GW Law Faculty Publications & Other Works Faculty Scholarship
2012
Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law Beyond Borders Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law Beyond Borders
(Introduction) (Introduction)
Paul Schiff Berman
George Washington University Law School
, pberman@law.gwu.edu
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.gwu.edu/faculty_publications
Part of the Law Commons
Recommended Citation Recommended Citation
Paul Schiff Berman, Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law Beyond Borders, 3, Cambridge
University Press, 2012
This Book Part is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Scholarly Commons. It has
been accepted for inclusion in GW Law Faculty Publications & Other Works by an authorized administrator of
Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact spagel@law.gwu.edu.
3
W
E LIVE IN A WORLD OF MULTIPLE OVERLAPPING
normative communities. For example, I am typ-
ing these words in a house in Massachusetts,
although I am a resident of Maryland, who works in Washington, DC.
Thus, Massachusetts state law may govern some of my activities, while
Maryland law or DC law may be relevant to other aspects of my life. And
in Massachusetts, Maryland, and DC I am also located within a variety of
political sub- divisions, such as towns, cities, counties, wards, neighborhood
districts, water regions, and so on, each of which may have normative
authority over me. Federal law governs many aspects of my life as well,
from the speed limits on the interstate highways to certain environmental
standards affecting the air and water, to the individual liberties the U.S.
Constitution protects. International law may be the source of additional
rights or protections, ranging from standards for trade, technology, and
the use of satellites to the frameworks for regulating the environment,
consumer product labeling, and the conduct of war. And certainly if I
travel abroad or surf Internet sites based overseas or enter into contracts
with foreign entities I will run up against international and transnational
legal norms.
But these governmental normative communities are just the tip of
the iceberg. Nonstate communities may also impose signi cant norma-
tive force. For example, if I think someone is violating the copyright of
this book, I may use international arbitration sanctioned by the World
1 Introduction
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM4
Intellectual Property Organization, a nongovernmental entity. If Web
searches for my book do not place my Web page high enough on the list, I
may need to challenge Google’s search indexing protocols. And I am gov-
erned (or at least strongly in uenced) by tenure rules at my university,
religious rules of my faith (if I am a believer), American Bar Association
rules regarding the conduct of law school classrooms, the metrics used
by US News & World Report when it ranks law schools, and simply the
practices and customs of the academic community of which I am a part.
And on and on.
This book seeks to grapple with the complexities of law in a world
where a single act or actor is potentially regulated by multiple legal or
quasi-legal regimes. Law often operates based on a convenient  ction
that nation-states exist in autonomous, territorially distinct spheres
and that activities therefore fall under the legal jurisdiction of only one
regime at a time. Thus, traditional legal rules have tied jurisdiction to
territory: a state could exercise complete authority within its territorial
borders and no authority beyond it. In the twentieth century, such rules
were loosened, but territorial location remained the principal touch-
stone for assigning legal authority. Accordingly, if one could spatially
ground a dispute, one could most likely determine the legal rule that
would apply.
But consider such a system in today’s world. Should the U.S. govern-
ment be able to sidestep the U.S. Constitution when it houses prisoners in
“offshore detention facilities in Guant á namo Bay or elsewhere around
the world? Should spatially distant corporations that create serious local
harms be able to escape local legal regulation simply because they are
not physically located in the jurisdiction? When the U.S. government
seeks to shut down the computer of a hacker located in Russia, does
the virus transmitted constitute an act of war or a violation of Russia’s
sovereignty? Does it make sense to think that satellite transmissions,
online interactions, and complex  nancial transactions have any territo-
rial locus at all? How can we best understand the complex relationships
among international, regional, national, and subnational legal systems?
INTRODUCTION 5
And in a world where nonstate actors such as industry standard-setting
bodies, nongovernmental organizations, religious institutions, ethnic
groups, terrorist networks, and others exert signi cant normative pull,
can we build a suf ciently capacious understanding of the very idea of
jurisdiction to address the incredible array of overlapping authorities
that are our daily reality?
Thus, a simple model that looks only to territorial delineations among
of cial state-based legal systems is now simply untenable (if it was ever
useful to begin with). Thankfully, debates about globalization have moved
beyond the polarizing question of whether the nation-state is dying or
not. But one does not need to believe in the death of the nation-state
to recognize both that physical location can no longer be the sole crite-
rion for conceptualizing legal authority and that nation-states must work
within a framework of multiple overlapping jurisdictional assertions by
state, international, and even nonstate communities. Each of these types
of overlapping jurisdictional assertions creates a potentially hybrid legal
space that is not easily eliminated.
With regard to con icts between and among states, the growth of
global communications technologies, the rise of multinational corporate
entities with no signi cant territorial center of gravity, and the mobility
of capital and people across borders mean that many jurisdictions will
feel effects of activities around the globe, leading inevitably to multiple
assertions of legal authority over the same act, without regard to ter-
ritorial location. For example, in 2000 a French court asserted jurisdic-
tion over the U.S.-based web portal Yahoo! because French users could
download Nazi memorabilia and Holocaust denial material via Yahoo!’s
auction sites, in violation of French law.
1
Yahoo! argued in response that
the French assertion of jurisdiction was impermissibly extraterritorial
in scope because Yahoo!, as a U.S. corporation transmitting material
1
Tribunal de grande instance (TGI) [ordinary court of original jurisdiction] Paris, May
22, 2000, Ordonnance de r é f é r é , UEJF et Licra c/ Yahoo! Inc. et Yahoo France , available
at http://www.juriscom.net/txt/jurisfr/cti/tgiparis20000522.htm.
