Bentley University Bentley University
Scholars @ Bentley Scholars @ Bentley
Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy
2014
Corporations, the Democratic De7cit, and Voting Corporations, the Democratic De7cit, and Voting
Jeffrey Moriarty
Bentley University
, jmoriarty@bentley.edu
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.bentley.edu/philosophy_facpubs
Part of the Applied Ethics Commons, Business Law, Public Responsibility, and Ethics Commons,
Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Human Resources Management Commons
Recommended Citation Recommended Citation
Moriarty, Jeffrey, 2014. Corporations, the Democratic De7cit, and Voting,
Georgetown Journal of Law &
Public Policy
.
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at Scholars @ Bentley. It
has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholars @
Bentley. For more information, please contact scholars@bentley.edu.
Corporations, the Democratic Deficit, and Voting
WAHEED HUSSAIN AND JEFFREY MORIARTY*
A
BSTRACT
Many corporations are enthusiastic participants in the political arena. The
most common, and most studied, forms of corporate political activity are
lobbying and campaign finance (Hillman, Keim, & Schuler, 2004). Increasingly,
however, corporations are engaging in a new kind of political activity. They are
taking on roles traditionally played by the state, notably, by providing public
goods like education, environmental protection and disease prevention, and
helping to sustain and enforce civil regulations like the UN Global Compact,
the Business Charter for Sustainable Development, and the Voluntary Standards
on Security and Human Rights (Kobrin, 2009; Matten & Crane, 2005; Ruggie,
2004; Scherer & Palazzo, 2011; Vogel, 2010).
Many writers argue that a “democratic deficit” is created when private
actors such as corporations take on state functions (Brenkert, 1992; Matten &
Crane, 2005; Scherer & Palazzo, 2011). The problem, it is said, is that the
course of public life is being shaped by agents who are not accountable to the
public. We evaluate this claim and consider what should be done about it. We
focus in particular on a recent attempt, put forward principally by Palazzo and
Scherer (Palazzo & Scherer, 2006; Scherer, Baumann-Pauly, & Schneider,
2013; Scherer & Palazzo, 2007, 2011; Scherer, Palazzo, & Baumann, 2006), to
address the democratic deficit by “democratizing” corporations. We argue that
their proposal, while promising, has a significant defect. We then propose a
remedy for this defect. In sum, our goal is to call attention to a new kind of
corporate political activity, to highlight its main ethical defect, and to examine
in detail an attempt to address it. More generally, this paper contributes to our
understanding of the evolving role of corporations in society.
I. I
NTRODUCTION ...................................... 430
II. T
HE NEW CPA: AVOIDING AN OLD PROBLEM BUT FACING A
NEW ONE .......................................... 433
III. I
S THERE A DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT? ........................ 435
* Waheed Hussain is Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Toronto. Jeffrey Moriarty is
Associate Professor of Philosophy, Bentley University. © 2014, Waheed Hussain and Jeffrey Moriarty.
This paper is equally the work of both authors. For helpful discussion of it, we thank participants in
the ethics of lobbying symposium, sponsored by the Georgetown Institute for the Study of Markets and
Ethics in November of 2013. For comments, we thank Chris MacDonald and Jason Brennan.
429
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
IV. PALAZZO AND SCHERERS MODEL OF DEMOCRATIC ACCOUNTABILITY . 439
V. A P
ROBLEM WITH THE MODEL ........................... 441
VI. T
HE SOLUTION ...................................... 443
VII. C
ONCLUSION ........................................ 447
R
EFERENCES ............................................ 448
I. I
NTRODUCTION
Let’s begin with what we will call the “standard model” of institutional
responsibilities in a democratic society. Generally speaking, democracy is an
ideal that requires that the members of society govern their common affairs
together. Social institutions in a democratic society must be structured so that,
directly or indirectly, citizens collectively determine how to organize important
aspects of social life and how to address the important challenges they face.
Perhaps the most important institution in this regard is the state. The various
agencies of the state make binding laws, develop regulations, and deploy
various collective assets, all on behalf of the people, carrying out the organiza-
tional plans and social policies that citizens have endorsed.
According to the standard model, business corporations have a subordinate
role to play in social life. The role of the corporation is primarily to pursue
profits within the constraints established by law and ethical principles (Friedman,
2002/1962; Jensen, 2002). It is up to the state and the people more generally to
decide broader questions about how to organize social life and how to address
important social challenges. Among its important functions, the state must
shape the legal and regulatory framework in society so as to ensure that the
pursuit of profits by corporations will advance the public policy objectives
adopted by the people.
In recent years, it has become increasingly apparent that the standard
model of institutional responsibilities has broken down. Corporations no longer
confine themselves to a subordinate role in social life. Instead of merely
pursuing profits within the scope of laws and regulations established by the
state, corporations have taken on public functions that were once the exclusive
domain of the people and the state, functions that include making laws, articulat-
ing regulations, and setting public policies (Matten & Crane, 2005; Vogel,
2010).
Take the case of forests. Forests play a key role in regional and global
ecosystems. As such, they are an essential social resource, and hence an
important part of the common life of a democratic community. So, according to
the standard model, members of a democratic society would collectively deter-
mine social policies regarding how to preserve and responsibly exploit forests,
and these policies would be articulated and implemented by the state. For
430 [Vol. 12:429T
HE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
example, democratic majorities would decide on policies regarding clear-cutting
and reforestation, and these policies would be articulated by the state in laws
and agency regulations. Private corporations would then have to respect these
rules, on pain of state sanction, as they pursue profits.
But in several important ways, the people are no longer in control of forest
policy in society (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007). First, corporations play an impor-
tant role in the legislative and regulatory processes. Through donations and
various forms of lobbying, they shape the laws and regulations that the state
enforces (De Figueiredo, 2002).
1
Second, when the legal and regulatory frame-
work is sparse or nonexistent, the corporation’s own internal policymaking
process essentially determines how forests will be managed. Finally, in many
cases, forestry companies are acting in remote areas where the state itself has a
very weak presence. In these cases, as well, the corporation itself effectively
decides on forestry policy, without any type of involvement by the people.
2
These three cases illustrate the basic idea that in many arenas, the corporation is
no longer a subordinate player, but plays a central role in making laws,
developing regulations, and carrying out social policies.
3
From now on, we will use the term “corporate political activity” (CPA) to
refer to cases in which corporations perform activities that on the standard
model are assigned to citizens or the state. These activities include making laws,
articulating regulations, and deploying assets to carry out important public
policies. It is helpful to distinguish between two kinds of CPA, depending on
how the corporation becomes involved in performing public functions.
The most common kind of CPA comprises lobbying and campaign finance
(Hillman, et al., 2004). In lobbying, corporations attempt to shape society’s
1. There is skepticism about the power of donations alone to influence laws and regulations
(Ansolabehere, De Figueiredo, & Snyder, Jr., 2003). But there is strong evidence that lobbying in-
fluences them (De Figueiredo, 2002). As a result, we find that corporations spend far more on lobbying
than on campaign finance (Milyo, Primo, & Groseclose, 2000).
