it
becomes loose
and
vague."
AlthoughJames conceded the
limits
imposed
on
clarity
by
the
ineffable
in
experience
and the
unstable
in
language, as
his classic
The
Varieties
ofReligzous
Experience
makes
abundantly
clear,
in his
writings
he
sought
to
move
beyond
the
vague,
rather
than
to
revel in
it.24
James
sharpened
his
thinking against
the hard
edges
of
the world he
encountered
in
experience,
and
his
own
writing reflected
his
preoccupation
with clarity and
precision.
In
a letter to
his former
student
Gertrude
Stein, written
shortly
before
his
death,
James
explained
why
he
had
not
yet
finished
reading
a novel she
had
sent
him: "As a rule
reading
fiction is
as
hard
for me
as
trying
to
hit a
target
by
hurling
feathers
at it.
I
need
resistance
to
cerebrate!" James's
pragmatism also
reflects his
awareness
of
the resistance
to
vagueness offered
by
the
world
beyond
his
own fertile
imagination.
In
the
absence
of
any
"resistance"
in
"external
reality,"
writing
can
become
an
exercise
in
creativity-
or
an excuse
for
unrestrained self-
indulgence.
James also
insisted
on
respecting
the conventional
meanings
of
words
lest
we
become
"ungeared"
from
our
cultural tradition and
unable
to
communicate
with
each other. When
critics
align
his
pragmatism
with a
"linguistic
skepticism"
that
encourages
creative
(mis)readings by
"strong poets"
-
critic
Harold Bloom's
description
of
critics
who
interpret
texts
unconstrained
by
conventional
understand-
ings
-they
depart
from
James's
vision.
24
Poirier,
Poetry and Pragmatism,
44, 46, 92, 131.
Compare James's own
cautionary words about
language,
which
might
seem
to
confirm
Poirier's
view:
"Good and
evil
reconciled
in
a
laugh! Don't
you
see the
difference,
don't
you
see
the
identity?" James asked.
"By George,
nothing
but
othing!
That
sounds like
nonsense, but
it
is pure onsense!"
James published
these epigrams,
however, to show how
words that struck him as
brilliant
when
he
wrote them-under
the
influence of nitrous
oxide-dissolved
into
meaninglessness
when the
nitrous
oxide
wore
off.
In
such extravagant
language,
James
said,
"reason and silliness
united."
See
William
James, The
Will
to
Believe and Other
Essays
in
Popular Philosophy
(1897; Cambridge,
Mass., 1979), 219-20;
see
also
William
James,
The
Principles of
Psychology (2 vols.,
1890; Cambridge,
Mass., 1981), I, 254-55.
For
an
interpretation
that stresses the
instability of James's writings
but emphasizes
what James hoped to
accomplish
thereby, see William
Joseph Gavin,
William
James and
the
Reinstatement of the
Vague
(Philadelphia, 1992).
25
William
James to Gertrude
Stein, May 25, 1910, William James
Papers
(Houghton Library,
Harvard
University,
Cambridge, Mass.).
On
William
James's
letters to his brother
Henry
that
contrast
the
writing
of
fiction
with
his
own
struggles against
the
"resistance"
of
"facts" and
the
ideas of "other
philosophers,"
see
R.
W. B. Lewis, TheJameses: A
Family
Narrative
(New
York, 1991), 409-10.
Poirier, Poetry and
Pragmatism,
114 The Journal of American
History
June 1996
Two of the most prominent late-twentieth-century
pragmatists, RichardJ. Bern-
stein and Hilary Putnam, have challenged versions
of pragmatism, including Rorty's
and Poirier's, that emphasize language and
dismiss the concept of experience.
Their work, less known outside philosophy
than Rorty's, is of particular interest
to
historians.
For
three decades, since the appearance
of his first book,John Dewey
(1966), Bernstein has worked to forge links
between recent continental European
philosophy and the American tradition of pragmatism.
In Praxis andAction (1971),
he traced the
pragmatist philosophy of activity
to its roots in Aristotle's philosophy
and
contrasted the promise of that orientation
with the danger that analytic
philosophy might sink into scholasticism
under the weight of "its own demand
for
ever-increasing technical mastery."
Dewey, by contrast, was alert to "the moral
and
social
consequences"
of
his
ideas, which
demanded a community of inquiry
devoted to the "shared values of
openness
and fairness."
From
the beginning,
Bernstein's
pragmatism
was
grounded
in
a
Deweyan conception
of
experience
and
its consequences for social organization:
"it is only by mutual criticism that we
can
advance our knowledge and reconstruction
of human experience.
"26
The
twin
pillars
of Bernstein's
pragmatism
have been
a
community
of
inquiry
and social action.
In
The
Restructuring
of
Social and Political
Theory (1976),
Bernstein
exposed
the
reductionism of
mainstream
social
science
and
looked for
alternatives
in
hermeneutics, phenomenology,
and
Habermas's
critical
theory.
In
Beyond
Objectivism
and
Relativism (1983),
he identified the "Cartesian
anxiety"
that had dominated and
debilitated
modern Western
thought:
"Either there
is
some
support
for
our
being,
a
fixed
foundation
for our
knowledge,
or we cannot
escape the
forces of darkness that
envelop
us
with
madness,
with intellectual
and
moral chaos."
As an alternative Bernstein
invoked the ideas of
Hans-Georg
Gadamer,
Hannah
Arendt, Habermas,
and
Rorty, arguing
that these thinkers
pointed
toward "the central
themes
of
dialogue, conversation,
undistorted
commu-
nication, [and]
communal
judgment"
that become
possible
"when
individuals
confront each
other as
equals
and
participants."
Bernstein
advanced
a characteristi-
cally Deweyan
conclusion
on
the
consequences
of these ideas: we must
aim
"toward
the
goal
of
cultivating
the
types
of
dialogical
communities" in which
practical
judgment
and
practical
discourse "become
concretely
embodied
in
our
everyday
practices,"
whether those
practices
involve
organizing
a
neighborhood
to build a
playground or organizing
a
group
of students
to
investigate
a historical
controversy
and test alternative
interpretations against
the available
evidence.
Pragmatism,
166-67.
For an alternative
view, see
David
Bromwich,
"Recent Work
in Literary Criticism," Social Research,
53
(Autumn
1986), 447.
Too often,
Bromwich
writes
(with
Fredric Jameson and Terry
Eagleton
in mind), critics
who indulge
their own impulses
as readers
obliterate
the
past,
minimizing "the differentness
of the
past,"
a
consciousness
of which
"performs
a critical
function." Historical
materials
"are not altogether
tractable:
they
will
not do everything
we
want them to."
When
recounting
changes
in
literary
criticism, Poirier
underscores
Bromwich's
point by
shifting
from the "linguistic
skepticism"
he
endorses
in
theory
to
a
commonsense reliance on shared
meanings
of words.
See Poirier,
Poetry and
Pragmatism,
171-93.
26
RichardJ. Bernstein,
John
Dewey (New
York, 1966);
RichardJ.
Bernstein,
Praxis andAction:
Contemporary
Philosophies
of Human
Activity
(Philadelphia,
1971), 319,
314.
Pragmatism:
An
Old Name
for
Some
New Ways
of
Thinking?
115
for
Bernstein,
originates
in
reflection on
experience
and
culminates
in
altered
expe-
rience.27
Putnam
established
himself by
contributing to
debates in
mathematical
logic
and
philosophy of
mind, but
like
Rorty he
has
become
increasingly
disenchanted
during the last two
decades
with much of
what passes for
professional
philosophy
in
the
United
States.
Without
denying the
importance
of logic,
formal
studies,
or
semantics,
Putnam has
nevertheless
described
such
work as
"peripheral"
and
a
reflection of the
"scientistic
character of
logical
positivism"
that
likewise
infects
much
analytic
philosophy.
"Contemporary
analytic
metaphysics,"
he
writes
acidly,
"has no
connection with
anything but
the
'intuitions' of a
handful
of
philosophers."
He is
equally
scornful of
the nihilism he
sees
in
Derrida's
deconstruction.
"Analytic
philosophers
basically
see
philosophy as a
science,
only
less
developed,
vaguer
and
newer, while
Derrida
basically
sees
philosophy
as
literature,
as
art.
I
don't think
either is
correct."
Putnam
interprets
Rorty's
occasional
expressions of
enthusiasm
for
Derrida as the
lingering effects of
Rorty's
disappointment with the
failure of
analytic
philosophy
to
deliver
the
certainty
it
promised.28
In
Realism
with a
Human
Face
(1990),
Putnam
sought
to
clarify his
differences
from
Rorty by
listing
five
principles
that
he-along with
the
early
pragmatists-
endorses,
but that
he
expected
Rorty
to reject.
First,
our
standards of
warranted
assertibility
are
historical;
second,
they
reflect
our
interests and
values;
and
third,
they
are
always
subject
to
reform,
as
are all our
standards.
Rorty accepted
those
but
challenged
Putnam's two
other
principles:
first,
that
"in
ordinary
circumstances,
there
is
usually
a
fact of the
matter as to
whether the
statements
people
make
are
warranted or
not";
and
second,
"whether a
statement is
warranted
or
not is
independent
of
whether the
majority
of one's
cultural
peers
would
say
it
is
warranted
or
unwarranted." From
Rorty's
perspective,
warrant
is
a
sociological
question,
so
we should evade
pointless
debates about relativism
by
moving
"everything
over
from
epistemology and
metaphysics to cultural
politics,
from claims
to
knowledge
and
appeals
to
self-evidence to
suggestions about what we should
try."
This
way
of
framing
the
issue illustrates
Rorty's
characteristic
style
of
argument,
which he
candidly
describes as
trying
to
make his
opponent
look
bad. When
Rorty
traces
this
disagreement
to Putnam's
purported
"appeals
to
self-evidence,"
he
does
just
that: Putnam's
formulation,
however,
does not
depend
on
self-evidence
any
more
than James's
or
Dewey's
ideas of
experience
depended
on
"introspection";
it de-
pends
instead on evidence
derived from
experience.29
Their
second
principal
difference,
Rorty points
out,
stems from
Putnam's "dislike
of,
and
my
enthusiasm
for,
a
picture
of
human
beings
as
just
complicated
animals."
27
Bernstein,
Restructuring of
Social and
Political Theory;
Richard J.
Bernstein,
Beyond
Objectivism
and
Relativism:
Science,
Hermeneutics,
and Praxis
(Philadelphia,
1983), 18,
223.
28
Putnam, Reason,
Truth, and
History, 126;
Hilary
Putnam,
Renewing
Philosophy
(Cambridge, Mass.,
1992), 197;
interview with
Putnam
in
Giovanna
Borradori,
The American
Philosopher,
trans.
Rosanna Crocitto
(Chicago,
1994), 60-61, 66.
29
Hilary
Putnam, Realism with a
Human Face
(Cambridge,
Mass.,
1990), 21;
Richard Rorty,
"Putnam and
the Relativist
Menace," Journal
of
Philosophy, 90
(Sept.
1993), 449, 457.
116
The Journal of American History
June 1996
Putnam has argued that
"one of our fundamental
self-conceptualizations" as
humans
"is
that
we are
thinkers,
and
that as thinkers
we are committed to there
being
some kind
of
truth."