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM6
uploaded in the United States, was protected by the First Amendment
of the U.S. Constitution.
2
Yet, the extraterritoriality charge runs in both
directions. If France is not able to block the access of French citizens to
proscribed material, then the United States will effectively be imposing
First Amendment norms on the entire world. And whatever the solu-
tion to this problem might be, a territorial analysis will not help because
the relevant transaction is both “in France and not “in France simulta-
neously. Cross-border environmental,
3
trade,
4
intellectual property,
5
and
tax regulation
6
raise similar issues.
The problem of multiple states’ asserting jurisdiction over the same
activity is just the beginning, however, because nation-states must
also often share legal authority with one or more international and
regional courts, tribunals, or regulatory entities. Indeed, the Project on
International Courts and Tribunals has identi ed approximately 125
international institutions, all issuing decisions that have some effect on
state legal authority,
7
though those decisions are sometimes deemed
binding, sometimes merely persuasive, and often fall somewhere between
the two. For example, under the North American Free Trade Agreement
(NAFTA) and other similar agreements, special panels can pass judgment
2
Id.
3
See, e.g. , Transboundary Harm in International Law: Lessons from the Trail Smelter
Arbitration (Rebecca M. Bratspies & Russell A. Miller eds., 2006); Philippe Sands,
Turtles and Torturers: The Transformation of International Law, 33 N.Y.U. J. Int’l L. &
Pol. 527 (2001).
4
See, e.g. , Richard W. Parker, The Use and Abuse of Trade Leverage to Protect the
Global Commons: What We Can Learn from the Tuna-Dolphin Con ict, 12 Geo. Int’l
Envtl. L. Rev. 1 (1999).
5
See, e.g. , Barcelona.com, Inc. v. Excelentisimo Ayuntamiento de Barcelona, 330 F.3d
617 (4th Cir. 2003); GlobalSantaFe Corp. v. GlobalSantaFe.com, 250 F. Supp. 2d 610
(E.D. Va. 2003); Graeme B. Dinwoodie, A New Copyright Order: Why National Courts
Should Create Global Norms, 149 U. Pa. L. Rev. 469 (2000).
6
See, e.g. , Paul Schiff Berman, The Globalization of Jurisdiction, 151 U. Pa. L. Rev. 311,
334–7 (2002).
7
See Project on International Courts and Tribunals, The International Judiciary in
Context (2004), available at http://www.pict-pcti.org/publications/synoptic _chart/
Synop_C4.pdf.
INTRODUCTION 7
on whether domestic legal proceedings have provided fair process.
8
And
though the panels cannot directly review or overturn local rulings, they
can levy  nes against the federal government signatories of the agree-
ment, thereby undermining the impact of the local judgment.
9
Thus, now
that a NAFTA tribunal has ruled that the conduct of a Mississippi trial
against a Canadian corporation “was so  awed that it constituted a mis-
carriage of justice amounting to manifest injustice as that expression
is understood in international law,
10
it is an open question as to how
Mississippi courts will rule in future cases involving foreign defendants.
11
Meanwhile, in the realm of human rights, we have seen criminal defen-
dants convicted in state courts in the United States proceed (through
their governments) to the International Court of Justice (ICJ) to argue
that they were denied the right to contact their consulate, as required by
treaty.
12
Again, although the ICJ judgments are technically unenforceable
in the United States, at least one state court followed the ICJ’s command
anyway.
13
Meanwhile, outside these more formal adjudicative processes,
there are many powerful transnational networks of governmental regula-
tors setting a kind of international policy as a de facto matter over much
of the global  nancial system, among other areas.
14
Finally, nonstate legal (or quasi-legal) norms add to this pluralism of
authority. Given increased migration and global communication, it is not
8
See North American Free Trade Agreement, U.S.-Can.-Mex., Dec. 7–17, 1992, art. 1135,
32 I.L.M. 605, 646.
9
Id.
10
Loewen Group, Inc. v. United States , ICSID (W. Bank) Case No. ARB(AF)/98/3 (June
26, 2003) (Final Merits Award), reprinted in 42 I.L.M. 811 (2003), also available at http://
naftaclaims.com/Disputes/USA/Loewen/LoewenFinalAward.pdf. Publicly released
documents on all NAFTA disputes are available at http://www.naftalaw.org.
11
See generally Robert B. Ahdieh, Between Dialogue and Decree: International Review
of National Courts, 79 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 2029 (2004) (discussing case).
12
See Case Concerning Avena and Other Mexican Nationals (Mex. v. U.S.), 2004 I.C.J. 12.
13
See Torres v. State , No. PCD-04–442, 2004 WL 3711623 (Okla. Crim. App. May 13, 2004)
(granting stay of execution and remanding case for evidentiary hearing).
14
See, e.g. , David Zaring, Rulemaking and Adjudication in International Law, 46 Colum.
J. Transnat’l L. 563 (2008); David Zaring, Informal Procedure, Hard and Soft, in
International Administration, 5 Chi. J. Int’l L. 547 (2005).