2. It might be objected that, if the corporation owns the forest, then “the people” have no right to
say what it does with it. This is incorrect. To be sure, people have certain fundamental rights that
democratic legislatures have no authority to abridge. The rights to freedom of thought and expression
are among them. But a corporation’s right to do what it wants with the forests it owns is not. Instead,
the nature and scope of corporations’ (and other parties’) property rights are legitimately circumscribed
by a democratic society. Within broad limits, society as a whole can decide which resources will be
owned by the state (e.g., oil fields, waterways, airwaves) and which will be owned by private citizens
(e.g., farms, ranches, factories), and how the use of those resources will be restricted. In the background
of this discussion is the difficult question of what precisely the scope of democratic authority is
(Christiano, 2010a). We cannot hope fully to resolve this issue here. However, we say more about why
the new CPA creates a democratic deficit in section 3.
3. A recent example of corporate involvement in public policy can be seen in the response to the
collapse of the Rana Plaza garment factory in Bangladesh in April of 2013 that killed 1100 workers.
Many observers said: “something must be done.” But governments did not take the lead; corporations
did. A group of powerful multinational corporations based in the U.S. and Europe agreed that they will
not do business with suppliers whose factories do not meet certain safety requirements (Greenhouse,
2013). One result of this is that building and fire codes for factories in Bangladesh are now effectively
being set by Western multinational corporations, not the people of Bangladesh.
Fn1
Fn2
Fn3
2014] 431CORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
legal and institutional framework by “presenting briefs, testimony, and argu-
ments to legislators and their staffs” in formal meetings, charity events, and
other venues (Stark, 2010, p. 503). In campaign finance, they attempt to do so
by donating money from political action committees (PACs) to legislators’
campaigns or to their political parties, or purchasing advertising in support of
legislators or in support of issues with which those legislators are identified
(Stark, 2010). This is what we will call “old” CPA.
Increasingly, however, corporations are engaging in a new form of political
activity. They are attempting to influence the state’s rules and regulations not
just through, but outside of, formal political processes. Among other activities,
corporations pursue climate change and public health policies (Kobrin, 2009;
Ruggie, 2004), enforce citizenship rights (Crane, Matten, & Moon, 2008;
Matten & Crane, 2005), promote peace (Fort & Schipani, 2004), and partner
with other corporations, non-governmental organizations (NGOs), and other
political actors to create and enforce systems of civil regulation (Ruggie, 2004;
Vogel, 2010). In many cases, corporations take on these roles not at states’
request, but on their own. In doing so, they effectively arrogate to themselves
the traditional functions of the state (Ruggie, 2004). This is what we call “new”
CPA.
It might be wondered why corporations engage in the new CPA. The reason
is probably the same as the reason why they engage in the old CPA, viz., they
think it is in their interest to do so (Hillman, et al., 2004). Through lobbying and
campaign finance, corporations incentivize legislators and regulators to pass (or
not pass) favorable (or unfavorable) laws or write (or not write) favorable (or
unfavorable) regulations. Creating public policy and rule-making, on the other
hand, can be seen as attempts to placate powerful political actors who threaten
corporations with negative publicity or boycotts if they do not take steps to
address social problems (Vogel, 2010).
4
An important difference between the old and new CPAs is how each operates.
The old CPA operates “through” the state. Corporations attempt to affect formal
political processes through lobbying and campaign finance to obtain certain
outcomes (e.g., favorable laws and regulations). But the people who they
attempt to influence are public officials (e.g., legislators, regulators), who are
accountable ultimately to the people in periodic elections. By contrast, the new
CPA unfolds “beside or around the state” (Vogel, 2010, p. 69) or “above and
beyond the state” (Scherer & Palazzo, 2011, p. 903). When they engage in new
4. Corporations are targeted in part because they have deep pockets. But corporations can also be
painted as complicit in creating social problems (e.g., by inserting themselves into the political arena),
or as benefiting from these problems (e.g., by operating in countries with extreme poverty to take
advantage of low labor costs) (Wettstein, 2009). It is unclear that these threats, if carried out,
substantially impact corporations’ financial performance (Vogel, 2010). But corporations do appear to
respond to them. Vogel suspects that the reason they do is that corporate executives “value public
approval and dislike negative media attention” (2010, p. 77). They prefer to be seen as heroes rather
than as villains in the media.
Fn4
432 [Vol. 12:429THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
CPA, corporations perform putatively political functions without direction from,
supervision by, or accountability to, states. Focusing on this difference, in the
next section we identify a familiar problem with the old CPA and show how the
new CPA avoids it. We then identify a new problem with the new CPA.
II. T
HE NEW CPA: AVOIDING AN OLD PROBLEM BUT FACING A NEW ONE
Perhaps the most common complaint against old CPA is that it is corruptive
(Stark, 2010; Sunstein, 1994). Stark says that “[d]emocratic officials are en-
trusted with power by the citizenry on the condition that they make decisions
based on no other consideration than the interest of the public” (Stark, 2010,
pp. 501–502).
5
When public officials receive gifts from private parties, either as
part of campaign finance or in the process of being lobbied, this may cause them
to make decisions not based on the public’s interest, but instead on the interest
of a private party. Of course, even if it is known that a public official has
received gifts from a private party, it is often hard to tell if she is acting in the
private party’s interest. The official may believe that her actions are in the
interest of the public as a whole. But even if officials make decisions “based on
no other consideration than the interest of the public,” their receiving gifts from
private parties may lead people to suspect that they are not acting solely on the
public’s interest. As Sunstein says, even the “specter of quid pro quo exchanges
violates” the norm against corruption (1994, p. 1392).
The accusation of corruption is implied in the familiar refrains that a certain
member of Congress has been “bought and paid for” by a private party such as
the National Rifle Association (NRA) or the Club for Growth, or that another
member of Congress is “in the pocket” of the AARP or the Service Employees
International Union (SEIU). The idea is that the member of Congress who has
been “bought and paid for” by, or who is “in the pocket” of, the special interest
group is not doing what she should be doing, viz., promoting the public good.
The new CPA largely avoids this problem of corruption, since it goes
“around” or “beyond” the state rather than “through” it. This problem exists
because there is someone in the political process, viz., the public official, who
has a duty to act solely in the public’s interest. The problem is that she may act
in the interest of the private party instead. By contrast, none of the major
players in new CPA—viz., representatives of corporations and NGOs—has a
duty to act solely in the public interest.
6
So there is no problem if they do not.
This is not to say, of course, that there is no possibility for any kind of
corruption in the new CPA. Corporate executives have a duty to promote the
5. The public official’s duty to make decisions “based on no other consideration than the interest of
the public” can be met even if she does not in fact make decisions that are in the public interest. She
fulfills her duty if she reasonably believes that her decisions are in the public interest.
6. More precisely, none of the major players in the new CPA has a duty to act solely in the interests
of the public as a whole, as government officials do. They do, of course, have a duty to represent the
interests of a portion of the public, i.e., the members of their particular organization or group (e.g., the
Sierra Club).
Fn5
Fn6
2014] 433CORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
interests of their firms, and they may be tempted by considerations of private
gain not to do so. But this kind of corruption exists in the new as well as in the
old CPA.
7
While the new CPA may be better than the old CPA with respect to corrup-
tion, it has seemed to many writers worse with respect to accountability. The
feature of the new CPA that makes it better with respect to corruption is the
same as the one that makes it worse with respect to accountability; namely, the
new CPA goes around or beyond the state rather than through it. In the old CPA,
the officials that corporations attempt to persuade through lobbying and cam-
paign finance are ultimately accountable to the public in periodic elections. This
is not the case with the new CPA. In this case, the agents performing putatively
political activities (e.g., corporate executives) are not accountable to the public.