In
Putnam's words, "that
means that there is no
eliminating
the normative," and Rorty is correct to emphasize
the gulf dividing
him
from Putnam on
this
issue. Putnam concedes the
historicist point that our
ways
of
using language
change, but
he
insists that even
so,
"some of
our sentences
are
true,
and-in
spite
of
Rorty's objections
to
saying
that
things
'make'
sentences
true -the
truth
of 'I
had cereal
for
breakfast
this
morning' does depend
on
what
happened
this
morning."30
This conclusion,
which many historians will find congenial,
depends finally on
Putnam'sJamesian conception
of what it is to be human
and his conviction, which
he has
reiterated
again
and again during
the last fifteen
years, that
we
should
characterize the mind as "neither
a
material nor an
immaterial organ but a system
of
capacities,"
which returns us to the
early pragmatists'
theory
of
voluntary
action.
In
two essays written with
Ruth Anna Putnam, Putnam
stresses the "continuing
interactive nature of experience"
as Dewey conceived
of it. Thinking involves
relating
our choices
and
our
actions to
their
consequences,
which
requires reflecting
not merely on
our
words
but
on the
experienced
effects of
our
practical activity.
"We
formulate ends-in-view
on the
basis
of
experience,"
they conclude,
"and
we
appraise
these
on the
basis
of
additional
experience."
For a
pragmatist,
to
be
engaged
in
that
practice
is
"to
be
committed
to the existence
of
truth.
Democracy
is a social condition of such
practice, and therein
lies its justification."31
For Putnam, as
for Bernstein, all inquiry presupposes
values
such as mutual
understanding
and
cooperation,
which
in
turn
require
free
and
open exchanges
of ideas
among equals
who
are
committed
to the value
of the
practice.
All of
these
are
deeply, irreducibly
normative
notions,
and
they require
a
conception
of human
thinking
and
agency
different
from
Rorty's
view. At
the conclusion of
Reason,
Truth,
and
History (1981),
Putnam stated this crucial
argument clearly
and force-
fully:
"The notion
of
truth
itself
depends
for
its
content
on our
standards
of
rational
acceptability,
and
these
in
turn
rest on
and
presuppose
our
values."32
Rorty's dualisms
cannot accommodate
the
early
pragmatists' conception
of
artistic
or
religious experience.
Rorty
shares
Dewey's
conception
of
the
liberating
social value
of
art,
which
engages
the
imagination by
destabilizing
the established
order
and
suggesting
imagined
alternatives.
But
for
Dewey,
as
forJames,
aesthetic
30
Rorty, "Putnam
and the Relativist
Menace," 458;
Hilary Putnam, "Why Reason
Can't Be Naturalized,"
in Hilary Putnam,
Philosophical Papers,
vol. III: Realism
and Reason (New
York, 1983), 229-47. See
also
Richard Rorty, "Putnam
on Truth," Philosophy
and Phenomenological
Research, 52
(June 1992), 415-18;
and
Hilary Putnam,
"Truth, Activation
Vectors, and Possessive
Conditions
for Concepts," ibid., 431-47.
Hilary
Putnam,
"The
Question
of
Realism,"
in
Hilary Putnam,
Words
and Life,
ed.
James
Conant (Cambridge,
Mass.,
1994), 299-302.
31
Putnam,
"Question of Realism,"
305, 292n6. On the
early pragmatists' theory
of
voluntary action
and its
relation to
their conception
of
truth,
see James
T.
Kloppenberg,
Uncertain
Victory:
Social Democracy and
Progressivism in
European and American
Thought, 1870-1920
(New York, 1986),
79-94. Hilary Putnam
and
Ruth Anna Putnam,
"Education
for Democracy,"
in
Putnam,
Words
and Life,
ed. Conant, 227; and
Hilary
Putnam and
Ruth
Anna Putnam,
"Dewey's Logic: Epistemology
as
Hypothesis,"
ibid.,
218.
32
Putnam, Reason,
Truth, and History,
215.
For
a
recent restatement of this
argument, see Putnam,
"Pragmatism and
Moral Objectivity,"
in
Putnam, Words
and Life, ed. Conant,
151-81.
Pragmatism: An Old
Name for Some
New Ways of
Thinking?
117
and
religious
experiences
of
the sort
Dewey
characterized as
"consummatory"
derive
their
explosive
power from qualities
that can
render them
finally inexpressible
in
language.
Rorty admits the
importance of
such fulfilling
experiences-for
him
they
come
from
art, literature,
or
the wild
orchids that have
fascinated him
since
his
childhood
-
but he denies
that such
private enjoyments
have anything
to
do with
philosophy.33 James
and Dewey
disagreed, and the
disagreement
has
important
implications.
Dewey's
aesthetics differed
from the
abstract and formal
theories of
analytic
philosophers
and New Critics.
He
emphasized
aesthetic
experience rather than
the
objects
of art. He
deplored
the
compartmentalization
that
cuts art off from
the rest of
existence,
and
he
denied
the
authority
of
elites to define
and control
what
passes
for art. As
Richard Shusterman
argues
in
Pragmatist
Aesthetics
(1992),
Dewey opposed
the
idea that all artistic
experience requires
interpretation
by
trained
professionals.
Such
linguistic
universalism,
which
Shusterman
accurately
describes
as "the
deepest dogma
of the
linguistic
turn
in
both
analytic
and continen-
tal
philosophy,"
he
judges
"neither
self-evident nor immune to
challenge."
Resur-
recting
the ideas
of
James
and
Dewey,
Shusterman insists that
pragmatism
"more
radically
recognizes uninterpreted
reality,
experience, and
understandings
as
al-
ready
perspectival, prejudiced,
and corrigible
-
in
short, as
non-foundationally
given."
He
recommends hermeneutics
for
use
only
in
particular
circumstances.
Shusterman
insists that
understanding
does not
always "require
linguistic
articula-
tion;
a
proper
reaction,
a shudder or a
tingle,
may
be
enough
to
indicate that
one has understood.
Some
of
the
things
we
experience
and understand"
-notably
aesthetic
and
somatic
experiences
-
"are
never
captured
in
language."34
Rorty,
locked
inside the tight
boundaries of
textualism,
appreciates such nondis-
cursive
experience
but denies
it
any philosophical
significance.
Dewey, by
contrast,
wrote that "a
universe
of
experience
is
a
precondition
of a universe of discourse.
Without
its
controlling
presence,
there is no
way
to
determine the
relevancy,
weight,
or coherence of
any
designated
distinction
or
relation. The universe
of
experience
surrounds and
regulates
the universe of
discourse
but
never
appears
as
such within
the
latter.
"
35
Linguistic
pragmatists
such
as
Rorty
and
other
contempo-
rary
thinkers who
privilege
language
and distrust
experience
not
only disagree
with
Dewey
but also
thereby
dismiss
much of what
historians value
in
their efforts
to understand the
past
as
it
was
lived.
In
James's introduction to
the
lectures
eventually published
as The
Varieties
of
Religious
Experience,
he
urged
his listeners to think
about
especially rich,
powerful,
`
See
Richard
Rorty, "Trotsky
and
the
Wild
Orchids,"
Common
Knowledge,
1
(Winter 1992),
140-53.
34 Richard
Shusterman, Pragmatist Aesthetics: Living Beauty,
Rethinking Art (Oxford, Eng., 1992),
22, 32,
62, 76, 120-34. See
also David R. Hiley, James F. Bohman,
and Richard Shusterman, eds., The
Interpretive
Turn:
Philosophy,
Science, Culture (Ithaca, 1991). On the difference
between nineteenth-
and
twentieth-century
hermeneutics, and the
reasons why historians should recover the
former, see Michael Ermarth, "The Transformation
of
Hermeneutics:
19th-Century Ancients and 20th-Century
Moderns," Monist,
64
(April 1981), 176-94.
John
Dewey,
Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938),
in
Dewey,
Later
Works, ed. Boydston, XII,
74. See
also
the
thoughtful
discussion
in
Richard Shusterman, "Dewey on
Experience: Foundation
or
Reconstruction?,"
Philosophical Forum,
26 (Winter 1994), 127-48.
118
The Journal of
American History
June 1996
and
sometimes
unforgettable experiences that he
described as "entirely
unparalleled
by anything
in verbal
thought."
Giles
Gunn,
in his
fine
book
Thinking
across
the
Amertcan Grain (1992), quotes at length
a passage that expresses
"much of
the
heritage of
pragmatism that Rorty has
found problematic." The
meaning of
such
intense
experiences,
in
James's words,
"seems to well up from out
of their
very centre,
in
a
way impossible verbally to
describe." On
reflection
,James
observed,
our
experience
of
every
moment of life
seems to
expand
in
the
way a
revolving
disk
painted
with a
spiral pattern appears at once to
grow continuously
from
within
itself and
yet
to remain the
same size.
Such "self-sustaining
in
the
midst
of
self-removal, which
characterizes all
reality and fact, is something
absolutely
foreign
to the
nature of
language, and even
to the nature of logic,
commonly
so-called,"
which
explainsJames's
aversion to the
emerging philosophical obsessions
with
language
and mathematical
logic
and his
stubborn
fascination
with
reli-
gious experience.
Something
forever
exceeds, escapes
from
statement,
withdraws from
definition,
must
be
glimpsed
and
felt,
not
told. No
one
knows this
like
your genuine
professor of
philosophy. For what glimmers
and twinkles like a bird's wing
in
the sunshine it is his
business
to
snatch and
fix.
And
every
time
he
fires his
volley
of
new
vocables
out
of his
philosophic
shot-gun,
whatever surface-flush
of success he
may feel,
he
secretly
kens
at the
same
time the finer hollowness
and irrelevance.
Whereas
philosophers
who have made the
linguistic
turn
might
scoff at
James's
insistence on
the inadequacies of language to
capture and pin down
the
magic
of
experience,
historians have
good
reasons to
pay
attention.36
Indeed,
for
historians the greater temptation
may be
to treat
experience
uncriti-
cally,
as a court
of
last
appeal, slighting
the role of
language
and communication.
Despite
the
incapacity
of
language to
encompass fully
the realms of
religious,
aesthetic,
emotional,
and
somatic
experience,
we nevertheless
usually
have access
to
the
experience
of other
persons,
and communicate
our
own
experience
to
others,
principally through language.
Although
lived
experience may
exceed
the
boundaries
of
discourse,
our
expression
of it
usually,
and
our
discussion
of it
always,
cannot.
Moreover, extralinguistic experiences
have most often
been
used
to authorize the
dogmatic
assertions of
foundational
principles
that
pragmatists
old and new distrust.
Traditionally
appearing
as
religious
truths
proclaimed
by
believers,
more
recently
such
foundational
principles
have
been
asserted
by
those
who claim that their
race, class, gender,
or
other
characteristic
gives
them immediate
experience
and
thus
insights inaccessible,
perhaps
even
incomprehensible,
to those
outside the
charmed-or
maligned-circle.37
How do
we assess
and
adjudicate
such
competing
claims, grounded
in
appeals
to
experience?
The
early pragmatists'
36
Giles
Gunn, Thinking across
the
American Grain: Ideology, Intellect,
and the
New Pragmatism
(Chicago,
1992), 112-13. For James's draft of the
opening of his Gifford lectures in Edinburgh, the basis for
The Varieties
of Religious Experience,
see
Perry, Thought
and Character
of William James, II, 328-29.
31
For an incisive discussion from an
implicitly pragmatist perspective, see David A. Hollinger,
Postethnic
America: Beyond Multiculturalism (New
York, 1995).
Pragmatism: An Old
Name for Some New Ways of Thinking?
119
concept
of truth is crucial not
only because it acknowledges those
appeals but
because,
in its ethical and
political
dimensions,
it offers a
method
for
evaluating
such claims.
It thus
provides
a
way
of
attempting to negotiate differences
that
might otherwise seem irreconcilable.
That pragmatic method is democracy.