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM8
surprising that people feel ties to, and act on the basis of af liations with,
multiple communities in addition to their territorial ones. Such commu-
nities may be ethnic, religious, or epistemic; transnational, subnational,
or international; and the norms asserted by such communities frequently
challenge territorially based authority. Indeed, canon law and other reli-
gious community norms have long operated in signi cant overlap with
state law. And in the Middle East and elsewhere, con icts between a per-
sonal law tied to religion and a territorial law tied to the nation-state con-
tinue to pose constitutional and other challenges.
15
Bonds of ethnicity can
also create signi cant normative communities. For example, some com-
mentators advocate regimes that give ethnic minorities limited autonomy
within larger nation-states.
16
Transnationally, when members of an ethnic
diaspora purchase securities issued by their “home country, one might
argue that, regardless of where, territorially, the bonds are purchased, the
transactions should be governed by the law of the “homeland.
17
Finally,
we see communities of transnational bankers and accountants develop-
ing their own regulatory regimes governing trade  nance
18
or accounting
standards,
19
as well as the use of modern forms of lex mercatoria
20
to
15
See, e.g. , Chibli Mallat, On the Speci city of Middle Eastern Constitutionalism, 38 Case
W. Res. J. Int’l L. 13, 47–55 (2006).
16
See, e.g. , Henry J. Steiner, Ideals and Counter-Ideals in the Struggle over Autonomy
Regimes for Minorities, 66 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1539, 1541–2 (1991) (identifying three
different types of autonomy regimes for ethnic minorities).
17
See Anupam Chander, Diaspora Bonds, 76 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1005, 1060–74 (2001) (describ-
ing debt instruments offered by the Indian government to raise capital principally from
its diaspora).
18
See Janet Koven Levit, A Bottom-Up Approach to International Lawmaking: The Tale
of Three Trade Finance Instruments, 30 Yale J. Int’l L. 125 (2005).
19
For example, the International Accounting Standards Board is an independent, not-for-
pro t organization that seeks “to develop a single set of high quality, understandable,
enforceable and globally accepted international  nancial reporting standards.” IFRS
Foundation, About the IFRS Foundation and the IASB, available at http://www.ifrs.org/
The+organisation/IASCF+and+IASB.htm.
20
See, e.g. , Clayton P. Gillette, The Law Merchant in the Modern Age: Institutional Design
and International Usages Under the CISG, 5 Chi. J. Int’l L. 157, 159 (2004) (noting
that the Convention “explicitly incorporates trade usages into contracts that it governs,
permits usages to trump con icting [Convention] provisions, and authorizes courts to
INTRODUCTION 9
govern business relations.
21
Such nonstate legal systems often in uence
(or are incorporated in) state or international regimes.
22
These spheres of complex overlapping legal authority are, not sur-
prisingly, sites of con ict and confusion. In response to this hybrid reality,
communities might seek to “solve such con icts either by reimposing the
primacy of territorially based (and often nation-state-based) authority or
by seeking universal harmonization. Thus, on the one hand, communities
may try to seal themselves off from outside in uence, either by retreating
from the rest of the world and becoming more insular (as many religious
groups seek to do), by building walls either literal or regulatory to pro-
tect the community from outsiders, by taking measures to limit outside
in uence (U.S. legislation seeking to discipline judges for citing foreign or
international law is but one prominent example), or by falling back on ter-
ritorially based jurisdiction or choice-of-law rules. At the other extreme,
we see calls for harmonization of norms, more treaties, the construction of
international governing bodies, and the creation of “world law.
interpret and complete contracts by reference to usages”). But see Celia Wasserstein
Fassberg, Lex Mercatoria – Hoist with Its Own Petard? 5 Chi. J. Int’l L. 67 (2004) (argu-
ing that the modern revival of lex mercatoria departs signi cantly from the historical
conception).
21
See, e.g. , Amitai Aviram, A Paradox of Spontaneous Formation: The Evolution of Private
Legal Systems, 22 Yale L. & Pol’y Rev. 1 (2004) (using game theory to argue that the exist-
ence of preexisting networks enhances a private legal system’s ability to enforce norms);
Lisa Bernstein, Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the
Diamond Industry, 21 J. Legal Stud. 115 (1992) (discussing the system of “private law-
making” in the New York Diamond Dealers Club); Lisa Bernstein, Private Commercial
Law in the Cotton Industry: Creating Cooperation Through Rules, Norms, and Institutions,
99 Mich. L. Rev. 1724 (2001) (describing the nonstate legal system used to govern com-
mercial transactions in the cotton industry); Eric A. Feldman, The Tuna Court: Law and
Norms in the World’s Premier Fish Market, 94 Cal. L. Rev. 313 (2006) (discussing a “Tuna
Court” in Japan that adjudicates disputes about sale prices in a tuna market).
22
See, e.g. , Levit, supra note 18, at 165 (describing ways in which formal lawmaking insti-
tutions such as the World Trade Organization have, over time, appropriated nonstate
trade  nance norms into their of cial legal instruments). See generally Carol Weisbrod,
Fusion Folk: A Comment on Law and Music, 20 Cardozo L. Rev. 1439 (1999) (using the
incorporation of folk music into “high culture classical compositions as a metaphor for
understanding the relationship between state and nonstate law).
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM10
I argue that we should be wary of pinning our hopes on legal regimes
that rely either on reimposing sovereigntist
23
territorial insularity or
on striving for universals. Not only are such strategies sometimes nor-
matively undesirable, but more fundamentally they simply will not be
successful in many circumstances. As I will address in more detail, the
in uence and application of foreign norms or foreign decision-making
bodies may be useful and productive, but in any event they are inevitable
and cannot be willed away by  at.