For this reason, many writers claim that the new CPA creates a “democratic
deficit” (Scherer, et al., 2013; Scherer & Palazzo, 2011).
Palazzo and Scherer are perhaps the most prominent contemporary propo-
nents of this idea. They say that corporations that shape public policy and
engage in rulemaking “have no democratic mandate for this engagement”
(Scherer & Palazzo, 2011, p. 907). In democratic countries, “political authori-
ties are elected periodically and are subjected to parliamentary control. By
contrast, corporate managers are neither elected by the public, nor are their
political interventions in global public policy sufficiently controlled by demo-
cratic institutions and procedures” (Scherer & Palazzo, 2011, p. 907; see also
Matten & Crane, 2005). Palazzo and Scherer believe that this deficit must be
repaired, and that the best way to do so is by changing how the corporation is
governed. In particular, they say that “[i]f corporations assume responsibility for
state functions and generate global rules, then it becomes obvious that it is
necessary to control corporations just as the democratic state needs to be
controlled by its citizens” (Scherer, et al., 2006, p. 517, emphasis in original;
see also Matten & Crane, 2005). Corporations’ “internal structures and pro-
cesses,” Palazzo and Scherer say, “have to become more democratic” (Scherer,
et al., 2006, p. 517).
Corporations’ increasing engagement in the new CPA has brought in-
creasing concern about its democratic character, with Palazzo and Scherer as
key contemporary writers on this subject. But these ideas are not wholly new.
Brenkert (1992) says that corporate social responsibility, understood as the
7. The feature of the new CPA that helps it to avoid the problem of corruption may also create
skepticism about its public value. Ideally, what comes out of the formal political process are sets of
laws and regulations that advance the common good. This hope is founded, in part, on the fact that the
primary political actors in this process—viz., public officials—have a duty to advance the common
good. But there is no person who has this duty in a new CPA process. So we might have correspond-
ingly less hope that the rules and regulations that come out of it will advance the common good. On the
other hand, in the new CPA, corporations are aiming to benefit the public (if only as a means of
advancing their own long-term welfare), while in the old CPA, they are aiming to benefit themselves or
their industries. Our view of the public value of the old and new CPA may depend on our degree of trust
in the government to provide for the public good.
Fn7
434 [Vol. 12:429THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
attempt by private firms to establish public welfare policy, is problematic. If
private corporations organize collective efforts to promote the public welfare,
he says, they must be made “amenable to greater public control and direction”
(1992, p. 164). Even Friedman (2008/1970) draws a similar conclusion. One
of his arguments against socially responsible acts by corporations is that they
are tantamount to “the imposition of taxes and expenditure of tax proceeds”
(2008/1970, p. 66). Friedman says that, because these are “governmental func-
tions,” it is “intolerable...[that those who perform them] should be selected as
they are now,” that is, by shareholders (2008/1970, p. 67). If corporate manag-
ers engage in socially responsible actions, then they must “be elected through a
political process,” i.e., democratically (2008/1970, p. 67).
In the remainder of this paper we will explore this problem for new CPA. We
begin by asking whether it is true that the new CPA creates a democratic deficit.
We then consider an attempt, put forward by Palazzo and Scherer, to address it
by “democratizing” corporations. We argue that this attempt has a serious
problem, and propose a remedy for it.
III. I
S THERE A DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT?
The democratic deficit might be summed up as follows: in shaping public
policy and making rules, corporations are taking on state functions. But they are
not being governed like states. Put this way, we can see that those who claim
that there is a democratic deficit are making some important assumptions. One
is that states should be governed democratically. Another is that corporations
are not, in general, governed democratically. Both of these assumptions seem
correct.
But other assumptions being made here are more problematic. One is that
shaping public policy and making rules are state functions (Matten & Crane,
2005; Scherer, et al., 2013; Scherer & Palazzo, 2011). That is, the assumption is
that these activities in some sense belong to the state, so that when a corporation
takes them on, it is necessarily performing state functions. A second, related
assumption is that any entity that takes on these functions should be governed
like the state, i.e., democratically. Both of these assumptions seem to us to
require justification. It is difficult, however, to find justifications in the writings
of those who make them. In this section we consider challenges to these
assumptions and show how they can be deflected. The end result will be a better
appreciation of how a democratic deficit is created when corporations engage in
the new CPA.
Against the assumption that shaping public policy and rulemaking are state
functions, it might be claimed that it is entirely up to the citizens of a state to
decide what roles the state will play. States normally perform certain functions,
but this does not prove that they should perform them, much less that they
“own” them. The citizens of some states may decide that they want the state to
prevent the spread of HIV/AIDS through taxpayer-funded public health cam-
paigns (a public policy). The citizens of other states may decide against this.
2014] 435C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
The citizens of some states may decide that they want the state to limit how
much carbon businesses and individuals emit (a set of rules). The citizens of
other states may decide against this. And so on. Almost any activity that we
typically associate with the state, including minting currency and providing
security, could be provided by private agents instead (Hasnas, 2003). On this
objection, then, when a corporation provides health services, or helps to create
and enforce environmental regulations, it is not necessarily performing state
functions. It depends on what the state’s citizens want the state to do.
What do citizens want the state to do? According to the conventional wisdom,
the context for—and part cause of—the rise of the new CPA is a deficit of
another sort: a governance deficit. States around the world are increasingly
thought to provide, relative to citizens’ wants, inadequate responses to public
needs and inadequate regulation of commercial activity (Newell, 2001; Palazzo
& Scherer, 2006; Scherer, et al., 2013; Vogel, 2010). The most commonly cited
reason for this is the economic forces collectively known as globalization,
featuring powerful multinational corporations and mobile capital. On the one
hand, some corporations operate in states with weak or non-existent democratic
institutions (Scherer & Palazzo, 2011). On the other hand, corporations that
operate in states with ostensibly strong democratic institutions are increasingly
able to get their way in politics, by threatening to decamp to other, less
demanding states (Christiano, 2010b; Shamir, 2004). Vogel concludes that
“[e]conomic globalization” has “undermined both the willingness and capacity
of governments to make global firms politically accountable” (2010, p. 73).
8
Corporations’ increasing performance of new CPA activities can be seen as an
effort to fill the governance deficit.
One might claim that the conventional wisdom challenges the assumption
that, when corporations effectively create public policy and make rules, they are
performing state functions. After all, corporations are engaging in these activi-
ties in an environment in which states are not engaging in them. But this would
be a mistake. The conventional wisdom does not suggest that the state’s citizens
have decided to turn over certain functions formerly performed by the state to
private actors, or even that these functions will not be performed by the state.
Rather, it suggests that, given current economic trends, citizens have trouble
expressing their will through the state’s formal political mechanisms. The fact
that states do not have certain public policies or create certain regulations
8. The idea that corporations are “under-regulated,” or are asked to provide too few public goods, is
not uncontestable; indeed, it may appear ludicrous to some. A recent theme of the politics of the
Republican Party in the U.S. is that businesses, especially small businesses, are choked by a sea of legal
red tape. But it is instructive to consider what citizens ask of businesses when they are confident that
their demands will be met. Consider, for example, the Alaska Permanent Fund. Through this fund, the
citizens of Alaska tax oil companies and distribute the revenues to current and future generations of
Alaskans. Corporations elsewhere in the U.S. are not subject to this high a level of taxation. This
suggests that what U.S. citizens really want is to tax corporations highly and share the wealth widely
among themselves. Citizens do not do this elsewhere in the U.S. because they believe that corporations
will be able to avoid complying with their demands.