Ethics and Politics
For both James and Dewey democracy
was much more than a form
of government
or a
set
of
legal arrangements.
Dewey urged us to stop "thinking
of democracy
as
something
institutional and external" and to see it as
"a
way
of
personal life,"
to realize that
"democracy
is a moral ideal and so far as it becomes
a fact is a
moral
fact."
In
James's
words,
"democracy
is a
kind
of
religion,"
and
for
pragmatic
reasons
"we are
bound
not to admit its failure." Such "faiths and utopias
are the
noblest exercise
of human
reason,"
and we must
not
surrender them
to cynicism.38
James and Dewey considered
their
pragmatism inseparable
from their commit-
ment to
democracy
as
an
ethical ideal.
Both
believed
that
their
challenge to
inherited philosophical
dualisms
and absolutes,
their
conception
of
truth
as fluid
and
culturally created,
and
their
belief
that all
experience
is
meaningful
were
consistent
only
with
democracy,
specifically
with the
principles
of
social
equality
and
individual autonomy.
The ideals of
equality
and
autonomy appealed
to
James
and
Dewey because
of
their
open-endedness
and
flexibility. They
did not entail
particular conceptions
of the
good
life for all
people
at all
times,
although they
did
rule
out
fixed and
hierarchical social
systems
sustained
by appeals
to
allegedly
universal
truths that all
members
of the
society
must
embrace.
For appeals to universal
truths, James and Dewey substituted a process
of
inquiry
that was
both democratic
and scientific.
Dewey's
enthusiasm for science is often
misinterpreted
as a narrow concern with
technique
to
the
exclusion of ethical
considerations;
to the
contrary,
Dewey
valued
the scientific method
because
it
embodied
an
ethical commitment
to
open-ended inquiry
wherein
human
values
shaped
the selection of
questions,
the formulation of
hypotheses,
and
the
evaluation
of
results.
Dewey
conceived
of the
ideal
scientific
community
as
a
democratically
organized, truth-seeking group
of
independent
thinkers who tested
their results
against pragmatic standards,
but
those standards
always reflected
moral,
rather
than
narrowly technical,
considerations.
This
unifying
thread
connects
all
of
Dewey's writings.
In
The
Study of
Ethics
(1894),
he insisted that
knowing
cannot be
separated
from
valuing.
The
qualitative
and
social dimensions of
experience
make
pure "objectivity"
or
"neutrality" impossi-
ble
for human
beings.
In
The Public
and
Its Problems he cautioned that "the
glorification
of
'pure'
science"
is
but
"a
rationalization
of
an
escape"
because
knowledge
"is
wholly
a
moral matter."
In
Experience
and
Nature
he stressed the
moral and aesthetic dimension
of
experience,
its
qualitative
as well
as
cognitive
38John
Dewey, "Creative Democracy-The Task before Us," in Dewey, Later Works, ed. Boydston, XIV,
228; William James, The Social Value of the College Bred, in William James, Writings, 1902-1910, ed. Bruce
Kuklick (New York, 1987), 1245.
Pragmatism:
An Old Name
for Some New
Ways of
Thinking?
121
understanding
and
desire,
with
that
world
to
which
one-sided
philosophy
confines
'nature."
39
Dewey
judged the notion
of
"value-free" inquiry
abhorrent as
well
as incoherent.
An
address
Dewey wrote for a
banquet
celebrating
his
eightieth birthday in
1939 states
clearly and
concisely the connection
between
his
devotion
to
democracy
and
his
philosophical
conceptions
of
experience
and ethics.
Democracy,
Dewey
proclaimed,
is "a
way
of life"
that requires "faith
in
the
capacity of
human
beings
for
intelligent
judgment
and action if
proper [that
is,
democratic] conditions
are
furnished." To those who
judged this faith naive or
utopian,
Dewey insisted
that
it derives
neither from
metaphysics nor from wishful
thinking but from
the
everyday
experience
of
neighbors
and friends
gathering
"to
converse
freely
with
one
another.
Intolerance, abuse,
calling
of
names
because
of differences of
opinion about
religion
or
politics
or
business,
as well
as because
of differences of
race,
color,
wealth
or
degree
of
culture are treason to the democratic
way
of life."
Anything
that
blocks
communication
engenders
"antagonistic
sects and factions"
and
undermines
democ-
racy. Legal
guarantees
-
the focus of
late-twentieth-century
efforts
to assure the
right to
free
expression
-are
inadequate
when "the
give
and take
of
ideas,
facts,
experiences,
is
choked
by
mutual
suspicion, by
abuse, by
fear
and hatred."
For
Dewey
democracy required
more than
securing
individual
rights.
It
required
faith
in
the
possibility
of
resolving disputes
through
uncoerced
deliberation,
"as
cooperative
undertakings,"
instead of
having
one
party suppress
the
other
overtly
through
violence
or
more
subtly
through
ridicule or
intimidation.
If
such
cooperation
is
impossible,
then
deliberative
democracy
as
Dewey
conceived
of
it is
impossible.40
The
emphasis
on difference
in
the
contemporary
United States does
not discredit
Dewey's
pragmatism,
as
some writers unfamiliar with
his
ideas
assume; instead
it echoes
Dewey's
own
view
of
diversity. Achieving
the
cooperation
necessary
for
social
life
requires
"giving
differences
a chance to show
themselves,"
he
insisted.
"The
expression
of
difference
is
not
only
a
right
of the other
persons
but
is
a
means
of
enriching
one's own
life-experience."
Dewey's conception
of
democracy
involved
enriching
the
range
of
choices,
and
expanding
the
possibilities
of
finding
different kinds of
fulfillment,
for all
persons.
Democracy
does not
impose
authority
from
above
but relies instead on
"the
process
of
experience
as end
and as
means,"
as
the source of
authority
and the
means of
choosing
among
and
testing
alternative
directions.
This
process
is
continuous because
its
terminus
cannot
be
designated,
or even
imagined,
in
advance of democratic social
experimentation
to
create "a
freer and more humane
experience
in
which all share and to which
all
contribute."
Dewey
harbored
no secret desire to
bring
all
diversity
to an end
under
the
shelter
of a
snug
but
stifling
consensus: to the
contrary,
a
democracy
without
difference
was a contradiction
in
terms,
because
he
believed
passionately
that
all
individuals,
39
John
Dewey, The Study of
Ethics:
A
Syllabus,
in
John Dewey,
The
Early Works, 1882-1898, ed. Jo Ann
Boydston (5 vols., Carbondale, 1967-1972), IV,
339; Dewey,
Public andIts
Problems, 344-45; Dewey,
Experience
and Nature, 74-76; and John Dewey,
Art
as
Experience,
in
Dewey,
Later
Works, ed. Boydston, X, 156.
40
Dewey, "Creative Democracy-The
Task before
Us," 224-30, esp.
226-28.
122
The Journal of
American History
June 1996
in
their
uniqueness, make
different contributions
to
democratic life.
The richer
the mix,
the richer the
culture that results from
the
interaction.4'
Dewey's
commitment
to
pluralism
and diversity, to
the
recognition
and cultiva-
tion of
difference,
and
to the
potential
of communication
to engender
cooperation
and
clarify,
if not
resolve, disputes
illustrates
how
wrongheaded
is
the familiar
charge,
which
Dewey
explicitly
and
repeatedly
denied,
that
his
emphasis
on
a
community
of
inquiry
reveals
the latent
elitism of
pragmatism.
Throughout
the
1920s, against
behaviorists
and empirical
social scientists
who invoked
his pragma-
tism on behalf
of their efforts at social engineering,
he insisted on
expanding
the
"community
of cooperative
effort and truth."
In
Individualism Old and New
(1929) he
elaborated the
argument advanced
in
The
Public and
Its Problems
concerning
the
folly
of
relying
on
elites.
He admitted that
some
communities
of
scientists,
"small
groups
having
a somewhat
technical
ability,"
did
indeed illustrate
how the process
of inquiry
might work,
yet he insisted
that such
groups reveal
only
"a
possibility
in the
present
-
one of
many possibilities
that
are
a
challenge
to
expansion,
and
not a
ground
for retreat
and contraction" from
democracy.
Unfortunately, interpreters
of
Dewey's
ideas sometimes
ignore
such
explicit argu-
ments and
assert that
there must be something
antidemocratic about
communities
of
inquiry,
even those
that
are
open,
expanding,
and
democratically
constituted.42
Although
it has
long
been
common to contrastJames's
individualism to
Dewey's
commitment
to social
action,
their differences
are
subtler.
They
reflect
in
part
the
simple
fact of James's
death
in
1910
and
Dewey's
growing
involvement
in
the
distinctive
political
controversies
of the
following
four
decades,
rather than
any
fundamental
inconsistency
in
their
political
orientations.
Both
conceived of lived
experience as
irreducibly
social
and
meaning-laden;
both
frequently
invoked de-
mocracy
as the social ideal
consistent
with their pragmatism.
James attributed the
"unhealthiness"
of
labor
relations,
for
example,
to "the fact that one-half of our
fellow-countrymen
remain
entirely
blind
to the internal
significance
of the lives
of the
other
half." Instead of
entering imaginatively
into their
ways
of
life-
to
say
nothing
of
entering
into
constructive,
democratic
dialogue
with
them-
"everybody
remains
outside of
everybody
else's
sight."
In
addition to
endorsing
deliberative,
or
discursive, democracy-
defined
by
the creative
potential
of
egalitar-
ian
dialogue,
not
merely
democratic
institutions
or
universal
rights
to
participate
in
political
activity
-James also
championed
what
would now
be
designated
multi-
culturalism.
His
ideal
of
a
democratic
culture, grounded
on
his
conception
of
41
Ibid.,
228-30. On this dimension
of
Dewey's
pragmatism, see also
Hilary Putnam,
"A Reconsideration
of Deweyan Democracy,"
in
Pragmatism
in
Law and
Society, ed. Michael
Brint
and William
Weaver (Boulder,
1991), 217-43.
On the importance
of pluralism to pragmatism,
see
also
Putnam, Words and
Life, ed. Conant,
194-95.
42
John
Dewey, Individualism
Old and
New,
in
Dewey,
Later
Works,
ed.
Boydston, V,
115. The assumption
that knowledge
inevitably
masks
and imposes power
often underlies
such charges of elitism. From
a Deweyan
perspective one
might concede the
point and ask what
alternative is preferable
to stipulating
that democratic
principles
should shape
the
process
of inquiry and
the formation of those
communities that
evaluate knowledge
claims. Particularly
for
scholars,
the refusal to
admit
that there
are
better and worse-more and less democratic-
ways to generate
knowledge
is
self-defeating.
See
the
judicious
review
essay:
Thomas
Bender,
"Social Science,
Objectivity,
and
Pragmatism,"
Annals
of
Scholarship,
9 (Winter-Spring
1992), 183-97.
Pragmatism:
An Old Name for Some
New Ways of Thinking?
123
immediate experience
and his commitment to
pragmatism, "commands
us to
tolerate, respect, and
indulge"
those
"harmlessly
interested and happy
in their
own ways, however unintelligible
these may be
to us." His creed was "Hands
off:
neither the whole of truth
nor the whole of good
is revealed to any single observer."
The
political consequence
of James's pragmatism
was "the well-known democratic
respect for the sacredness
of individuality," the
"tolerance of whatever
is not
itself
intolerant."43
The
early pragmatists'
arguments for democracy
helped inspire generations
of
social and
political
activists ranging
from
Progressive
reformers through New
Dealers
to members
of the
civil rights
movement
and
the New Left.