Therefore, I suggest an alternative response to legal hybridity: we
might deliberately seek to create or preserve spaces for productive inter-
action among multiple, overlapping legal systems by developing proce-
dural mechanisms, institutions, and practices that aim to manage, without
eliminating, the legal pluralism we see around us . Such mechanisms, insti-
tutions, and practices can help mediate con icts by recognizing that mul-
tiple communities may legitimately wish to assert their norms over a
given act or actor, by seeking ways of reconciling competing norms, and
by deferring to alternative approaches if possible. And even when a deci-
sion maker cannot defer to an alternative norm (because some assertions
of norms are repressive, violent, and/or profoundly illiberal), procedures
for managing pluralism can at least require an explanation of why defer-
ence is impossible.
The excruciatingly dif cult case-by-case questions concerning how
much to defer to another normative community and how much to impose
the norms of one’s own community are probably impossible to answer
de nitively. The crucial antecedent point, however, is that although peo-
ple may never reach agreement on norms, they may at least acquiesce
in procedural mechanisms, institutions, or practices that take pluralism
seriously, rather than ignoring it through assertions of territorially based
power or dissolving it through universalist imperatives. Processes for man-
aging pluralism seek to preserve spaces of opportunity for contestation
23
I borrow the term “sovereigntist” from Peter Spiro, The New Sovereigntists: American
Exceptionalism and Its False Prophets, Foreign Affairs 9–15 (Nov./Dec. 2000).
INTRODUCTION 11
and local variation. Accordingly, a focus on hybridity may at times be
both normatively preferable and more practical precisely because agree-
ment on substantive norms is so dif cult. And again, the claim is only that
the independent values of pluralism should always be factored into the
analysis, not that they should never be trumped by other considerations.
Of course, even if pluralist institutions and processes better re ect
the complexity of the world around us, that is not necessarily a reason
to adopt them. Yet, we may  nd that the added norms, viewpoints, and
participants produce better decision making, better adherence to those
decisions by participants and nonparticipants alike, and ultimately better
real-world outcomes. And while this may not always be so, the essential
point is that in the design of procedures, institutions, and discursive prac-
tices these possible bene ts need to be considered.
This alternative jurisprudence I propose is fundamentally both cos-
mopolitan and pluralist . Thus, I should take a moment at the outset to
explain what I mean by both terms. This is particularly important because
in political and scholarly discourse these terms are often subject to vary-
ing uses, meanings, and connotations.
By cosmopolitan, I mean to invoke a framework recognizing that we
are all fundamentally members of multiple communities, both local and
global, territorial and epistemic. Unfortunately, many con ate cosmopol-
itanism with universalism.
24
Yet cosmopolitanism does not require a
belief in a single global welfare or even a single universal set of governing
norms; nor does it necessarily require that global welfare trump state or
local welfare. Instead, cosmopolitanism is a useful trope for conceptual-
izing the current period of interaction across territorial borders precisely
24
See, e.g. , Viet D. Dinh, Nationalism in the Age of Terror, 56 Fla. L. Rev. 867, 879 (2004)
(“Rather than aspiring to universal cosmopolitanism , statelessness may well foster rever-
sion to a sel sh individualism.”) (emphasis added); see also Bruce Ackerman, Rooted
Cosmopolitanism, 104 Ethics 516, 534 (1994) (“If I were a European right now, I hope
I would have the guts to stand up for rootless cosmopolitanism: forget this nationalistic
claptrap, and let us build a world worthy of free and equal human beings.”); Anupam
Chander, Diaspora Bonds, 76 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1005, 1046 (2001) (“The cosmopolitan
model . . . dissolves the multirootedness of diasporas into a global identity.”).
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM12
because it recognizes that people have multiple af liations, extending
from the local to the global (and many nonterritorial af liations as well).
Thus, cosmopolitanism is emphatically not a model of international citi-
zenship in the sense of international harmonization and standardization,
but is instead a recognition of multiple refracted differences where peo-
ple acknowledge links with the “other” without demanding either assim-
ilation or ostracism.
Pluralism goes even further and recognizes that our conception of law
must include more than just of cially sanctioned governmental edicts or
formal court documents. As discussed previously, many different non-
state communities assert various forms of jurisdiction and impose all
kinds of normative demands. Moreover, people often feel themselves to
be bound by such entities, regardless of the formal status of those entities.
Indeed, legal pluralists have long noted that law does not reside solely in
the coercive commands of a sovereign power.