Fn8
436 [Vol. 12:429THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
cannot be taken as evidence that this is what citizens want. If anything, citizens
seem to want their states to craft more adequate public policies, and create and
enforce more regulation. This, in turn, suggests that corporations, when they
engage in the new CPA, may well be performing state functions, understood as
functions that citizens want their states to perform.
In response, it might be granted that corporations are performing state
functions when they engage in the new CPA, i.e., when they shape public
policy and make rules. But it might be objected that there is nothing wrong
with—and in particular, nothing anti-democratic about—their doing so. This
goes to the second controversial assumption mentioned above: that any entity
that shapes public policy and makes rules should be governed like the state, i.e.,
democratically.
Some might argue that we demand control over state functions when coercion
is involved. And there typically is coercion involved when the state shapes
public policy and creates commercial regulation. States fund their provision of
public initiatives by requiring citizens to pay taxes. States enforce commercial
regulation with the threat of legal action against violators. Because coercion is
involved in these activities, it might be said, there would be a democratic deficit
if we did not have a say over them. But there is no coercion involved, the
objection continues, when corporations effectively shape public policy and
make rules. When corporations provide goods such as security services and
education to workers, they do so out of their own revenue, not out of the taxes
that they require people to pay. Flouting the civil regulation that corporations
help to create and enforce is met with social or market penalties, not legal
penalties (Scherer & Palazzo, 2011; Vogel, 2010). As a result, the objection
concludes, we have no right to a democratic say over the new CPA, and cannot
complain of a democratic deficit when we lack one.
The objection should be resisted. First, it takes too narrow a perspective on
the idea of coercion. The market is a social institution, one whose various rules
are backed by the coercive power of the state. If someone tries to gain access to
corporate resources, for example, without the permission of the corporation’s
officers, the state will use its police powers to prevent her from doing so. The
fact that corporations have resources to devote to addressing public problems is
itself a consequence of the fact that they are the beneficiaries of a complex
system of property, contract, and exchange that is ultimately enforced by the
state (Cohen, 2011; Waldron, 1993). Coercion could not be a standard for when
democratic oversight is required because coercion and the threat of coercion is a
constant background element in economic interaction in our society, even if we
are not always aware of it.
Once we resist the temptation to focus on coercion and bring the institutional
character of the market more clearly into view, we can see a sharper response to
the objection. The essence of democracy is the idea that citizens should be able
to shape their shared social, political, and economic conditions. It is hard to see
how our basic institutions could be justified unless they enabled us to control
2014] 437C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
our society in this way (Hussain, 2012). To the extent that corporations shape
public policy for satisfying certain social needs and make and enforce commer-
cial rules, however, this does not happen. Instead, the state’s social, political,
and economic conditions are being shaped by a small group of corporate
executives. While these executives may engage in the new CPA in response to
pressure brought to bear by politically powerful groups of citizens, they are not
accountable to the citizens as a whole, and need not include them in their
decision-making processes (Brenkert, 1992). Indeed, the corporate executives
who shape the social, political, and economic conditions of a certain state may
not even be citizens of that state (as, e.g., when the executives of Western
multinationals set rules affecting building and fire codes in a developing country
[Greenhouse, 2013]).
9
The problem is not just that, insofar as corporations shape the social, politi-
cal, and economic conditions of a state, citizens do not shape them. It is that
corporations’ shaping of these conditions threatens to degrade or undermine
citizens’ will and ability to shape them. When corporations create public policy
and make rules, citizens’ incentives to do so are weakened. They may reason-
ably conclude that their resources are better spent pursuing their private inter-
ests. But democratic self-governance is a skill—or perhaps better, a set of skills.
It requires the ability to identify and rank values, speak on one’s behalf and
listen to others, plan for the long term, and compromise. Like any set of skills,
these skills will atrophy over time if they are not practiced (Mill 1998/1861).
The new CPA thus threatens to create a democratic deficit that cannot easily be
repaired.
Let us then conclude, with many other writers, that the new CPA creates a
democratic deficit. Now the question is, what should be done about it? We have
presented the democratic deficit in the form of a conditional: to the extent that
corporations take on state functions by providing public goods and making
rules, then they should be governed like states, i.e., democratically. It may
9. Questions might be raised about what constitutes objectionable “shaping” of society’s shared
social, political, and economic conditions. A famous singer, for example, might shape society’s shared
social conditions (for the worse) by popularizing a dance move that degrades women. Our argument
might seem to imply, implausibly, that the singers actions create a democratic deficit. Two points can
be made in reply. First, we assume a threshold of significance. That is, actions create a democratic
deficit only if they shape society’s social, political, and economic conditions to a significant degree.It
will be hard to say in some cases whether this line has been crossed, but results like this are sometimes
unavoidable. An analogy is found in limits on money in politics. It is thought to be anti-democratic for
rich people have too much power in politics. So campaign contributions are capped. In the U.S., for
example, citizens can donate no more than $2600 to a candidate in a federal election. But a precise
answer cannot be given as to why the “too much” threshold is $2600 and not $2500 or $2700. A
corporation’s shaping forestry policy, we think, crosses the significance threshold—given forests’
importance for ecosystems, erosion prevention, and air quality—but a singer’s popularizing a dance
move may not. Second, and more importantly, not all shaping is the same. Citizens in a liberal
democracy are properly understood to have a nearly unfettered freedom to express themselves as they
see fit. As a result, popularizing a degrading dance move would be protected by democratic norms, even
it shaped society’s shared social conditions significantly. We thank David Shoemaker for pressing this
objection.
Fn9
438 [Vol. 12:429THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
appear, then, that there are only two options. Either corporations should be
democratized (in particular, their performance of state functions should be
subject to democratic control), or they should stop performing state functions.
But there is a third option. That is, corporations should continue performing
state functions but society should live with the resulting democratic deficit.
Democracy is important, but it is not the only thing that matters. We might think
that the good that comes out of corporations’ performing state functions is
worth the democratic deficit.
We cannot hope to resolve all of these issues here. But we will take one
important step toward doing so by evaluating the viability of an attempt to
“democratize” corporations offered recently by Palazzo and Scherer (Palazzo &
Scherer, 2006; Scherer, et al., 2013; Scherer & Palazzo, 2007, 2011; Scherer,
et al., 2006). We cannot say whether corporations should be democratized,
should stop performing state functions, or continue to perform state functions
without being democratized, until we understand what it might mean to democ-
ratize a corporation. We choose Palazzo and Scherers model of democratic
accountability for corporations for three reasons: first, it was specifically de-
signed to address the democratic deficit caused by the new CPA; second, it has
received a great deal of attention, especially in the business ethics literature; and
third, despite its flaws, it provides an intriguing way to think about how to
restore democratic control over corporations. While focused on Palazzo and
Scherers model, our analysis of it, as we will show, enables us to draw more
general conclusions about accountability for corporations engaged in the new
CPA.