In
the
debates
that
rage among
contemporary
thinkers
concerning
the
political consequences
of
pragmatism,
the
democratic
convictions of James
and Dewey have slipped
out of
focus
because
the
political
ideas of linguistic pragmatists
such
as Rorty have attracted
so
much attention. Because Rorty's version of liberalism
appeals to many
Americans
disillusioned
with
politics
or
cynical
about
its
prospects,
it is
important
to
be
clear
about
the similarities
and the
differences
between
his
ideas and those of the
early
pragmatists. Rorty
has
repeatedly
characterized
the culture
and institutions
of
liberal democracy
as a
precious
achievement
and
endorsed the
social-democratic
program
that has
been
at the
heart of
pragmatic
political
activism since the
days
ofJames and
Dewey,
or
Rauschenbusch
and
Croly. But,
unlikeJames
and
Dewey,
he
denies that
pragmatism
provides any philosophical
foundation for such a
poli-
tics
-
or that we
need
one.
Rorty nevertheless
characterizes pragmatism
as "a philosophy
of
solidarity
rather
than
despair."
He tries to reassure
his
readers
that we need
not
discard
our
beliefs
about
the
natural
world,
or our moral and
political
values, just
because
we realize
we
have made
them,
rather
than found them. Our faith
in
science,
like
our other
faiths, helps
us
get
things done,
and
it
will
continue to
help
us even after
we
have
stopped trying
to
"divinize"
it -likewise our
democratic
faith.
In
the
absence
of
foundations, Rorty
recommends that we
look instead
to
history-but
from
an
idiosyncratic,
even
antihistorical
vantage point.
We
must
accept
"our
inheritance
from,
and
our
conversation
with,
our fellow-humans
as our
only
source
of
guid-
ance."
This is our
defense
against
the
nihilism
that those
who
believe
in
universal
principles
fear will follow
from
pragmatism.
"Our identification
with our commu-
13
William
James,
Talks to Teachers
on
Psychology;
And to Students
on Some of Life's Ideals
(1899; New
York,
1958),
188-89,
169, 19-20.
On James's
tragic sensibility
and Dewey's indomitable democratic
faith,
see
Kloppenberg,
Uncertain Victory,
115-95,
340-415. OnJames's politics,
cf. the contrasting emphases
of
Deborah
J. Coon,
"'One
Moment in the
World's
Salvation': Anarchism and
the Radicalization
of William
James,
"Journal
ofAmerican
History,
83 (June 1996),
70-99;
and George
Cotkin, William
James: Public
Philosopher
(Baltimore,
1990).
On Dewey's
democratic
ideas,
cf.
Westbrook,
John
Dewey and
American Democracy;
and Alan
Ryan,
John
Dewey
and the
High
Tide
of
American Liberalism
(New
York,
1995).
For the
long-standard
view of
the
differences
between James's
and Dewey's outlooks,
see
James
Campbell,
The
Community Reconstructs:
The
Meaning
of Pragmatic
Social Thought
(Urbana,
1992). For
criticism of
Dewey, George
Herbert
Mead, andJames
Tufts for
trying to
moderate class
conflict and
to translate their
Protestantism
and republicanism
into a reformism
supposedly
ill
suited to the industrial era,
see Andrew
Feffer,
The Chicago
Pragmatists
andAmerican
Progressivism
(Ithaca,
1993).
An imaginative
analysis
that credits
Dewey and especially
James
with realizing
that corporate
capitalism
ushered
in
possibilities
for
a
"postmodern
subjectivity"
is
James
Livingston,
Pragmatism
and
the
Political
Economy of
Cultural Revolution,
1850-1940 (Chapel
Hill,
1994).
124
The Journal
of American History
June
1996
nity-our society,
our political tradition,
our intellectual
heritage-is heightened
when we see this
community
as ours rather than
nature's, shaped rather
than
found,
one
among
many which
men have made."
If we were to surrender
our
aspirations
to certainty,
he writes, we "would
regard
the justification of
liberal
society simply
as a matter of historical
comparison with
other attempts
at social
organization." At
first
glance historians
might
find Rorty's argument
intriguing:
He
urges
us to "try not to
want
something
which stands beyond history
and
institutions" because
"a
belief
can
still regulate
action" even
if
we realize it
is
"caused by nothing
deeper than contingent
historical
circumstances." In
Rorty's
"liberal utopia,"
the claim that there
is "'something
that stands beyond
history'
has become unintelligible."44
Rorty urges
us
to discard
attempts
to
provide philosophical
props
to
hold
up
our humanitarian and
democratic
values,
to face
unblinkingly
the
contingency of
our
sense
of self
and
our commitments, and
to
adopt
a
posture
of ironic distance
from
whatever
we now accept as
our
"final vocabulary."
The hero of Rorty's
"liberal
utopia"
can
"slough
off
the
Enlightenment
vocabulary"
of rational foundations
underlying universal
principles and
strive simply to avoid
inflicting pain
on others,
a
taboo Rorty
simply posits
as
self-evident
to
anyone
who has inherited
our
tradition.
Having given
up
his own
adolescent
attempts
to "hold
reality
and
justice
in
a
single vision,"
Rorty
has
become
convinced
that
"an
intricately-textured
collage
of
private
narcissism
and
public pragmatism"
may be
our
best
hope
for
synthesizing
love and
justice.
We
can no
longer
aim
for more than what
Alan
Ryan
calls
"welfare-capitalism-with-a-human
face," Rorty
has written.
Terms such as
"capital-
ist
economy" and
"bourgeois
culture" have
become
meaningless
since
1989;
in
the
absence
of
any contrasting
socialist alternatives,
"we
Western
leftists" should
"banalize
our
vocabulary
of
political
deliberation."
Taking
that advice to
heart,
Rorty
claims
that
our
political
needs boil
down
to
"security"
and
"sympathy"
or,
as
he
put it,
"mere niceness" to
all "featherless
bipeds."
Such
formulations,
evidently
calculated to infuriate Rorty's
earnest
critics,
no
doubt
account
for
much of
his
no-
toriety.45
Rorty contends
that philosophy
can
no
longer
offer
much
guidance
to those
interested
in
ethics and
politics.
For
him
liberal
democratic
cultures
are
simply
"a product
of time
and
chance,"
"an accidental
coincidence,
"
or "a fortunate
happenstance,"
and
the historical
emergence
of the
United States
was "an
admirable
result"
that occurred
"just by good
luck."
Rorty's
devil-may-care
view of
history
as
caprice
and
his
intentionally
banal
ethic
of
"niceness" contrast
strikingly
with
James's stance
in
such
essays
as "The Moral
Philosopher
and
the
Moral Life"
and
Dewey's
historical
analyses
of the
connections
between
theories
of
ethics and
Richard Rorty, "Solidarity
or Objectivity,"
in
Post-Analytic
Philosophy, ed.
Rajchman
and
West,
15-16;
Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism,
166; Richard Rorty,
Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity
(New York, 1989),
xvi, 53, 189-90.
`
Rorty, Contingency,
Irony, and Solidarity, 53;
Rorty, "Trotsky and the Wild
Orchids," 140-53; Rorty,
Philosophical Papers, I, 210;
Richard Rorty,
"The
Intellectuals
at the End of Socialism,"
Yale
Review,
80
(April
1992), 1-16; Richard Rorty,
"Human Rights, Rationality,
and Sentimentality," ibid.,
81
(Oct. 1993),
1-20.
Pragmatism:
An Old Name for Some New
Ways of Thinking?
125
political organization, between
personal responsibility
and social justice.
Rorty
claims that
Dewey's pragmatism
"did
not
tell you
what
purposes
to
have;
its ethics
is situational at best."46
That could be said generally
of James as well. But
as
Robert Westbrook and
I argue, Dewey challenged prevailing
systems of
ethics
and
conventional liberal and
socialist political theories,
but he neither endorsed
the
judgment
of
many
analytic philosophers that ethics
and political philosophy
are
obsolete
nor
accepted
anything like Rorty's advice
that urging sympathy
is the
best
we can do.
James
and Dewey both
believed that demolishing
earlier arguments about
ethics and politics cleared
the way for critical analysis
of personal freedom and
responsibility, rather than
bringing such discourse to
an end. As Dewey put it
in
1940,
in
a statement that
indicates the gulf separating
him from Rorty, "any
theory
of
activity
in
social
and moral matters, liberal
or otherwise,
which
is
not
grounded
in
a
comprehensive
philosophy, seems to
me to be only a projection
of
arbitrary personal preferences.
"
When Rorty writes
that "we do not need philoso-
phy
for
social criticism"
or contends that "Dewey,
like Nietzsche, altered
our
conception of reason
.
. .
in
a way that leaves no room
for the idea that democratic
ideals can be supported
by invoking ahistorical 'demands
of reason,"' he neglects
Dewey's
own
"comprehensive
philosophy."
More accurate
is
Rorty's observation
of the difference
between
his
hypothetical Dewey and
the historical Dewey,
who
cared passionately about
demonstrating the connection
between experience and
the ethical
and
political
ideal of democracy. Historicizing
reason, a project
many
of James's
and
Dewey's
late-twentieth-century admirers
share with
them,
need
not culminate
in
Rorty's
rigid divisions of language
from experience and of
the
private
from the
public
sphere, nor
in
his dismissal
of ethics and politics
as
proper
subjects
for
philosophers,
nor, as
I
will argue
in
my conclusion,
in his
disregard
for
the
careful
and critical study of how and why
our tradition
has taken its
distinctive
shape. Rorty's
position
is
insufficiently pragmatic.
Although
he considers
himself a
partisan of
social democratic reforms and
criticizes academic cultural
politics,
his
liberal
ironism
encourages selfishness,
cynicism, and resignation
by
undercutting
efforts to confront the hard facts of
poverty
and
greed.4
Varieties of
Contemporary
Pragmatism
Numerous
contemporary
thinkers
have invoked
pragmatism
to
bolster
a
wide
range
of
political arguments;
their
contributions
to
debates
about race, gender,
and law
46
Rorty, Contingency, Irony,
and Solidarity, 22, 37, 68; Rorty, "Dewey between Hegel and Darwin," 65, 64.
47
John Dewey, "Nature in
Experience,"
in
Dewey, Later Works, ed. Boydston, XIV, 150; Borradori,
American
Philosopher, trans. Crocitto, 117;
Rorty, "Dewey between Hegel and Darwin," 68. On the contrast
between
Rorty's ideas about history, religion,
ethics, and politics and those of other pragmatists,
seejames
T. Kloppenberg,
"Democracy and Disenchantment:
From Weber and Dewey to Habermas and Rorty,"
in
Modernist Impulses in
the
Human Sciences, ed. Ross,
69-90; and James T. Kloppenberg, "Knowledge and
Belief
in American
Public
Life," in Knowledge and Belief:
Enlightenment Traditions and
Modern
Religious Thought, ed. William M.
Shea and
Peter
A.
Huff
(New York,
1995), 27-51. On the connection between Dewey's
ideas about ethics
and
his commitment to democracy, see
Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy. See also Richard Rorty,
"Intellectuals in Politics," Dissent,
38 (Fall 1991), 483-90.
126
The
Journal of
American
History
June
1996
make clear
how many
distinct
versions of
pragmatism
are alive
and which
versions
differ
markedly
from
the
ideas
of
the
early
pragmatists. Cornel West has
constructed
a
loose
narrative
tradition
connecting
James
and
Dewey
with
Emerson,
Du
Bois,
and
such
thinkers as
C. Wright
Mills,
Sidney Hook,
and
Reinhold
Niebuhr. In
addition to
accurately
associating
antifoundationalism
and
democratic
sensibility
with
American
pragmatists, West
characterizes them
as
champions of those whom
the
theorist of
anticolonialism
Frantz
Fanon calls
"the
wretched of the earth."