25
Rather, law is constantly
25
See, e.g. , Sally Falk Moore, Legal Systems of the World: An Introductory Guide to
Classi cations, Typological Interpretations, and Bibliographical Resources, in Law
and the Social Sciences 11, 15 (Leon Lipson & Stanton Wheeler eds., 1986) (“[N]ot
all the phenomena related to law and not all that are lawlike have their source in
government.”). For further discussions of legal pluralism, see Keebet von Benda-
Beckmann, Transnational Dimensions of Legal Pluralism, in Begegnung und Kon ikt:
eine kulturanthropologische Bestandsaufnahme 33, 33–48 (2001); Boaventura de Sousa
Santos, Toward a New Legal Common Sense: Law, Globalization, and Emancipation
(William Twinning & Christopher McCrudden eds., 2d ed., 2002); Law and Globalization
from Below: Towards a Cosmopolitan Legality (Boaventura de Sousa Santos & C é sar
A. Rodr í guez-Garavito eds., 2005); Gunther Teubner, ‘Global Bukowina’: Legal
Pluralism in the World Society, in Global Law Without a State 3–28 (Gunther Teubner
ed., 1997); Carol Weisbrod, Emblems of Pluralism: Cultural Differences and the State
(2002); Franz von Benda-Beckmann, Who’s Afraid of Legal Pluralism? 47 J. Legal
Pluralism & Unof cial L. 37 (2002); David M. Engel, Legal Pluralism in an American
Community: Perspectives on a Civil Trial Court, 5 Am. B. Found. Res. J. 425 (1980);
Marc Galanter, Justice in Many Rooms: Courts, Private Ordering, and Indigenous Law,
19 J. Legal Pluralism 1, 28–34 (1981); John Grif ths, What Is Legal Pluralism? 24 J.
Legal Pluralism & Unof cial L. 1 (1986); Sally Engle Merry, Legal Pluralism, 22 Law &
Soc’y Rev. 869, 870 (1988) [hereinafter Merry, Legal Pluralism]; Sally Falk Moore, Law
and Social Change: The Semi-Autonomous Social Field as an Appropriate Subject of
Study, 7 Law. & Soc’y Rev. 719 (1973) [hereinafter Moore, The Semi-Autonomous Social
Field]; Balakrishnan Rajagopal, The Role of Law in Counter-hegemonic Globalization
INTRODUCTION 13
constructed through the contest of these various norm-generating
communities.
26
Thus, although “of cial” norms articulated by sovereign
entities obviously count as “law, such of cial assertions of prescriptive
or adjudicatory jurisdiction are only some of the many ways in which
normative commitments arise.
Moreover, legal pluralists have sought to document hybrid legal
spaces, where more than one legal, or quasi-legal, regime occupies the
same social  eld.
27
Historically, such sites were most prominently associ-
ated either with colonialism – where the legal system imposed by empire
was layered on top of indigenous legal systems
28
– or the study of reli-
gion – where, as noted previously, canon law and other spiritual codes
have often existed in an uneasy relationship with the state legal system.
29
and Global Legal Pluralism: Lessons from the Narmada Valley Struggle in India, 18
Leiden J. Int’l L. 345 (2005) (U.K.); Brian Z. Tamanaha, A Non-Essentialist Version
of Legal Pluralism, 27 J.L. & Soc’y 296 (2000); Sally Engle Merry, International Law
and Sociolegal Scholarship: Toward a Spatial Global Legal Pluralism (Studies in Law,
Politics, & Society, Vol. 41 Austin Sarat ed., 2007).
26
See Robert Cover, Foreword: Nomos and Narrative, The Supreme Court 1982 Term,
97 Harv. L. Rev. 4, 43 (1983) [hereinafter Cover, Nomos and Narrative] (“The position
that only the state creates law . . . confuses the status of interpretation with the sta-
tus of political domination.”); see also Robert Cover, The Folktales of Justice: Tales
of Jurisdiction, in Narrative, Violence, and the Law: The Essays of Robert Cover 173,
176 (Martha Minow, Michael Ryan, & Austin Sarat eds., 1992)(“[A]ll collective behav-
ior entailing systematic understandings of our commitments to future worlds [can
lay] equal claim to the word ‘law.’”) (alterations in original); Perry Dane, The Maps of
Sovereignty: A Meditation, 12 Cardozo L. Rev. 959, 963–4 (1991) (“This Article belongs
to a body of legal scholarship that refuses to limit the domain of law to the law of the
state.”).
27
See Moore, The Semi-Autonomous Social Field, supra note 25, at 720.
28
See, e.g. , Leopold Pospisil, Modern and Traditional Administration of Justice in New
Guinea, 19 J. Legal Pluralism 93 (1981).
29
See, e.g. , Carol Weisbrod, The Boundaries of Utopia (1980) (examining the contrac-
tual underpinnings of four nineteenth-century American religious utopian commu-
nities: the Shakers, the Harmony Society, Oneida, and Zoar). As Marc Galanter has
observed, the  eld of church and state is the “locus classicus of thinking about the mul-
tiplicity of normative orders.” Galanter, supra note 25, at 28; see also Carol Weisbrod,
Family, Church and State: An Essay on Constitutionalism and Religious Authority, 26
J. Fam. L. 741 (1988) (analyzing church-state relations in the United States from a plu-
ralist perspective).
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM14
Legal pluralists explored the myriad ways that overlapping legal systems
interact with each other and observed that the very existence of multiple
systems can at times create openings for contestation, resistance, and cre-
ative adaptation.
30
In this book, I apply a cosmopolitan pluralist framework to the global
arena and argue that this framework is essential if we are to more com-
prehensively conceptualize a world of hybrid legal spaces. This approach,
I realize, is unlikely to be fully satisfying either to committed nation-
state sovereigntists or to committed universalists. Indeed, these poles in
some ways echo those that Martii Koskenniemi famously identi ed as
the irreconcilable positions inherent in all international legal argument.
31
Thus, sovereigntists will object to the idea that nation-states should
ever take into account international, transnational, or nonstate norms.
32
Universalists, for their part, will chafe at the idea that international norms
should ever be subordinated to local practices that may be less liberal or
less rights-protecting. And even hard-line pluralists will complain that a
view focusing on how of cial actors respond to hybridity is overly state-
centric.