IV. P
ALAZZO AND SCHERERS MODEL OF DEMOCRATIC ACCOUNTABILITY
Palazzo and Scherers model of democratic accountability for the corporation
is based on the ideal of deliberative democracy. According to this ideal, free,
unforced, and rational deliberation among citizens should be sovereign in
society. Assuming the standard model of institutional responsibilities, this is
accomplished when society’s public officials—its legislators and regulators—
are accountable to the citizens. However, when the state is no longer able to
play a central role in directing the course of public life, whoever steps in
to perform the state’s functions in society must be subject to deliberation.
It follows that private actors who take up various state functions in society
must become subject, in some way, to free, unforced, and rational deliberation
among citizens. Palazzo and Scherer sometimes express this point in terms of
legitimacy. It is illegitimate, they say, for private actors to perform state
functions without being democratically accountable to society (Palazzo &
Scherer, 2006).
Palazzo and Scherer propose to make corporations accountable to society by
embedding them in a form of ongoing dialogue among citizens and their
representatives in a society-wide process of democratic decision-making. They
describe their model as a “complex communicative process of accountability
2014] 439C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
where...limits[oncorporate behavior] are defined and redefined in a continu-
ous process of deliberative discourse” (Palazzo & Scherer, 2006, p. 82).
The discourse at issue consists primarily of the exchanging of reasons by all
parties affected by (proposed) corporate actions and practices. Corporations are
required to present reasons to justify their actions or practices. Those who are
affected by them may present reasons for changing those actions and practices.
All parties must be willing to take these reasons seriously and change their
behavior when the balance of reasons tells in favor of doing so (Palazzo &
Scherer, 2006). Public authorities play a background role in this process,
guaranteeing “the transparency of discourse, the monitoring and enforcement of
corporate compliance, the comparability of information and standards, and the
access of less powerful actors to deliberation” (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007,
pp. 1112–1113).
10
According to Palazzo and Scherer, once the process is up and
running, corporations can legitimately perform various state functions in society
just in case their involvement can be “regarded as the result of [this] process of
public deliberation” (Palazzo & Scherer, 2006, p. 80).
Palazzo and Scherer do not claim that every instance of corporate activity
should be subject to social deliberation. To do so would invite the objection that
corporate democracy of this form is hopelessly inefficient (Hansmann, 1996).
Instead, they say, “the deliberative concept...follows the principled priority
of systematic routine as advocated by Habermas” (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007,
p. 1111, emphasis in original). The default position is that corporations can act
according to their own internal decision-making procedures. But this must stop
when there is “a public discourse on the legitimacy of a given issue” (Scherer &
Palazzo, 2007, p. 1111). At this point, Palazzo and Scherer, corporations must
begin exchanging reasons with the public.
As this implies, for Palazzo and Scherer deliberative oversight does not
require democratizing corporations by giving control of them to their employees
(Scherer & Palazzo, 2007). They advocate a form of democratization that
involves the whole citizen body. The point is to “establish a democratic control
on the public use of corporate power” by subjecting corporate activity to the
“overarching processes of (national and transnational) public will formation”
through which citizens collectively direct the course of public life (Scherer &
Palazzo, 2007, p. 1108).
11
10. Various other features of social life may need alteration to achieve these goals (Cohen, 1989).
For example, to ensure that all citizens can participate in the deliberative process, it may be necessary
to restructure ownership rights in the mass media so that everyone has adequate access to newspapers,
television, the Internet, and other channels of communication. It may be necessary to enact limits on
work hours to ensure that citizens have the time to consume information, think about important public
issues, and participate in public debate. It may further be necessary for citizens to have access to
adequate resources, so that they can engage with them in deliberation as equals rather than as
dependents.
11. Yet another way of democratizing corporations is found in early versions of stakeholder theory,
which require the creation of boards of directors with representatives from each stakeholder group
(Evan & Freeman, 1988). For a critical discussion of this view, see Moriarty (2012).
Fn10
Fn1 1
440 [Vol. 12:429THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
Palazzo and Scherer identify the Forest Stewardship Council (FSC) as an
example of the form of democratization they have in mind (Scherer & Palazzo,
2007, 2011). The FSC is an umbrella organization that brings together NGOs,
government agencies, and corporations to agree on principles of sound forest
management and to certify wood products as complying with these standards.
Democratization in the case of the FSC is not pointed inward, making the
involved corporations more accountable to their employees or other stake-
holders. It is rather pointed outward, integrating them into more encompassing
processes of democratic deliberation among a wide range of actors in society
trying to make decisions about issues of public concern. As Palazzo and Scherer
put it, corporations do not, in participating with the FSC, “invite stakeholders
into their internal decision-making processes,” but rather move themselves out
to “the political processes of public policy making” (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007,
p. 1110). Given this focus, Palazzo and Scherer label their model of democratic
governance for corporations understood as public actors “political corporate
social responsibility,” or “political CSR” (Scherer & Palazzo, 2011).
V. A P
ROBLEM WITH THE MODEL
Palazzo and Scherer believe that, to close the democratic deficit that appears
when corporations engage in the new CPA, corporations’ actions must be
subject to social deliberation. It seems correct to say that, if a corporation is not
required to explain itself to others, or listen to those others’ points of view, then
it is not truly accountable to them. But we might wonder if that is all that is
required. Is a corporation’s performance of a state function legitimate—is it
accountable to the people—just in case it is the subject of deliberation among
affected parties? Or must this deliberation come to a particular conclusion that
the corporation is in some way subject to?
Surprisingly, Palazzo and Scherer do not directly address these questions. It
would be odd, however, if they answered ‘yes’ to the first one. This would
imply that the corporation, provided that it first engaged in deliberation with
affected parties, could legitimately perform whatever state function it wanted,
even if virtually all of those parties disapproved. As expected, then, several
passages in Palazzo and Scherers writings suggest a ‘no’ answer. They say that
“[modern] theories of political legitimacy link the rightfulness of domination to
the consent of the governed citizens” (Palazzo & Scherer, 2006, pp. 79–80), and
that deliberation leads “to better and broader accepted political decisions and...
thus contributes to sustaining moral legitimacy” (Palazzo & Scherer, 2006,
pp. 80–81). This suggests that the legitimacy of a corporation’s performance of
a state function requires more than just deliberation about it. It suggests that an
agreement of some sort is also required.
The problem is that deliberation, while perhaps capable of reducing disagree-
2014] 441C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
ment, is unlikely to eliminate it.
12
This is familiar to all casual observers of
politics, and indeed debates of all kinds among people with divergent interests.
Even well informed people deliberating in good faith may fail to come to
agreement. There are many reasons for this; we will highlight four.
One is time. It takes time to gather the relevant data, analyze it, construct
arguments based on it, subject those arguments to critical scrutiny, develop
counter-arguments, and so on. But time is not unlimited, especially in the
business world. And we would not want to change the business world so that
citizens and corporations had unlimited time to deliberate. The result is some
disagreements that could be resolved but, due to time constraints, are not.
A second source of disagreement derives from trust in information. In
deliberative processes, the state plays a role in ensuring that the public has
access to relevant information (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007). But even when all
parties have all the same information, they will have different degrees of trust in
different sources of information. An NGO and a corporation may publish
competing studies on the effects of a new pollution control measure, one which
concludes that it is cheap and effective (the NGO’s), the other of which
concludes that it is expensive and useless (the corporation’s). Some will trust
the corporation’s study more than the NGO’s, and some will trust the NGO’s
study more than the corporation’s. This may lead to a deliberative impasse.