West
distances his
position from
Rorty's
pragmatism,
which he
judges
too
narrowly
focused on
language
and
insufficiently
attuned to
the pressing
need for
political
activism.
"The
distinctive
appeal of
American
pragmatism
in
our
postmodern
moment,"
West writes,
"is its
unashamedly
moral
emphasis
and its
unequivocally
ameliorative
impulse."
Although
lack of
precision
and inattention
to detail
make
West's
The American
Evasion
ofPhilosophy
problematic
as a
history
of
philosophy,
it
is a
spirited and
provocative
piece of
pragmatic
cultural
criticism.48
An
ardent
admirer of
Dewey,
West
nevertheless
argues that
Dewey's
pragmatism
must be
supplemented
with the
tragic and
religious
sensibilities
of Niebuhr
("the
vertical
dimension"),
the
awareness of
class of Karl
Marx and
Antonio
Gramsci,
and
a
sharper
sensitivity to issues
of race
and gender
(the
"horizontal
dimension")
than
the
early
pragmatists
showed.49 In
recent years,
as he has
attained
celebrity
status of
a
sort neither
James nor
Dewey
had to
endure, West
has become less an
academic
philosopher
than
a "jazz
freedom
fighter" whose
"prophetic
pragmatism"
attempts to
translate
a
philosophical
perspective
descended
fromJames
and
Dewey,
a
religious awareness of evil
and
finitude,
and a radical democratic
politics
into
the
idioms of
postmodern
academic
discourse, black
spirituality,
and
hip-hop.
Rorty
has
complained
that
West's phrase
"prophetic
pragmatism"
sounds
as odd
as
the
phrase
"charismatic trash
pick up."50
West's
cheerleading seems
pointless
to
Rorty
since he
believes
we
cannot bridge
the gap
between the
rich
possibilities
available to us
in
private life
and Dewey's
imagined
"great
community,"
a now-
meaningless
utopia we
cannot
envision on
the
flattened
landscape
of welfare
capitalism.
Between the
negative
freedoms
individuals
enjoy
in
a liberal
democracy
and the
promise
of an
even richer form
of
life
within a
more
radically
democratic
public
sphere-the
"positive
freedom"
that Dewey
embraced
in
Liberalism and
48
Cornel
West,
The
American
Evasion of Philosophy: A
Genealogy of Pragmatism
(Madison, 1989),
4.
49
Cornel
West, "Politics of
American Neo-Pragmatism,"
in Post-Analytic Philosophy,
ed. Rajchman and
West,
259-72. On West's account
of American pragmatism and
his "prophetic pragmatism,"
see Kloppenberg,
"Knowledge and Belief in
American Public Life." Fine studies of
philosophy, religion, and
ethics from pragmatist
perspectives are Henry Samuel
Levinson, The Religious
Investigations of William James
(Chapel Hill, 1981);
and
Steven C. Rockefeller, John
Dewey: Religious Faith and
Democratic Humanism (New
York, 1991). For a
"modest pragmatism" that does
not rely explicitly on Dewey
but echoes many of his
ideas, see Jeffrey Stout,
Ethics
after Babel: The Languages
of Morals and Their
Discontents (Boston,
1988).
s0
Cornel
West, Race Matters
(1993;
New
York, 1994),
150-51.
For
Henry
Louis
Gates
Jr.'s description
of
West as "the
preeminent African-American
intellectual of our
time,"
see Jack
E.
White,
"Philosopher
with
a
Mission," Time, June 7, 1993, pp.
60-62; for another generous
assessment of West, see
Robert Boynton, "The
New
Intellectuals," Atlantic
Monthly, 275 (March 1995), 53-70.
Compare the pyrotechnic
display of
ressentiment
by
Leon
Wieseltier,
"All
and
Nothing
at
All," New Republic,
March
6, 1995, pp. 31-36.
For
responses from
readers (including Rorty), see
"Decline of Cornel West," ibid.,
April 3, 1995, pp. 6-7.
Richard Rorty, review
of
The
American Evasion of
Philosophy by Cornel West,
Transition, 52 (1991), 75-77.
Pragmatism: An Old
Name for Some New Ways of Thinking? 127
Social Action -falls a chasm. To
Rorty, our century illustrates the cruelty that
must result
from attempts to force
community where there is conflict. But to West
(and others drawn toward Dewey's
ideal), it is essential that pragmatists continue
striving for the democratic
transformation of everyday experience.
Like
West, many feminists
endorse pragmatism
as
an alternative to the sterility
of
analytic philosophy and the
nihilism of post-structuralism and as a lever to
dislodge entrenched ways
of
thinking. Against dueling conceptions of fixed
"male"
and "female"
natures, feminist
pragmatists instead call for an open-ended, anti-
essentialist, experimental approach
to gender. In a special issue of the journal
Hypatia published
in
1993,
Charlene Haddock Seigfried, who has written
exten-
sively on William James, has
brought together works by historians, philosophers,
and
political theorists exploring the
potential of pragmatism for feminism."5 Such
early pragmatists as James, Dewey,
and George Herbert Mead considered pragma-
tism
a
weapon
in
the campaign
against restrictive gender roles for the
same
reason
they considered it a weapon in the
campaigns against imperialism and racism
and
for
democracy. They
allied with feminist
activists
and
championed
feminist scholars
such as Jessie Taft
because their
conception
of
pragmatism
extended
beyond
language to an awareness of the
experience of people who were denied choices,
or
unnecessarily restricted
in
their
choices, by prevailing assumptions and patterns
of social
relations.52
The pervasiveness of power that
many contemporary feminists emphasize has
led
some, notably Joan Scott, to
resist the concept of "experience" because they
fear it can lead us
away
from historicism
toward
a new foundationalism.
But
instead
of
dismissing
the
concept
as Rorty does, Scott recommends examining
how
experience
is
said to
yield unassailable
knowledge,
a
strategy resembling
that
of James
and
Dewey."3 Similarly, other feminists resist
the
ideas
of
a
community
of
inquiry
or
a
deliberative
democracy because they fear such ideas valorize
white
"
Charlene Haddock
Seigfried, Chaos
and
Context:
A
Study
in
Williamjames
(Athens, Ohio, 1978);
Charlene
Haddock Seigfried, William James's Radical Reconstruction of Philosophy (Albany, 1990). Seigfried brought
together
a
group
of
essays with
her
introduction, Charlene Haddock Seigfried, "The Missing Perspective:
Feminist
Pragmatism," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 27 (Fall 1991), 405-74. And
see the
special
issue
"Feminism and Pragmatism," ed. Charlene Haddock Seigfried, Hypatia, 8 (Spring 1993).
There are
no specifically
pragmatist or feminist doctrines about philosophical or political issues, according to Richard Rorty, "Feminism,
Ideology, and Deconstruction: A Pragmatist View," ibid., 96-103.
52
The
special issue "Feminism and Pragmatism" contains essays on the importance of experience for early
feminist
pragmatists
and
responses
to
contemporary linguistic pragmatists.
See
especially
Jane
Upin,
"Charlotte
Perkins Gilman: Instrumentalism beyond Dewey," Hypatia, 8 (Spring 1993), 38-63; M. Regina Leffers, "Pragma-
tistsJane Addams andJohn Dewey Inform the Ethic of Care," ibid, 64-77; Gregory Fernando Pappas, "Dewey
and Feminism: The
Affective and Relationships in Dewey's Ethics," ibid.,
78-95;
Timothy
V.
Kaufman-Osborn,
"Teasing Feminist Sense from Experience," ibid., 124-44; Mitchell Aboulafia, "Was George Herbert Mead a
Feminist?," ibid., 145-58; Jane Duran, "The Intersection of Feminism and Pragmatism," ibid., 159-71; and
Lynn Hankinson Nelson,
"A
Question of Evidence," ibid., 172-89. For documents illuminating Jessie Taft's
pragmatist feminism and demonstrating James's commitment to feminism in practice, see "Archive," ibid.,
215-33.
13
For a persuasive case for historicizing the concept of experience and examining critically all appeals to
experience that resembles the perspective
I
call pragmatic hermeneutics, see Joan Scott, "The Evidence of
Experience," Critical Inquiry, 17 (Summer 1991), 773-97. Cf. James T. Kloppenberg, "Objectivity and Histori-
cism: A Century of American Historical Writing," American Historical Review, 94 (Oct. 1989), 1011-30. For
a feminist
perspective
on the
uses
of
the concept of experience,
see
Lorraine Code, "Who Cares?
The
Poverty
of
Objectivism
for
a Moral
Epistemology,"
Annals
of
Scholarship,
9 (Winter-Spring 1992),
1-18.
128
The Journal
of
American History
June
1996
male norms
of
rationality
and
are thus
inevitably
exclusionary.
Recent
work
by
pragmatist
feminists
suggests
both
how
historicizing
experience
enables
us
to move
beyond
language
without
positing
a
new foundationalism
concerning
"women's
ways of
knowing"
or
"rational
deliberation"
and
how
to acknowledge
power
relations
without
positing
a new
essentialism
about
"difference"
and
"power."
Pragmatist
legal
theorists
such as
Joan
Williams
and
Margaret
Jane
Radin
argue
that profound
conflicts,
for example,
those
between
women
who
work
inside
and
outside
the
home
and
between
women
who
support
and who
oppose
abortion
rights,
are
powerfully
shaped
by
deep
but
seldom
recognized
cultural
fissures
concerning
the
meanings
of freedom
and
responsibility
for
men and
women.
Those
divisions
can
be
traced to the nineteenth-century
doctrine
of
separate
spheres,
unfortunately
resurrected
as
an indirect
consequence
of early-twentieth-century
feminist
essen-
tialism. The
ironic
result
was a
reinforcing
of stereotypes
of
home and
mother
that undercut
feminists'
efforts to
loosen
gender
roles and
broaden
women's oppor-
tunities.
Reinscribing
a comparable
essentialism
under
the
banner
of
"difference,"
as
some
contemporary
feminists
do,
merely
resuscitates
older
versions
of separate
spheres
and notions
of privileged
knowledge
that
exclude
new
categories
of outsiders
rather than
opening
doors
of understanding
that
might
lead
to tolerance
or
even,
potentially,
mutual
respect.
From
an
explicitly
pragmatist
perspective,
Williams
challenges
currently
fashionable
notions
of female
as well
as
male
identity
and
the
ostensible
predispositions
of
women
for
"relationships"
and
"caring"
and
of
men for
"justice"
and
"rights."
Radin
argues
that
pragmatist
feminists
should
"reject
static, timeless
conceptions
of
reality"
in
favor
of
"contextuality,
expressed
in
the commitment
of
Dewey
and
James to
facts
and their meaning
in
human
life,
and narrative,
expressed
in
James's
unfolding 'epic'
universe
and
Dewey's
historicism." Echoing
West's
challenge
to
Rorty's
narrowing
of
pragmatism
to
language,
Radin
concludes
in
a Deweyan
spirit:
"If
we
are
pragmatists,
we will
recognize
the
inescapability
of perspective
and
the
indissolubility
of
thought
and
action,"
insights
that
can help
feminists
avoid
rigid
and
counterproductive
dogmas.
54
Other
legal
theorists share Williams's
and
Radin's
enthusiasm for
pragmatism
as
a way
of resolving
the
battles
pitting
those
affiliated
with the
critical
legal
studies
movement
on the left
or with
the law and
economics
movement
on the
right against
those attempting
to keep
alive
notions
of
original
intent as
the
standard
for
interpreting
the Constitution.