All I can say to such objections is that if a perspective displeases
everyone to some extent, it is, for that very reason, also likely to be a
perspective that manages hybridity in the only way possible: by forging
provisional compromises that fully satisfy no one but may at least gener-
ate grudging acquiescence. And, in a world of multiple norms, such pro-
visional compromises may ultimately be the best we can do. In any event,
the central argument of this book is that hybridity is a reality we can-
not escape, and a pure sovereigntist or universalist position will often be
unsustainable as a practical matter. Thus, cosmopolitan pluralism offers
30
See, e.g. , Merry, Legal Pluralism, supra note 25, at 878 (noting room for resistance and
autonomy within plural systems).
31
See Martii Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal
Argument (1989) (rev. ed. 2006). I am grateful to Duncan Hollis for identifying key
points of contact between my argument and Koskenniemi’s.
32
In part, this objection is grounded in concerns about loss of democratic accountability
and legitimacy. I address some of these concerns in Chapter 3.
INTRODUCTION 15
both a more accurate descriptive account of the world we live in and a
potentially useful alternative approach to the design of procedural mech-
anisms, institutions, and discursive practices.
Of course, one thing that a cosmopolitan pluralist approach will
not do is provide an authoritative metric for determining which norms
should prevail in this messy hybrid world. Nor does it de nitively answer
the question of who gets to decide. Indeed, pluralism fundamentally chal-
lenges both positivist and natural rights–based assumptions that there
can ever be a single answer to such questions. For example, as pluralists
have documented in the colonial context, the states efforts to squelch
a nonstate community are likely only to be partial,
33
and so the state’s
assertion of its own trumping authority is not the end of the debate, but
only one gambit in an ongoing normative discourse that has no  nal
resolution. Likewise, there is no external position from which one could
make a de nitive statement as to who is authorized to make decisions in
any given case. Rather, a statement of authority is itself inevitably open
to contest. Power disparities matter, of course, and those who wield coer-
cive force may be able to silence competing voices for a time. But even
that sort of temporary silencing is rarely the end of the story either. Thus,
instead of the unitary answers assumed by both universalism and sov-
ereigntist territorialism, cosmopolitan pluralism provides a “jurisgenera-
tive model
34
that focuses on the creative interventions made by various
communities drawing on a variety of normative sources in ongoing polit-
ical, rhetorical, and legal iterations.
35
33
See, e.g. , Lauren Benton, Making Order out of Trouble: Jurisdictional Politics in the
Spanish Colonial Borderlands, 26 Law & Soc. Inquiry 373, 375–6 (2001) (describing
jurisdictional politics in seventeenth-century New Mexico and observing that, while
“the crown made aggressive claims that royal authority and state law superseded other
legal authorities,” in reality “[j]urisdictional disputes became not just commonplace but
a de ning feature of the legal order”).
34
See Cover, Nomos and Narrative, supra note 26, at 11–15.
35
Cf. Seyla Benhabib, Another Cosmopolitanism 49 (Robert Post, ed., 2006) 49 (2006)
(“Whereas natural right philosophies assume that the principles that undergird demo-
cratic politics are impervious to transformative acts of popular collective will, and
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM16
Certainly individual communities may decide that their norms should
trump those of others or that their norms are authoritative. So, for exam-
ple, a liberal democratic state might decide that certain illiberal commu-
nity practices are so beyond the pale that they cannot be countenanced,
and therefore the state may invoke its authority to sti e those practices.
But a cosmopolitan pluralist approach recognizes that such statements
of normative commitment and authority are themselves subject to dis-
pute. Accordingly, instead of clinging to the vain hope that unitary claims
to authoritative law can ever be de nitive, cosmopolitan pluralism rec-
ognizes the inevitability (if not always the desirability) of hybridity.
Cosmopolitan pluralism is thus not a framework that dictates particular
substantive outcomes. It observes that various actors pursue norms, and
it studies the interplay, but it does not propose a hierarchy of substantive
norms and values.
Nevertheless, while it does not offer substantive norms, a cosmopol-
itan pluralist approach may favor procedural mechanisms, institutions,
and practices that provide opportunities for plural voices. Such proce-
dures can potentially help to channel (or even tame) normative con ict
to some degree by bringing multiple actors together into a shared social
space. In addition, including multiple voices may lead to better substan-
tive outcomes because such multiplicity provides the possibility for cre-
ative alternatives that might otherwise not be heard. This cosmopolitan
pluralist commitment can, of course, have strong normative implications
because it asks decision makers and institutional designers at least to
consider the independent value of pluralism. For example, as discussed
in more detail later, we might favor a hybrid domestic-international tri-
bunal over either a fully domestic or a fully international one because it
includes a more diverse range of actors, or we might favor complemen-
tarity or subsidiarity regimes because they encourage dialogue among
whereas legal positivism identi es democratic legitimacy with the correctly generated
legal norms of a sovereign legislature, jurisgenerative politics is a model that permits us
to think of creative interventions that mediate between universal norms and the will of
democratic majorities.”).
INTRODUCTION 17
multiple jurisdictions, and so on. And we might prefer con ict of law
frameworks that recognize the reality of hybridity rather than arbitrarily
choosing a single governing legal regime to resolve problems implicating
multiple communities. In any event, cosmopolitan pluralism questions
whether a single world public order of the sort often contemplated by
both nation-state sovereigntists and international law triumphalists is
achievable, even assuming it were desirable.