A third source of disagreement is cognitive bias. There are many such biases,
but one that is especially problematic in this context is the self-serving bias.
This bias leads people to think that outcomes that benefit them, or benefit them
disproportionately, are fair (Bazerman & Messick, 1996). This leads to conflict
because the interests of different parties to social deliberation are likely to
diverge in important ways. Suppose that there is social deliberation about
whether a corporation should adopt a new pollution control measure. Many
affected parties will likely agree that the outcome should be fair—i.e., it should
balance benefits and burdens across affected parties—but they will likely
disagree about which outcome is fair. Each side will be especially sensitive to
the benefits it will enjoy and the burdens it will suffer (Christiano, 2004).
A fourth and perhaps the most important source of disagreement is value
pluralism (Gutmann & Thompson, 1996). Some citizens will think that, e.g.,
preserving old-growth forests is more important than economic growth; others
will think the opposite. This will lead them to different conclusions about the
extent to which corporations should be permitted to cut down old-growth
forests. Some citizens will think that we have powerful moral duties to those
who will be living in future generations; others will deny this. This will lead to
different conclusions about how much effort corporations and individuals should
make to reduce their carbon emissions. Values can be debated, but disagree-
ments about values cannot be easily debated away.
12. Indeed, in some cases, deliberation may increase the intensity of conflict. For a summary of the
literature on the effects of deliberation, see Mendelberg (2002).
Fn12
442 [Vol. 12:429THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
The claim that social deliberation in the real world is unlikely to lead to full
agreement, for these and other reasons, has been pressed forcefully by delibera-
tive democracy’s critics (Przeworski, 1998). But it is conceded by its propo-
nents as well (Goodin, 2008; Mansbridge, 2006). We are aware of no deliberative
democrat who thinks that social deliberation about contested issues will typi-
cally lead to consensus. Indeed, it seems more likely that it typically will not,
especially in liberal, pluralist societies. This goes for social deliberation about
the legitimacy of corporations’ performance of state functions. Where does this
leave Palazzo and Scherers theory?
Palazzo and Scherer recognize that “dissensual communication” is a problem
with which their model of democratic accountability for the corporation “will
have to deal” (Palazzo & Scherer, 2006, p. 83). But they offer no way to deal
with it. This reveals a significant hole in their model. If deliberation were sure
or even likely to lead to agreement between corporations and citizens, then we
might think of deliberation as a plausible source of accountability. The corpora-
tion would be accountable to the citizens because it would first discuss its plans
with them, and in the end it would do what citizens—and the corporation
itself—thought it should do. But it would be surprising for this to occur
regularly, for the reasons given above. And deliberation alone is not a full form
of accountability. It would be implausible to describe a corporation that did
whatever it thought was best, provided it first talked things over with citizens, as
truly accountable to them. Given the likelihood of irresolvable disagreement,
there must be some way for participants in deliberative processes to come to a
resolution, one that can be used to guide corporate behavior. In the following
section, we offer a way to fill this hole in Palazzo and Scherers model.
VI. T
HE SOLUTION
We suggest that dissensual communication can be overcome by voting.We
propose, in particular, a majority rule standard. Thus we claim that it is more
plausible to say that a corporation’s performance of a public function is legiti-
mate just in case there is (i) social deliberation about it, followed by (ii) major-
ity approval of it by affected parties in a free and fair vote. Put another way,
subjecting corporations’ action to social deliberation and voting, rather than
social deliberation alone, is a more plausible way of making them accountable
to the people, and hence of closing the democratic deficit that arises when
corporations perform state functions.
To be clear, our suggestion is not that social deliberation should be eliminated
and replaced with voting, but that voting should follow deliberation. Voting is a
way of making decisions when deliberation does not result in consensus. Of
course, it is not the only way of making decisions. We might toss a coin or draw
straws. But voting—especially majority voting—is a particularly democratic
2014] 443C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
way of deciding.
13
And indeed many supporters of deliberative democracy
endorse majority voting after deliberation (Goodin, 2008; Mansbridge, 2006).
Palazzo and Scherers silence on the question of voting is surprising because
the Forest Stewardship Council (FSC)—their primary example of a system of
democratic accountability suitable for the corporation—itself employs a voting
system in addition to a deliberative process. Members are divided into three
chambers: social, environmental, and economic. Each chamber is further subdi-
vided into a Northern and Southern group (group membership is determined by
the wealth of the country the member is from as opposed to its geographical
location). The FSC’s membership elects a board of directors that devises rules
and procedures for the organization, while the membership as a whole votes on
the FSC’s policies and principles. For a policy or principle to be approved, it
must receive majorities in each of the three chambers of the FSC.
14
The FSC,
then, is under no illusion that full agreement can be reached among individuals
and groups with disparate interests and values. Yet it does not think that this
delegitimizes corporate behavior. Its solution, like ours, is a system of majority
voting that follows social deliberation.
The introduction of voting into Palazzo and Scherers model of democratic
accountability for the corporation raises questions. We cannot hope to answer or
even raise them all here. We highlight what we believe to be the most salient
ones.
Some questions will have a familiar ring. One is: who should vote? A second
is: on what issues should they vote? In our view, these questions will be fully
answered by the answers that must be given to analogous questions about the
social deliberation that precedes voting. With respect to the first question,
anyone who has a right to participate in social deliberation should also have a
right to vote. As seen, Palazzo and Scherers answer to the question of who
should be able to participate in deliberation is: everyone who is possibly
affected by the action in question. So they should believe that everyone who is
possibly affected by the action should be allowed to vote on it.
15
With respect to
the second question, people should be able to vote on any issue about which
there is social deliberation that does not result in consensus. Since “the delibera-
13. Two points. First, we choose majority rule because of its long association with the idea of
democracy and its widespread used by actual democracies. However, we offer here no independent
argument for the soundness of this decision procedure and acknowledge that competitors to it have
been advanced. Second, in proposing a majority rule decision procedure, we do not assume that
decisions should be made by a simple majority. We consider weighted voting systems below.
14. For a description of the FSC’s governance system, see http://www.fsc.org/governance.html.
15. Of particular interest is the role that corporations themselves play in social deliberation and
voting. Palazzo and Scherer think that they should participate in the same way that political groups such
as the AARP and the Club for Growth do. Representatives of these groups are properly understood as
advocates for their members’ points of view. We deny that corporations and their representatives should
play this role. Instead, we claim, they should function as technical experts in political processes,
presenting relevant evidence and making disinterested arguments. The reason is that corporations are
not politically representative organizations. We develop this argument in Hussain & Moriarty (2014).
Fn13
Fn14
Fn15
444 [Vol. 12:429THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
tive concept...follows the principled priority of systematic routine as advo-
cated by Habermas,” corporations are permitted to carry out their activities as
normal, until the public becomes concerned about a certain issue, at which point
deliberation must commence (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007, p. 1111; emphasis in
original). We claim that, if deliberation does not result in consensus, then voting
should follow.