From the
perspective
of such
legal
pragmatists,
much
legal
reasoning
-
at both
ends
of
the
political
spectrum
-
is
blinkered
by
abstract
and
absolute
principles
from
seeing
how the law has
func-
tioned
in
practice
in
American
culture."
I'Joan
Williams,
"Gender
Wars:
Selfless
Women
in the
Republic
of Choice,"
New
York
University
Law
Review,
66
(Dec.
1991), 1559-1634.
See
also
Joan
Williams, "Deconstructing
Gender,"
Michigan
Law
Review,
87 (Feb.
1989),
797-845;
and
Joan
Williams,
"Virtue
and
Oppression,"
Nomos:
Yearbook
of the
American
Society
of Political
and
Legal
Philosophy,
ed. John
W. Chapman
and William
A. Galston (New
York,
1992),
309-37.
MargaretJane
Radin,
"The
Pragmatist
and the Feminist,"
in
Pragmatism
in
Law
and
Society,
ed.
Brint
and Weaver,
127-53.
1s
SeeJoan
Williams,
"Critical
Legal
Studies:
The Death
of Transcendence
and
the Rise
of the
New
Langdells,"
New
York
University
Law Review,
62
(June
1987),
429-96.
Pragmatism:
An Old Name
for Some New
Ways of
Thinking?
129
The
rise
of
legal
pragmatism may
seem surprising.
The
goal of
the legal
process
is to find
truth. Juries are
instructed to
decide on the
basis of the
evidence
presented;
the
effects
of decisions
experienced by
defendants
and plaintiffs
are concrete
and
determinate.
The law
might
thus seem
an
especially
inhospitable place
for
a
linguistic
pragmatism
that treats all
disputes as
ultimately
rhetorical
contests.
Instead,
law offers
one of the
liveliest arenas of
debate about
the
consequences
of
pragmatism,
and
one
that should
be
of
particular
interest to
historians.
The
jurist
Richard Posner,
the leading
member
of
the
law and economics
movement,
believes that
pragmatists'
antiessentialism
and
consequentialism
are
compatible
with
his
commitment to
"the idea that the law
should strive to
support
competitive
markets." He
reduces
legal pragmatism
to
the
bare
minimum:
"a rejection
of
a
concept
of
law
as
grounded
in
permanent
principles
and realized
in
logical
manipulation
of those
principles,
and
a determination
to
use law
as
an instrument
for
social
ends." For Posner
pragmatism
is
nothing
but a
method;
substantive
changes
-from
attempts to reinstate white
supremacy
to
commitments to
securing
racial
equality
-result
not
from
careful
reasoning but
only
from "a
sudden
deeply
emotional switch
from
one non-rational cluster
of
beliefs
to another
that
is
no
more (often
less) rational."
Holmes
at
his
most
cynical could
hardly
have
put
the
point
more
bluntly.
Posner's
pragmatism,
like
Rorty's,
thus
appears
to
consist of
nothing more than
antifoundationalism.
56
But the
protean
critic
Stanley Fish,
in his
recent
incarnation as a
legal
theorist,
points
out
that
Posner
embraces
pragmatism
as a
fig
leaf to
conceal
economic
dogmas
concerning
market
efficiency
as
absolute
as Kant's transcendental
aesthetic
or
Marx's
notion
of
the
proletariat.
Fish
contrasts
both
Posner's faith
in
the
market
and
Rorty's
faith
in
strong poets
to his
own
pragmatism,
which
really
does
lead
nowhere. "Once
pragmatism becomes a
program"
-any
program,
Fish
insists-
"it
turns
into the
essentialism it
challenges.""
Fish's
linguistic
turn
carries
him
even further
away
from
Dewey
than does
Rorty's.
From Fish's
perspective,
"the
law's
job"
is "to
give
us
ways
of
re-describing
limited
partisan
programs
so
that
they
can be
presented
as
the
natural outcomes
of
abstract
interpersonal
imperatives."
As
humans we cannot
escape
partisanship
or
perspective; they
are
inevitable conditions
of our
existence.
For
Fish the
pursuit
of
disinterestedness,
James's
aspiration
to
tolerance,
and
Dewey's
desire
for
a
deliberative
democracy
are all
chimerical; only
the
admission
that one's own
point
of
view
remains
partial
is
consistent with
pragmatism.
The
very pretense
of
"reasoned
exposition"
-
in
judges'
opinions
or
scholarship
-
is
just rhetoric,
"impelled by
a
vision as
partisan
and
contestable
as
that
informing
any
rhetoric that dares
accept
that name."58
56
Richard Posner,
"What
Has
Pragmatism
to Offer Law?," in Pragmatism in
Law
and
Society, ed.
Brint
and
Weaver, 42,
44. See also Richard
Posner,
The
Problems
ofJurisprudence
(Cambridge,
Mass., 1990), 150.
1'
Stanley Fish, "Almost
Pragmatism:
The
Jurisprudence of
Richard Posner, Richard
Rorty, and Ronald
Dworkin,"
in
Pragmatism in
Law
and Society,
ed. Brint and
Weaver, 63.
58
Ibid, 71, 56.
At
an interdisciplinary
conference
on
pragmatism
held in
November
1995
at the
City
University
of
New
York,
Fish was
chosen
to
provide
the closing
remarks,
which
allowed
him
to offer
as the
last
word on the subject his
version of pragmatism
-which might fairly be
summarized as
"anything goes." Although
Bernstein, Putnam, and
Westbrook participated in
the conference,
discussion centered on the
ideas of thinkers
such as Rorty and Fish.
That focus reflects current
academic debate;
this essay attempts to demonstrate
the
130
The Journal of
American History
June
1996
But even
Fish slips.
He concedes that
his
antifoundationalism
finally
has a
foundation,
the concept
of "difference,"
which,
he
asserts,
"is
not
a
remediable
state;
it
is
the bottom
line
fact of the
human
condition,
the condition of
being
a finite
creature."
Although
the
challenge
to the law's
generality
seems
jarring,
Fish's proclamation
of difference
resonates
with the pleas of
many voices claiming
to speak
for the
marginalized
in
American discourse
today.
ForJames and
Dewey,
appreciating
the
inevitability
of
perspective
made
pragmatism
necessary;
it was
not
-
as
it
is
for
Fish
-
the last word. From
the
realization
of difference came the
necessity of
democracy. This
more robust
conception of the
relation between
pragmatism
and legal theory
is reflected
in
the
writings of those
legal theorists,
such as Cass Sunstein,
who consider the democratic
commitments of James and
Dewey integral
to the
pragmatist
project.59
After surveying
the competing
versions of
pragmatism and
postmodernism
in
legal theory,
Sunstein
recently concluded
that
"the
valuable
postmodern claims
tend to
be
not
postmodern
at
all,
but
instead
part
of
the
philosophical
heritage
of
pragmatism,"
which unsettled formalism without wallowing
in
the nihilist
resignation
that all
effort
is
futile
in
the
face of
power.
Pragmatism
insists that
all
our
categories,
legal
and
otherwise,
are
constructed.
This awareness
marks
"the
beginning
of
the effort to construct
our
categories
well, by
reference to our
goals
and
needs,
and
not
as a
reason
to abandon
the
whole
enterprise."
For Sunstein-
as
for
Dewey
and
for the
legal
realists
who earlier
in
the twentieth
century
embraced
pragmatism
as
the
philosophy
informing
their
jurisprudence
-
deliberative democ-
racy provides
the standard
for
judging
the
adequacy
of our
ways
of
determining
those
goals
and
needs.60
This
crucial argument
indicates
why
democracy
is
uniquely
consistent
with
pragmatism.
As
Putnam has
accurately pointed
out, Dewey
offered an "epistemo-
logicaljustification
of
democracy.
"
Dewey
used
epistemology
to
ground
democracy,
conceived as the
testing
of
hypotheses by
free
individuals
participating
in
the
unfettered
pursuit
of truth.
In
our
day
such a
conception
of
democracy
must remain
open-ended
because we,
unlike seventeenth- and eighteenth-century
champions
of
democracy,
cannot
claim
to know
what
our final
ends will
be. Since
we
cannot
answer
in
advance
the
questions
"what are
we?" and "how should we live?"-
questions
earlier democrats
thought they
could
answer
through
reason or
revela-
differences
between
linguistic
pragmatism
and
the
ideas
of earlier
pragmatists
and to show what has been
lost
in the transformation.
59
Ibid., 72. For versions
of pragmatist legal theory
more
Deweyan
than
Rortyan (or Fishy),
see
especially:
Thomas C. Grey, "What
Good Is Legal Pragmatism?,"
in Pragmatism in Law and Society,
ed. Brint and Weaver,
9-27; Cornel West, "The
Limits of Neopragmatism,"
ibid., 121-26; Radin, "Pragmatist
and the Feminist,"
ibid., 127-53; Joan C.
Williams, "Rorty, Radicalism,
Romanticism: The Politics
of the Gaze," ibid.,
155-80;
Jean Bethke Elshtain,
"Civic Identity and the State,"
ibid., 181-96; Martha
Minow and Elizabeth
V.
Spelman,
"In Context," ibid., 247-73;
Catharine Wells, "Situated
Decisionmaking," ibid., 275-93;
and especially Putnam,
"Reconsideration of
Deweyan Democracy," ibid.,
217-43.
60
Cass Sunstein,
The
Partial Constitution (Cambridge,
Mass., 1993), 127. For
criticism
of Sunstein's
program
as
reinstating
the
power
of educated white male elites,
see Robin West,
"The
Constitution
of Reasons," Michigan
Law Review, 92 (May 1994),
1409-37. Cf. James T. Kloppenberg,
"Deliberative Democracy
andJudicial Suprem-
acy," Law and History Review,
13 (Fall 1995), 393-411.
On
the relation between pragmatism
and
legal realism,
see Morton
J. Horwitz,
The Transformation of American
Law, 1870-1960:
The Crisis of Legal Orthodoxy (New
York, 1992); and James
T. Kloppenberg, "The Theory
and Practice
of
Legal
History," Harvard Law Review,
106 (April 1993), 1332-51.
Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking? 131
tion- we must commit ourselves to continuing inquiry. Thus a pragmatist episte-
mology and ethics
in
the spirit of James and Dewey culminates necessarily
in
a
democratic politics.
In
Putnam's words, which echo many similar proclamations
in
Dewey's work, "democracy
is not
just
a form of social life
among
other
workable
forms
of social life; it
is
the precondition for the
full
application of intelligence
to the solution of social
problems."
It
is
the
form
of social life consistent with
prag-
matism."6
Pragmatism and Democracy
This
view of the relation between
pragmatism and democracy,
which intellectual
historians have been
urging
now for a
decade, helps explain
the
resurgence
of
interest
in
pragmatism. Now that alternative ideals appear either discredited or
impossible, democracy has emerged as a universally attractive norm. But in our
multicultural
and skeptical age,
the case for
democracy
can no
longer be established
on the
basis
of
self-evident
truths
about
natural
rights
or
arguments
from
religious
doctrine
that no
longer
command
general
assent. Is there a
philosophical
foundation
on which
democracy
can rest at the
end
of the twentieth
century? According
to
linguistic pragmatists such as Rorty and Fish and postmodernist theorists
such
as
Foucault and Derrida, whose work has influenced much recent American critical
theory,
there is none. But the
great strength
of
pragmatism
as James
and Dewey
conceived
of
it,
which historians more
fully
than
analytic philosophers
and
law-
seeking
social scientists
have recognized and demonstrated, lay
in
its
denial
of
absolutes,
its
admission
of
uncertainty,
and
its resolute commitment to the continu-
ing vitality of the ideal of democracy as a way of life.