At the same time, mechanisms, institutions, and practices of the sort
discussed in this book require actors at least to be willing to take part in
a common set of discursive forms. This is not as idealistic as it may at  rst
appear. As Jeremy Waldron has argued, “[t]he dif culties of inter-cultural
or religious-secular dialogue are often exaggerated when we talk about
the incommensurability of cultural frameworks and the impossibility of
conversation without a common conceptual scheme. In fact conversation
between members of different cultural and religious communities is sel-
dom a dialogue of the deaf.
36
Nevertheless, it is certainly true that some
normative systems deny even this limited goal of mutual dialogue. Such
systems would (correctly) recognize the liberal bias within the vision of
procedural pluralism I explore here,
37
and they may reject the vision on
that basis. For example, while abortion rights and antiabortion activists
could, despite their differences, be said to share a willingness to engage in
a common practice of constitutional adjudication, those bombing abor-
tion clinics are not similarly willing, and accordingly there may not be any
way to accommodate such actors even within a more pluralist framework.
Likewise, communities that refuse to allow even the participation of par-
ticular subgroups, such as women or minorities, may be dif cult to include
within the cosmopolitan pluralist vision I have in mind. Of course, these
36
Jeremy Waldron, Public Reason and “Justi cation in the Courtroom, 1 J.L. Phil. &
Culture 107, 112 (2007).
37
This is not to say that the vision of pluralism I explore should be taken as synonym-
ous with liberalism, though they share many attributes. Pluralism arguably assigns an
independent value to dialogue among communities and an importance to community
af liation that is absent from (or at least less central to) liberal theory.
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM18
groups are undeniably important forces to recognize and take account of
as a descriptive matter. But from a normative perspective, an embrace of
a cosmopolitan pluralist jurisprudence need not commit one to a world-
view free from judgment, where all positions are equivalently embraced.
Thus, I argue not necessarily for undifferentiated inclusion, but for a set
of procedural mechanisms, institutions, and practices that are more likely
to expand the range of voices heard or considered, thereby creating more
opportunities to forge a common social space than either sovereigntist
territorialism or universalism.
38
In that sense, the vision I pursue here is
at least partly indebted to the proceduralist vision of J ü rgen Habermas
39
and can perhaps be embraced or criticized on similar grounds.
Chapter 2 begins by providing several illustrative examples of jur-
isdictional hybridity, where multiple legal norms of international, state,
substate, and nonstate entities may overlap. I also introduce literature on
legal pluralism and argue that pluralism provides a helpful framework
for understanding a hybrid world where normative assertions of multiple
entities – both state and nonstate – compete for primacy.
Chapters 3 and 4 then consider the two most common responses
we see in the legal arena to the sort of hybridity described in Chapter
2: sovereigntist territorialism and universalism. While each of these
approaches may sometimes be deemed necessary and may sometimes
be useful in addressing overlapping norms, I argue that they have serious
shortcomings. First, as a normative matter both sovereigntist territorial-
ism and universalism retreat from the potential bene ts of cosmopolitan
pluralism by limiting the range of norms considered and the range of
voices at the table. This may be a problem in and of itself because enter-
taining plural points of view within a procedural or institutional struc-
ture may carry independent bene ts of inclusion, diversity, creativity,
38
This focus on jurisgenerative structure, rather than on the necessary inclusion of, or
deference to, all points of view, may differentiate legal pluralism as I use it here from
multiculturalism.
39
See generally Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse
Theory of Law and Democracy (trans. William Rehg, 1996).
INTRODUCTION 19
and dialogue that go beyond the outcome reached. And, of course, the
outcome reached may also ultimately be more creative and more effec-
tive because of the diversity of input. Second, even if one is dubious
about the normative case for cosmopolitan pluralism, I argue that, as a
descriptive matter, neither sovereigntist territorialism nor universalism
will actually be a fully effective response to a world of legal assertions
beyond borders, and therefore a broader and more  exible framework
will often be necessary simply to cope with the messy reality of law on
the ground.
Chapters 5 and 6 lay out the core principles that undergird a cos-
mopolitan pluralist approach and then describe a variety of procedural
mechanisms, institutional designs, and discursive practices already at
play in the world that take such an approach. Although each of these
examples can be subjected to criticism on a variety of grounds, they do at
least attempt to build structures that seek to manage, without eliminat-
ing, pluralism.
Finally, Chapters 7 through 9 address the knotty doctrines known in
the United States as con ict of laws, though sometimes referred to else-
where as private international law. These doctrines attempt to negotiate
the interaction of communities by delineating jurisdictional boundaries,
determining which communities’ norms should apply to multicommunity
disputes, and analyzing the circumstances under which one community
might enforce the judgment reached by another community. As such, these
doctrines are potentially fundamental areas for employing a cosmopol-
itan pluralist frame to the legal negotiation of difference. Yet, too often
con ict of laws is relegated to a technocratic process of trying to forge
rules that will clarify boundaries and render only one community or one
set of norms legitimate or dominant. I argue instead that these doctrines
should engage interdisciplinary scholars of law and globalization and
that they offer a potential site for creative thinking about the interaction
of norms. And, although as noted previously my aim throughout the book
is to suggest a conceptual approach not to provide doctrinal answers, I do
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM20
offer a few illustrative examples of how each of these con icts doctrines
might be affected by a cosmopolitan pluralist framework.