But the introduction of voting into Palazzo and Scherers model raises new
questions as well. Perhaps the most important of these is: how much weight
should each party’s vote have? Many writers have argued that democracy
requires equality (Christiano, 2008; Dahl, 1959), and it is natural to translate
this into a one-party-one-vote scheme. But other writers think weighted voting
systems are better suited to realizing democratic ideals (Brighouse & Fleurbaey,
2008; Mill, 1998/1861). In these systems, each party’s vote is proportionate to
its “stake” in the decision.
A voting procedure appended to Palazzo and Scherers model of democratic
accountability should reflect the values already embedded in it. But support for
both “equal” and “weighted” voting systems can be extracted from their model.
In one place, Palazzo and Scherer say that deliberations between corporations
and citizens must be “free of any internal coercion that could detract from the
equality of the participants” (1996, p. 305, emphasis added). This suggests that
a one-party-one-vote scheme may be best. But, following Habermas (1996),
Palazzo and Scherer claim that all of those affected by a corporate action should
have a chance to deliberate about it. This suggests that a voting scheme in
which people’s voting power is proportionate to the extent to which they are
affected by the action, or their stakes in it, may be more fitting. Moreover, the
FSC itself uses a weighted voting scheme. As mentioned, to be approved, a
policy or principle must receive majority support from each chamber (social,
environmental, and economic). But the Northern and Southern group within
each chamber each gets 50% of the voting power, regardless of their number of
members. In addition, to be accepted, motions must receive majority support
from the FSC as a whole. And each chamber is given equal voting power (i.e.,
33% of the vote), again regardless of their number of members.
Ultimately, we think this issue is too complex to be resolved here. We have
argued that Palazzo and Scherer’s model of democratic accountability for the
corporation should include a majority rule voting procedure, but its exact design
requires further analysis. Future research on this subject should be alive to the
possibility that different voting schemes may be appropriate in different con-
texts.
We have said that Palazzo and Scherer are silent on the issue of voting,
despite the fact that almost all deliberative democrats think voting is a practical
necessity, and the FSC uses a voting system. Where they come closest to
mentioning this issue, they seem to suggest that voting need not be a part of
their model. Thus while Palazzo and Scherer say that corporate political activity
should be subject to greater democratic control, they insist that their theory does
2014] 445C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
not require a “radical democratization of [the corporation’s] decision-making
processes” (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007, p. 1111). They go on: “[c]ivil society
actors should not assume the role of the state or that of the corporation but,
rather, should limit their engagement to controlling the political and economic
systems” in which the firm operates (Scherer & Palazzo, 2007, p. 1111).
We agree with the first of the above passages but not the second. That is, we
agree that making the corporation accountable to the public does not require
allowing the public to “grab hold,” as it were, of the reins of corporate power,
changing corporate leaders from decision-makers to mere executors of public
choices. This is so in two senses. First, not every action that the corporation
performs must be the subject of social deliberation or voting. Second, the public
does not so much tell the corporation what to do in the public sphere as
constrain its actions within it. In both of these senses, corporations remain
private concerns. But we disagree with Palazzo and Scherer in that we think that
realizing the ideal of deliberative democracy requires an exercise of control
over the corporation itself, not just the “political and economic systems” in
which it operates. The public’s limiting its control of the corporation to the
political and economic systems in which it operates is precisely what creates
the democratic deficit that Palazzo and Scherers model of democratic account-
ability for the corporation is meant to address. To remedy it, the public must be
able to set limits on corporate behavior itself.
The discussion in this section may seem to diminish the attractiveness of
Palazzo and Scherers model. Putting aside the fact of disagreement—as Palazzo
and Scherer mostly do—we have the following sanguine view of the relation-
ship between the corporation and the public: The corporation contemplates
performing a state function; it engages in a deliberative dialog with the public
about it; agreement is reached; and the corporation performs the action. When
there is no disagreement, everyone gets the result that they think there is most
reason to bring about, i.e., what they think is the right result. The corporation, in
particular, is not asked to do something that it thinks, in the final analysis, it
does not have most reason to do. Palazzo and Scherers model thus appears to
promise accountability without conflict or pressure. This is an attractive ideal.
We have stressed in this section that this ideal is in many cases unobtainable.
Dissensual communication is more likely to be the norm than the exception in
liberal, pluralist societies. This means that democratic accountability for the
corporation, on a proper understanding of Palazzo and Scherers model, will
involve conflict. When disagreement is introduced, we confront the possibility
that someone—one or more groups of citizens, or the corporation itself—will
have to live with a result that they think there is not most reason to bring about,
i.e., what they think is the wrong result. This further means that corporate
accountability will involve pressure. The corporation, in particular, may be
pressured to do something that it does not think it has most reason to do. This
does not mean that a corporation’s failure to obey the public’s will—following
social deliberation and expressed in a majority vote—should be met with
446 [Vol. 12:429T
HE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
state-sponsored force or threats of force. But corporations should feel significant
pressure to conform, perhaps because the costs of failing to conform (e.g., loss
of FSC certification) are high. Otherwise, the corporation cannot truly be said to
be subject to the people’s will.
While our discussion to this point has focused on Palazzo and Scherer, it
yields more general conclusions about democratic accountability for corpora-
tions engaged in the new CPA. To begin, any attempt to democratize corpora-
tions must involve more than deliberation. Since deliberation is unlikely to
result in consensus, a decision procedure is needed. Majority voting, we said, is
a democratic way of making decisions. But to say that democratically account-
ability for corporations requires majority voting raises new questions, such as
who should vote, on what they should vote, and how much weight each party’s
vote should have. Finally, the fact that a decision procedure such as majority
voting is necessary for making corporations accountable to citizens means that
repairing the democratic deficit by democratizing corporations is likely to be
costly. These costs must be kept in mind in determining how the democratic
deficit should be addressed.
VII. C
ONCLUSION
The new CPA—shaping public policy and rule-making—proceeds “beside or
around” or “above and beyond” the state, while the old CPA—lobbying and
campaign finance—proceeds “through” it. This helps the new CPA to avoid the
problem of corruption, which is one of the main problems with the old CPA.
But it presents a new and potentially more serious problem, viz., the democratic
deficit. Insofar as corporations shape public policy and make rules, they are
performing state functions but are not being governed like the state, that is,
democratically. Palazzo and Scherer offer a way to eliminate this deficit. We
have argued, however, that it is incomplete. They suggest that corporations can
be democratized through a society-wide process of deliberation. We have
argued that conflict is unlikely to be deliberated away, and voting will also be
required.
Where does this leave us? One thing we have stressed is that the new
corporate political activity, while avoiding one of the problems with the old
corporate political activity, is not problem-free. It creates a democratic deficit,
which should be acknowledged. Another is that, to judge by our examination of
one of the most prominent efforts to repair the deficit, doing so will involve loss
for some parties; not everyone can have their way. Future research must explore
the full costs of this and other ways of democratizing the new corporate political
activity. Ultimately, we will have to decide whether democratizing corporations
is worth the cost, whether it would be preferable for corporations to cease
shaping public policy and making rules, or whether we should simply live with
the democratic deficit, given the potential benefits of the new CPA.
2014] 447C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
REFERENCES
Ansolabehere, S., De Figueiredo, J. M., & Snyder, Jr., J. M. (2003). Why is
there so little money in U.S. politics? Journal of Economic Perspectives,
17(1), 105–130.