Indeed, pragmatism appeals
to
many
American thinkers as a
homegrown
alterna-
tive to
postmodernism
that
escapes
the weaknesses of
Enlightenment
rationalism
without
surrendering
our commitments to the values of
autonomy
and
equality.
Textualists such as
Rorty and
Fish
consider pragmatism
consistent with the
perspec-
tive on
language
most often associated with Derrida. Others
see it
instead
as a
way
of
thinking open
to
the critical
insights
of
postmodernism
but
resistant to
cynicism
and
nihilism
because
of its
conception
of
experience
and
its commitment
to
democracy.62
In
The New Constellation (1992),
his most recent
work,
Bernstein faces the
postmodernist challenge
head
on. Foucault
and Derrida
deny,
in
radically
different
ways,
the
possibility
of
reaching
the democratic
understandings
that
Dewey
envi-
sioned.
Bernstein
successfully
undertakes
the
apparently unpromising
task of
find-
ing
in
their
writings
ethical
and
political
ideas
consistent with his own
pragmatism.63
Bernstein shares
postmodernists'
commitments to
antifoundationalism, fallibilism,
61
Putnam, "Reconsideration of
Deweyan Democracy," 217. On the link between this "modern view of truth"
and democracy, see also Putnam and
Putnam, "Dewey's Logic," 198,
215-17;
and Hilary Putnam
in
Borradori,
American Philosopher, trans.
Crocitto, 61-62.
62 I
am
grateful
to Richard
Fox,
Robert
Westbrook,
and Joan Williams for conversations that
helped
sharpen
my understanding of the issues
discussed
in
this paragraph.
63
Richard J. Bernstein, The New
Constellation: The Ethical-Political Horizons of
Modernity/Postmodernity
(Cambridge, Mass.,
1992).
132
The
Journal of
American
History
June
1996
Richard
J.
Bernstein
c.
1992.
Since
the
1960s,
Bernstein has
elaborated
the
connections between the
ideas of
European
thinkers,
from
Aristotle
to
Jurgen
Habermas,
and his
Deweyan
pragmatism,
which
emphasizes practical
political activity.
Courtesy
Richardje
Bernstein.
contingency,
and
pluralism,
but he
emphasizes
the
grounding
of
pragmatism
in
the
phenomenology
of
experience.
Because
experience
itself is
social,
Bernstein
believes, our
private
selves cannot
be cordoned
off from
our ethical
responsibilities
-
even behind the shield of
"difference."
We
must
always
be
prepared
to
expose
our
private
passions
and our
personal
choices to
criticism and to
engage
in
dialogue
those
who
disagree
with
us,
not because we
believe that
consensus will
necessarily
result,
but
because
it is
only
through
that
process
that
we
learn to understand
one
another and ourselves.
Bernstein's
Deweyan
pragmatism
pays
attention to
history,
particularly
the
history
of
American
democracy.
Whereas
Rorty
asserts
confidently
that
Americans
who inherit "our tradition" share his
own commitments to
preserving
individual
privacy and
refusing
to
inflict
pain,
Bernstein insists
that
the
"breakdown of
moral
Pragmatism:
An Old Name
for Some New
Ways of Thinking? 133
and political
consensus" is "the
overwhelming 'fact' of contemporary
life."
Rorty
blithely explains
the emergence
of American
liberal democracy
as
a
product
of
chance and contingency;
his account
ignores or trivializes
the efforts of
historical
actors. Behind
the values and
institutions that Rorty
and many postmodernists
take
for
granted
lie
not only the
now-disputed doctrine
of natural rights
and the
notion of God's
covenant with a chosen
people but also
the experiences of
countless
Americans who have struggled to
nudge reality closer
to the elusive ideal
of de-
mocracy.
64
Another
important
reason for
American scholars'
renewed interest
in
pragmatism
has been the
widespread influence ofJUrgen
Habermas,
arguably the
most impor-
tant philosopher
of
the late
twentieth century, who
now describes
himself simply
"as
a
good pragmatist."
Habermas's
affinity
with
American pragmatism
will
surprise
some historians who know
him
only by reputation
or are acquainted
with
only
parts
of his
massive
work.
In
his
attempt to
free
Marxism
from Marx's scientism
and
his
fetishizing
of the proletariat,
Habermas has
constructed a theory
of commu-
nicative action
centered on what
he calls the ideal speech
situation.
His philosophy
depends
on
ideas
of the self constituted
through
social interaction and
of
undis-
torted
communication as
the paradigm
for social
democracy
that can be traced
directly
to
Mead
and
Dewey.
Although
it
startles
longtime partisans
of American
pragmatism,
interest in these ideas
among many younger
scholars derives
largely
from the writings
of Habermas.65
Habermas too
has distanced
his understanding of
pragmatism
from Rorty's.
In
response to Rorty's
jibe that he tends
to "go transcendental,"
Habermas
traces his
conception
of
dialogue
to "the
already operative potential
for
rationality
contained
in
the everyday
practices
of communication,"
which
depend
on our confidence
in
the validity
of
propositions,
the
rightness
of
norms,
and
the truthfulness
or
authenticity
of those with whom
we
communicate.
In
ordinary experience,
Ha-
bermas
contends,
we
learn
to
recognize
the
(frequently
unrealized) potential
of
dialogue.
Dismissing
as
self-defeating
the
universal skepticism
and
resistance
of
some
postmodernists,
Habermas
opts
instead
for
the
perspective
of
the
early
pragmatists:
"I
have
for
a long time
identified myself
with that radical
democratic
mentality
which
is
present
in
the
best
American
traditions and
articulated
in
American
pragmatism.
This
mentality
takes
seriously what appears
to so-called
radical thinkers
[such as Foucault
and Derrida] as
so much reformist naivete."
He
endorses
Dewey's `'attempt
to make
concrete concerns with
the
daily
problems
of one's
community' [an attempt
that] expresses both
a
practice
and an attitude."66
64
Bernstein,
New Constellation, 326-39;
for Bernstein's
extended discussion
of Rorty, see ibid.,
233-92.
See also RichardJ.
Bernstein, Philosophical
Profiles:
Essays in a
Pragmatic Mode (Cambridge,
Eng.,
1986),
260-72.
61
JUrgen Habermas,
"Questions and Counterquestions,"
in
Habermas and Modernity,
ed. RichardJ.
Bernstein
(Cambridge, Mass.,
1995), 198. On
the strange career of pragmatism
in
Europe,
see
Hans Joas, Pragmatism
and Social Theory,
trans. Jeremy Gaines,
Raymond Meyer,
and Steven Minner (Chicago,
1993). Joas
has also
written the best study
of George Herbert
Mead: Hans Joas,
G. H. Mead: A Contemporary
Re-examination
of
His Thought (Cambridge,
Mass., 1985).
See the significant restatement
of pragmatism
in HansJoas, The Creativity
of Action, trans.
Jeremy Gaines and
Paul Keast (Chicago, forthcoming).
66
Habermas,
"Questions and Counterquestions,"
196-98.
Habermas traces refinements
in
his major
works
to
insights derived
from Mead's symbolic
interactionism. See
the new concluding chapter
written for
the English
edition of Jurgen
Habermas, Moral Consciousness
and Communicative
Action, trans.
Christian Lenhardt
and
Shierry Weber Nicholsen
(1983; Cambridge,
Mass., 1990),
195-202.
134
The Journal
of
American History
June 1996
These
controversies
among
contemporary
pragmatists
replay
in
a
different key
the familiar
contrast
between the
images of
mind
as
mirror and
lamp,
between
the
empiricism
of
the
Enlightenment
and the
romantics'
obsession
with the
creative
potential
of
the
artistic
imagination.
Their
disagreements
have
helped focus
debate
and
enabled
other
thinkers,
such
as
Habermas,
to
clarify their own ideas
by
sharpening
the
distinctions
between
those who
embrace
linguistic
pragmatism
and
those
who see
its
inadequacies.67
Our
heightened
awareness
of
the
opacity and
instability
of
language has
compli-
cated
the
question
of how we
should
deal with
experience, both as
scholars
and
as citizens
trying
to reach
agreement
by
exchanging
views. So
too, our
heightened
awareness of the
historicity
of our
political institutions and our
sensitivity
to the
social and cultural differences
that
complicate
democratic
dialogue
make it
hard
for
us to
see
how
we can
achieve the
early
pragmatists' political
goals.
Dewey
recognized
that
he
failed to
provide
clear,
detailed
political
strategies
for
realizing
his
ideal
of
democratic
life,
and
that
fuzziness
is one of the
most
troublesome
aspects
of his
legacy.
James's
greater
sensitivity
to
the
uniqueness
of each
individual,
to
the difficulties of
communicating
the
ineffable
quality
of
lived
experience,
and
to the
tragic betrayal
of
some ethical
ideal
in
every
choice between
irreconcilable
conceptions
of the
good make
his
variety of
pragmatic
political
thinking
perhaps
better
suited to our own
time. For as
the
experience
of
community
has
become
ever
rarer
in
the
years since Alexis de
Tocqueville
first
announced its
endangered
status,
and
as politics
is
more and more
submerged
beneath
a
flood
of
symbols,
finding
paths
leading
toward the creation
of
democratic communities seems
more
problematical
than
ever.
History
can
help,
if
only
we historians
have the
courage
of
our
conventions.
History
and Pragmatic
Hermeneutics
Because the
community
of
historians
is
a
paradigmatic
example
of a
pragmatic
community
of
inquiry,
distinguishing
between
pragmatism
old
and
new
matters
profoundly to
us.
To "new" textualist
pragmatists,
history
is
no
more than
a
linguistic
exercise in
which professional
competitors
strive to
persuade
readers
by
fashioning arguments
that
are
judged
successful
according
to various
contingent
and
culturally specific
criteria. For
those
"new"
textualists,
historians
are
writers
of
texts
who
have
at
their
disposal
a
variety
of
tools,
including
but
not limited
to
"evidence,
"
"reason," "logic,"
and
"common
sense,"
all of which
require quotation
marks
to
signal
their
status as
merely conventional notions.
Canny
textualists claim
that
all
such
tropes
are rhetorical
devices
deployed (more
or less
shrewdly
and
67
See
Bernstein,
"Resurgence of
Pragmatism"; and
RichardJ.
Bernstein, "American
Pragmatism: The Conflict
of
Narratives," in
Rorty and
Pragmatism, ed.
Saatkamp, 54-67.
Those contemporaries I have
linked together
as
Deweyan critics of
linguistic
pragmatism do not
necessarily share
my perception of
their
similarities. See, for
example, Robert
Westbrook, "A New
Pragmatism,"
American
Quarterly, 45 (Sept.
1993),
438-44;
and
the
spirited
exchange: Giles
Gunn,
"Response to Robert
Westbrook,"
ibid., 46 (June
1994), 297-303;
and Robert
Westbrook, "Response to Giles
Gunn,"
ibid., 304-7.
Pragmatism: An
Old Name for Some New Ways
of Thinking? 135
self-consciously)
in
our discursive
tradition to persuade
others in our community
and to achieve a certain standing
within it. It is indeed
difficult to see how history
written by "new" pragmatists
could contribute anything
distinctively different
from novels or poetry to helping
us to understand experience,
communicate with
each other, or construct a
more democratic culture.68
To
"old" pragmatists and
to historians aligned (consciously
or not) withJames,
Dewey, Putnam,
and
Bernstein, history retains its distinctive
significance
as the
study
of "a
reality independent
of us," to use James's phrase.