One nal potential criticism of the book should perhaps be addressed
at the outset. In the oft-discussed scholarly divide between “lumpers”
and “splitters,
40
I am clearly a “lumper. That is, I offer here a highly syn-
thetic account that draws ties among a wide variety of different doctrines
and lumps together a variety of different scholarly positions into broader
categories. As such, I can rightly be criticized for eliding potentially
important distinctions and grouping together phenomena or perspec-
tives that are quite different from each other. For example, I treat sov-
ereigntist territorialism as a single perspective, even though it represents
a wide variety of positions, some of which focus more on nation-state
sovereignty, while others focus more on territorial approaches to con ict
of laws, and so on. Yet, despite some obvious problems, I believe lumping
nevertheless serves valuable purposes. By grouping together categories
of thought and legal doctrines that are traditionally treated as distinct, we
may be able to recognize broader patterns, make connections, and iden-
tify innovations that might otherwise have been opaque. Most import-
antly, while splitting is particularly useful for exploring  ne distinctions
with precision once a paradigm has been established, lumping can help
foster the creative imaginings that make new paradigms possible. In any
event, while both approaches are valuable and necessary, this book is
dedicated to sparking broad-based creative thinking about a world of
law beyond borders and therefore lumps concepts together, with all the
advantages and disadvantages such an approach entails.
True to that lumping spirit, the book seeks to engage scholars from a
wide variety of  elds, including those in anthropology, sociology, cultural
studies, international relations, and critical geography, as well as legal
scholars studying Internet law, international business, trade and  nance,
40
See George Gaylord Simpson, The Principles of Classi cation and a Classi cation
of Mammals, 85 Bulletin of the American Museum of Natural History 1, 23, (1945)
(“Splitters [see] very small units . . . . Lumpers [see] only large units . . ..”) (alterations in
original).
INTRODUCTION 21
public international law, and con ict of laws. I also hope to contribute to
ongoing debates about the ef cacy of international law, changing struc-
tures of sovereignty, and cosmopolitan theory. I argue that rational choice
understandings of how international law works or pure theory debates
about sovereignty are limited because they focus too heavily on coercive
power, thereby deemphasizing the role of rhetorical persuasion, informal
articulations of legal norms, changes in legal consciousness, and networks
of af liation that may not possess literal enforcement power. Accordingly,
my invocation of “law beyond borders” refers not only to the assertion of
norms across territorial borders, but also the fact that legal articulations
often function “beyond” the supposed conceptual borders between law
on the one hand and political rhetoric on the other.
41
And if, as discussed
previously, cosmopolitanism is de ned not as universalism but as an
acknowledgment of multiple af liation and a call for conversation across
difference, then this book also explores law as a crucial potential site for
cosmopolitan dialogue.
In all of this discussion, I emphasize a cultural analysis of law, which
argues that law both re ects and constructs social reality. This is, of course,
not the only way of understanding how law operates. For example, one
might think law is simply about constructing simple, easily de ned rules
that promote ef ciency and predictability, regardless of how they re ect
social reality. Yet, even if such an impulse is part of the web of ratio-
nales underlying legal rules, I believe it does not capture the rich reality
of how law operates in relation to social life. Indeed, a simple formalist
rule that fails to accord with social reality and lived experience tends
to be replaced over time, rst by what are known as legal  ctions and
then by new legal norms. For example, as discussed in more detail in
Chapter 3, very clear, simple nineteenth-century jurisdictional rules that
depended on physical presence in a territorial location could not cope
with the changed social reality wrought by advances in transportation
41
See Koskenniemi, supra note 31, at 69 (“Before any meaningful attempt at reform . . .
the idea of legal objectivity – and with it the conventional distinction between law, pol-
itics and morality (justice) needs to be rethought.”).
GLOBAL LEGAL PLURALISM22
and communications technologies and the resulting shifts in how corpora-
tions and governments operated and how people increasingly lived their
lives. Accordingly, those jurisdictional rules were altered, rst, through
somewhat strained judicially created notions of what constitutes “pres-
ence in a location and then by a completely new legal regime for con-
ceptualizing jurisdiction that shifted the focus away from simple physical
presence. Thus, I start from the premise that social reality matters in legal
discussions and that a more culturally based analytical framework should
at least be an important part of our discussions of how to conceptualize
law and globalization.
Ultimately, by studying the many local settings in which the norms of
multiple communities – geographical, ethnic, national, and epistemic –
become operative, scholars can gain a far more nuanced understanding
of the international and transnational legal terrain. This is a world in
which claims to coercive power, abstract notions of legitimacy, and argu-
ments about legal authority are only part of an ongoing conversation,
not the  nal determining factors. It is a world where “jurisgenerative
practices proliferate, creating opportunities for contestation and creative
adaptation.
42
And though we may not like all the norms being articulated
at any given moment, it will do no good to ignore them or insist on their
lack of authority. In a hybrid world, law is an ongoing process of articu-
lation, adaptation, rearticulation, absorption, resistance, deployment, and
on and on. It is a process that never ends, and scholars and policy makers
would do well to study the multiplicity and engage in the conversation,
rather than impose a top-down framework that cannot help but distort
the astonishing variety on the ground.
42
See id. at 556, 596–9 (embracing international legal discourse as a space for “open pol-
itical con ict and constant institutional revision”).