Bazerman, M. H., & Messick, D. M. (1996). Ethical leadership and the psychol-
ogy of decision making. Sloan Management Review, 37(2), 9–22.
Brenkert, G. G. (1992). Private corporations and public welfare. Public Affairs
Quarterly, 6(2), 155–168.
Brighouse, H., & Fleurbaey, M. (2008). Democracy and proportionality. Jour-
nal of Political Philosophy, 18(2), 137–155.
Christiano, T. (2004). The authority of democracy. Journal of Political Philoso-
phy, 12(3), 266–290.
Christiano, T. (2008). Democracy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclope-
dia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 ed.): URL ⫽⬍http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
fall2008/entries/democracy/.
Christiano, T. (2010a). The constitution of equality: Democratic authority and
its limits. New York: Oxford University Press.
Christiano, T. (2010b). The uneasy relationship between democracy and capital.
Social Philosophy and Policy, 27(1), 195–217.
Cohen, G. A. (2011). Capitalism, freedom, and the proletariat. In M. Otsuka
(Ed.), On the currency of egalitarian justice, and other essays in political
philosophy (pp. 147–165). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cohen, J. (1989). The economic basis of deliberative democracy. Social Philoso-
phy and Policy, 6(2), 25–50.
Crane, A., Matten, D., & Moon, J. (2008). Corporations and citizenship.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Dahl, R. A. (1959). A preface to democratic theory. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
De Figueiredo, J. M. (2002). Lobbying and information in politics. Business
and Politics, 4(2), 125–129.
Evan, W. M., & Freeman, R. E. (1988). A stakeholder theory of the modern
corporation: Kantian capitalism. In T. L. Beauchamp & N. E. Bowie (Eds.),
Ethical theory and business (3rd ed., pp. 97–106). Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Fort, T. L., & Schipani, C. A. (2004). The role of business in fostering peaceful
societies. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Friedman, M. (2002/1962). Capitalism and freedom (40th anniversary ed.).
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Friedman, M. (2008/1970). The social responsibility of business is to increase
its profits. In F. Allhoff & A. J. Vaidya (Eds.), Business in ethical focus: An
anthology (pp. 65–69). Toronto: Broadview Press.
Goodin, R. E. (2008). Innovating democracy: Democratic theory and practice
after the deliberative turn. New York: Oxford University Press.
448 [Vol. 12:429T
HE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
Greenhouse, S. (2013). Major retailers join Bangladesh safety plan, New York
Times, May 13. Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/2013/05/14/business/
global/hm-agrees-to-bangladesh-safety-plan.html.
Gutmann, A., & Thompson, D. F. (1996). Democracy and disagreement. Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse
theory of law and democracy (W. Rehg, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hansmann, H. (1996). The ownership of enterprise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Hasnas, J. (2003). Reflections on the minimal state. Politics, Philosophy, and
Economics, 2(1), 115–128.
Hillman, A. J., Keim, G. D., & Schuler, D. (2004). Corporate political activity:
A review and research agenda. Journal of Management, 30(6), 837–857.
Hussain, W. (2012). Is ethical consumerism an impermissible form of vigilan-
tism? Philosophy and Public Affairs, 40(2), 111–143.
Hussain, W., & Moriarty, J. (2014). Accountable to whom? Rethinking the
normative model of political CSR. Working paper.
Jensen, M. C. (2002). Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate
objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly, 12(2), 235–256.
Kobrin, S. J. (2009). Private political authority and public responsibility: Trans-
national politics, transnational firms, and human rights. Business Ethics
Quarterly, 19(3), 349–374.
Mansbridge, J. (2006). Conflict and self-interest in deliberation. In S. Besson &
J. L. Marti (Eds.), Deliberative democracy and its discontents (pp. 107–132).
Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Matten, D., & Crane, A. (2005). Corporate citizenship: Toward an extended
theoretical conceptualization. Academy of Management Review, 30(1), 166–
179.
Mendelberg, T. (2002). The deliberative citizen: Theory and evidence. In
M. W. Delli Carpini, L. Huddy, & R. Y. Shapiro, Political decision making,
deliberation, and participation (Research in micropolitics, volume 6) (pp. 151–
193). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Mill, J. S. (1998/1861). Considerations on representative government. In J. Gray
(Ed.), On liberty an other essays (pp. 203–467). New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press.
Milyo, J., Primo, D., & Groseclose, T. (2000). Corporate PAC campaign
contributions in perspective. Business and Politics, 2(1), 75–88.
Moriarty, J. (2012). The connection between stakeholder theory and stakeholder
democracy: An excavation and defense. Business & Society, OnlineFirst. doi:
10.1177/0007650312439296.
Newell, P. (2001). Managing multinationals: The governance of investment for
the environment. Journal of International Development, 13(7), 907–919.
Palazzo, G., & Scherer, A. G. (2006). Corporate legitimacy as deliberation: A
communicative framework. Journal of Business Ethics, 66(1), 71–88.
2014] 449C
ORPORATIONS, THE DEMOCRATIC DEFICIT, AND VOTING
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334
Przeworski, A. (1998). Deliberation and ideological domination. In J. Elster
(Ed.), Deliberative democracy (pp. 140–160). New York: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Ruggie, J. G. (2004). Reconstituting the global public domain: Issues, actors,
and practices. European Journal of Interational Relations, 10(4), 499–531.
Scherer, A. G., Baumann-Pauly, D., & Schneider, A. (2013). Democratizing
corporate governance: Compensating for the democratic deficit of corporate
political activity and corporate citizenship. Business & Society, 52(3), 473–
514.
Scherer, A. G., & Palazzo, G. (2007). Toward a political conception of corporate
responsibility: Business and society seen from a Habermasian perspective.
Academy of Management Review, 32(4), 1096–1120.
Scherer, A. G., & Palazzo, G. (2011). The new political role of business in a
globalized world: A review of a new perspective on CSR and its implications
for the firm, governance, and democracy. Journal of Management Studies,
48(4), 899–931.
Scherer, A. G., Palazzo, G., & Baumann, D. (2006). Global rules and private
actors: Toward a new role of the transnational corporation in global gover-
nance. Business Ethics Quarterly, 16(4), 505–532.
Shamir, R. (2004). Between self-regulation and the Alien Tort Claims Act:
On the contested concept of corporate social responsibility. Law & Society
Review, 38(4), 635–664.
Stark, A. (2010). Business in politics: Lobbying and corporate campaign contri-
butions. In G. G. Brenkert & T. L. Beauchamp (Eds.), Oxford handbook of
business ethics (pp. 501–534). New York: Oxford University Press.
Sunstein, C. R. (1994). Political equality and unintended consequences. Colum-
bia Law Review, 94(4), 1390–1414.
Vogel, D. (2010). The private regulation of global corporate conduct: Achieve-
ments and limitations. Business & Society, 49(1), 68–87.
Waldron, J. (1993). Homelessness and the issue of freedom. In his Liberal
Rights (pp. 309–338). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wettstein, F. (2009). Multinational corporations and global justice: Human
rights obligations of a quasi-governmental institution. Stanford, CA: Stan-
ford Business Books.
450 [Vol. 12:429T
HE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LAW &PUBLIC POLICY
Orig. Op. OPERATOR: Session PROOF: PE’s: AA’s: COMMENTS ARTNO:
1 t DCT k 2 d b 6 8
2334