We understand, as
Putnam has argued, that
our entire practice as historians-our
"form of life," to
use Ludwig Wittgenstein's
phrase-depends on "our belief
that truth and falsity
'reach all the way to' the
past and 'do not stop short."'
It is possible to admit,
with
Putnam,
that this
belief
"is part of a picture," but
we should acknowledge,
with him, that
as
historians
"the picture is essential to
our lives." In Putnam's
words,
"our lives show
that
we believe
that
there are
more and
less warranted
beliefs about
political
contingencies, [and]
about
historical
interpretations."
Were
we to discard that
way
of
looking
at the
past,
we
would have
to
discard our
form
of
life.69
Narratives
capable
of
inspiring
and
justifying
the
sympathy
Rorty prizes
in
"our
tradition" already exist, and
not
only
those of
the novelists and poets
that
Rorty
invokes. They
include
the
narratives contained
in
sacred texts
such
as the Bible
and
secular democratic texts such
asJudith Sargent
Murray's essay
"On
the
Equality
of
the
Sexes,"
Abraham
Lincoln's Second
Inaugural,
and Martin Luther
King Jr.'s
speech
at the
1963 March
on Washington, narratives
with
powerful
ethical
and
cultural significance transmitted
by various traditions
and by
the
community
of
professional
historians. In a society that
is
ostensibly
committed to the ideals
of
democracy
but
that
falls
tragically
short
in
practice,
the narratives we
historians
construct
help
to
perpetuate
disturbing
and
inspiring
memories and thus to
shape
a
culture
more
capable
of
approximating
those ideals. Without
historians'
com-
mittment to a pragmatic test
of truth,
which
involves
subjecting
our accounts
of
the past
to
rigorous testing
by our scholarly
community,
we
are
locked
into an
exercise
of
textual creation
that
is
arid
and
pointless.
In
That
Noble
Dream (1988),
Peter Novick
concluded
that
because the
ideal
of
pure scholarly objectivity
has been
exposed
as chimerical
(thanks
in
part
to
textualists
such
as
Rorty
and
Fish),
historians have divided
into
warring camps,
unable
and unwilling
to
reach agreement
about standards
of
purpose
and
critical
judgment. Although
Novick
acknowledged
the
attempts
of Bernstein and
Putnam,
68
By their qualifications
and caveats, two recent
endorsements of textualism
illustrate the lure
of a more
Deweyan pragmatism.
On the necessity of giving some
determinate shape to the
past even
if
one abandons
grand
narratives, see Dorothy
Ross, "Grand Narrative in
American Historical Writing:
From Romance to Uncertainty,"
American Historical Review,
100 (June 1995), 675-77.
For an argument that
"strong misreading" -of
the sort
Rorty recommends and
Derrida practices-"is altogether
misplaced as historical
reading and critique" because
"history does not emulate
creative writing and is
constrained by different
norms of inquiry," see Dominick
LaCapra, "History, Language,
and
Reading: Waiting
for
Crillon," ibid., 814,
816.
69
James, Pragmatism,
111-12, 102-3; Putnam,
Words
and
Life,
ed.
Conant,
276-77; Hilary
Putnam, The
Many Faces
of
Realism
(LaSalle, 1987), 70-71.
136
The Journal
of American
History
June 1996
and of
historians such
as Thomas
Haskell and
David Hollinger, to sustain
a viable,
mediating
historical
discourse that
I
have termed
pragmatic
hermeneutics,
he
curtly dismissed
their
effort: "as
of the 1980s,"
he wrote,
"hardly anybody
was
listening."70
As the
spirited debates
over pragmatism
examined
here
illustrate,
interest
in
these ideas
is now broad
and deep.
For historians
especially,
the early
pragmatism
of James
and Dewey
presents a sturdy
alternative
to untenable
forms
of
both
objectivism
and relativism.
The
pragmatic
test
we should
apply to
historical scholarship
is
the
same test
James and Dewey proposed
a century ago:
Is
it consistent
with the
evidence
we
have of
others' lived
experience,
and will it
make a difference
in our
lives? If we
historians
conceive
of our task as
the early pragmatists
did,
we will write
not only
with an awareness
of
our rhetorical
strategies
but also with
a desire to
document
and explain
struggles
over power
in
the
American past
and
in
the culture
that
surrounds
us and
makes our work
possible
and necessary.
Waged
by
activists
inspired
by religious
and political
traditions,
these hard-fought
battles
-
and not
just
the important redescriptions,
to use Rorty's
preferred
term, offered
in
literary
and
critical texts-made
possible
our culture's
painfully
limited progress
toward
greater autonomy
and
equality
for all citizens.
Historical
scholarship
understood
as
pragmatic
hermeneutics
shows that the outcomes
were the
result not
purely
of
chance
and redescription,
as the more cavalier
of
textualists would
have
it,
but
instead
of
specific
struggles
fought by people
who wielded
other
weapons
be-
sides
language.71
All
of
this is not to
deny
the
role
interpretation
has always played,
and
will
continue to
play,
in
historical
writing.
Just as people
in
the
past
selected parts
of
their
experience
to record and preserve
in the
records they
left
us,
we
select
parts
of the
past
to examine and we choose
how to
tell our stories.
But to admit
that
interpretation
is
important
is not
to claim that
everything
is
interpretation.
It
is
crucial that
we
historians
be able
to distinguish
what happened
from what
did
not, and
what was
written from
what was
not, and our
discursive
community
must test its
propositions
in the widest
range
of
public
forums.
Arguments
insisting
on the
importance
of
such
public
verification
by appeals
to
evidence
from
experi-
ence, arguments
forcefully
made
against
textualists
by
Gunn,
Shusterman, West,
Williams, Putnam,
and
Bernstein,
are also made
by
historians whose
pragmatism
derives
from James and
Dewey.
That commitment
explains
why
some
of us have
worked to establish
the
difference
between
pragmatists
old and
new,
between
Poirier's
extravagant
James
and
the historical
James,
between
Rorty's
hypothetical
Dewey
and the historical
Dewey.
Pragmatism
offers
historians
something beyond
70
Peter
Novick, That
Noble Dream:
The
"Objectivity
Question
"andthe
American
Historical Profession
(New
York, 1988),
629. For
readings of American
historians'
practice
that discern
widespread if
implicit commitment
to
something
resembling
pragmatic hermeneutics,
see
Kloppenberg,
"Objectivity
and Historicism";
Thomas Haskell,
"Objectivity
Is
Not Neutrality:
Rhetoric
vs. Practice
in Peter
Novick's That
Noble Dream,"
History
and Theory,
29 (no.
2, 1990), 129-57;
and David
A. Hollinger,
"Postmodernist
Theory
and Wissenschaftliche
Practice,"
American
Historical
Review, 96 (June
1991), 688-92.
71
On the relation
between
religious faith,
social reform,
and pragmatism,
see
Kloppenberg,
"Knowledge
and Belief
in American Public Life."
Pragmatism:
An
Old Name for Some
New Ways
of
Thinking?
137
the denial of absolutes,
a method for providing
reliable, even if provisional,
knowledge that can
make a difference
in
how we
understand our culture and
how
we live.72
Historians face
a
choice, then, between newer
varieties
of
linguistic pragmatism
that see all truth claims
as contingent and older
varieties of pragmatism descended
more
directly
from
james
and
Dewey.
The
latter
begin
with a
nuanced
conception
of experience as the arena
for truth testing and culminate
in ethical and democratic
activity,
the
precise
content of which cannot be
specified
in
advance
or imposed
on
others because diversity
and experimentation are
integral to this form of
pragma-
tism. "There can be
no final truth in ethics any
more than in physics,"
James
wrote, until the last
human being "has had his
experience and said his say."
Or
as Dewey put it, "growth
itself is the only moral
'end."'73
Notwithstanding
those endorsements
of
indeterminacy,
which
contemporaries
alert to the threat of oppression
and exclusion should
find attractive, James's
and
Dewey's pragmatism
did not
lack
substantive
values: the ideals of democracy,
grounded
in
their
experience
as social beings and their
commitment to communities
of
inquiry rigorously
testing all truth claims,
provided the norms that
guided
them. Their pragmatism
thus extended beyond
the boundaries of language
in
two directions:
in
its
fluid and historicized conception
of the social experience
that lies behind linguistic
expression, and
in
its dedication to
the
diverse
forms
of
continuing democratic
practice, including the
negotiation
rather than
the elimi-
nation of difference. The
early pragmatists believed
that eliminating the
obstacles
of
outmoded philosophical
and political
doctrines would
free
Americans
to solve
the
problems they
faced. The tragedies
of
the twentieth
century
have made
us
less sanguine about
that prospect; we
lack
their
confidence that
pragmatism
and
democracy by
themselves will resolve all
our
conflicts.
Thus some
contemporary
thinkers,
like those romantics
disillusioned by
the failures
of
eighteenth-century
democratic
revolutions, emphasize
the
instability
of
meanings,
the
particularity
of
personal identities,
and
the creative
genius
of individual
artists over rational
deliberation.
The
new
linguistic pragmatism
will
no doubt
continue to attract
attention
from
many
disciplines because
it reflects that
disappointment
and
also
challenges
the
persistent
impulses
to formalism
and
scientism still
powerful
in
American thought.
But a revised
version
of
the
pragmatism
of James
and Dewey,
chastened by tragedy
to
distrust simple
democratic
cheerleading,
can
avoid
those
dangers
while
offering
a
method
of
generating
and
testing
ideas
about
what
happened to
Americans
in
the past and
of
deliberating
on what should
happen
72
On
the
inevitability
of selection
and
interpretation
in
historical writing,
see Putnam,
Words
and Life, ed.
Conant,
206-7.
For a recent
endorsement
of pragmatism
as
an alternative
to postmodern
skepticism
about
historical
truth,
which recommends
combining
it with
"practical
realism" because pragmatism
is
otherwise
rudderless
due
to its "deference
to practice
over principle,"
see
Joyce
Appleby,
Lynn Hunt,
and
Margaret
Jacob,
Telling
the
Truth about History
(New
York,
1994), 283-91.
This
familiar
but historically
inaccurate
characterization
of pragmatism
as nothing
more
than antifoundationalism
underestimates
its resources
for
histori-
ans'
practice.
73
William
James,
"The
Moral
Philosopher
and the
Moral
Life,"
in
James,
Will to
Believe,
141; John
Dewey,
Reconstruction
in
Philosophy,
in
Dewey,
Middle
Works,
ed.
Boydston,
XII, 173.
138
The Journal of American
History
June
1996
in the future. For that
reason the early pragmatists' ideas will remain
valuable
for
historians committed to
explaining why
America has taken
the
shape
it has
and for citizens
committed to
solving problems
democratically.
The early pragmatists'
"old ways of thinking"
already incorporated
the most
valuable insights
of the linguistic turn and
the postmodern suspicion
of power.
Those insights did
not blindJames and Dewey,
nor have they blinded
the contem-
poraries
who have
resurrected the
spirit
of their
pragmatism,
to the
world of
experience
that
lies
beneath
and
beyond
language
and to the
ties of mutual
respect that might
bind us together as
humans despite our differences.
Such
clear-sightedness was
among the old ways of thinking
central
tojames's
and Dewey's
pragmatism, and it
remains a necessary although
not sufficient
condition for
advancing
toward the democratic goals
of
equality
and
autonomy.
Without
it we
engage
in
shadow
play,
unable
to
distinguish
experience
from
illusion.