AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
Aesthetics and the Environment: The Appreciation of Nature, Art and Architecture
presents fresh and fascinating insights into our interpretation of the environment.
Although traditional aesthetics is often associated with the appreciation of art, Allen
Carlson shows how much of our aesthetic experience does not encompass art but
nature, in our responses to sunsets, mountains, or more mundane surroundings,
such as gardens or the views from our windows. He demonstrates that, unlike works
of art, natural and ordinary human environments are neither self-contained
aesthetic objects nor specifically designed for convenient aesthetic consumption. On
the contrary, our environments are ever present constantly engaging our senses, and
Carlson offers a thought-provoking and lucid investigation of what this means for
our appreciation of the world around us. He argues that knowledge of what it is we
are appreciating is essential to having an appropriate aesthetic experience and that
scientific understanding of nature can enhance our appreciation of it, rather than
denigrate it.
Aesthetics and the Environment also shows how ethical and aesthetic values are
closely connected, argues that aesthetic appreciation of natural and human
environments has objective grounding, and explores the important links between
ecology and the aesthetic experience of nature. This book will be essential reading
for those involved in environmental studies and aesthetics and all who are interested
in the controversial relationship between science and nature.
Allen Carlson is an authority in aesthetics and has pioneered the field of
environmental aesthetics. He is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Alberta,
Canada.
AESTHETICS AND THE
ENVIRONMENT
The appreciation of nature, art and
architecture
Allen Carlson
London and New York
First published 2000
by Routledge
11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group
This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005.
“To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of
thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.”
© 2000 Allen Carlson
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced
or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means,
now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and
recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without
permission in writing from the publishers.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available
from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Carlson, Allen
Aesthetics and the environment: the appreciation of nature, art and
architecture/Allen Carlson
p. cm.
“Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada”
Includes bibliographical references and index
1. Environment (Aesthetics)
BH301.E58C37 1999 99–28959
111.85–dc21 CIP
ISBN 0-203-99502-3 Master e-book ISBN
ISBN 0-415-20683-9 (Print Edition)
FOR ARLENE, ELEANOR AND VIRGINIA
CONTENTS
List of illustrations ix
Preface x
Acknowledgements xi
Introduction: aesthetics and the environment xii
PART I The appreciation of nature 1
1 The aesthetics of nature 3
A brief historical overview 3
A brief overview of contemporary positions 5
The natural environmental model: some further ramifications 11
Notes 13
2 Understanding and aesthetic experience 17
Aesthetic experience on the Mississippi 17
Formalism and aesthetic experience 19
Disinterestedness and aesthetic experience 24
Conclusion 27
Notes 27
3 Formal qualities in the natural environment 29
Formal qualities and formalism 29
Formal qualities in current work in environmental aesthetics 30
Background on the significance assigned to formal qualities 31
Formal qualities in the natural environment 34
Conclusion 38
Notes 39
4 Appreciation and the natural environment 41
The appreciation of art 41
Some artistic models for the appreciation of nature 42
An environmental model for the appreciation of nature 47
Conclusion 51
Notes 51
5 Nature, aesthetic judgment, and objectivity 55
Nature and objectivity 55
Walton’s position 56
Nature and culture 58
Nature and Walton’s psychological claim 60
The correct categories of nature 63
Conclusion 68
Notes 69
6 Nature and positive aesthetics 73
The development of positive aesthetics 73
Nature appreciation as non-aesthetic 76
Positive aesthetics and sublimity 79
Positive aesthetics and theism 82
Science and aesthetic appreciation of nature 85
Science and appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature 88
Science and positive aesthetics 91
Notes 95
7 Appreciating art and appreciating nature
103
The concept of appreciation 103
Appreciating art: design appreciation 108
Appreciating art: order appreciation 110
Appreciating nature: design appreciation 115
Appreciating nature: order appreciation 118
vi
Conclusion 122
Notes 123
PART II Landscapes, art, and architecture 127
8 Between nature and art 129
The question of aesthetic relevance 129
Objects of appreciation and aesthetic necessity 131
Between nature and art: appreciating other things 133
Notes 135
9 Environmental aesthetics and the dilemma of aesthetic
education
139
The eyesore argument 139
The dilemma of aesthetic education 140
The natural 141
The aesthetically pleasing 143
Life values and the eyesore argument 144
Conclusion 147
Notes 148
10 Is environmental art an aesthetic affront to nature? 151
Environmental works of art 151
Environmental art as an aesthetic affront 153
Some replies to the affront charge 156
Some concluding examples 159
Notes 162
11 The aesthetic appreciation of Japanese gardens 165
The dialectical nature of Japanese gardens
165
The appreciative paradox of Japanese gardens 168
Conclusion 172
Notes 173
12 Appreciating agricultural landscapes 177
vii
Traditional agricultural landscapes 177
The new agricultural landscapes 179
Difficult aesthetic appreciation and novelty 184
Appreciating the new agricultural landscapes 187
Conclusion 190
Notes 191
13 Existence, location, and function: the appreciation of
architecture
197
Architecture and art 197
To be or not to be: Hamlet and Tolstoy 199
Here I stand: to fit or not to fit 203
Form follows function and fit follows function 208
Function, location, existence: the path of appreciation 212
Notes 215
14 Landscape and literature 219
Hillerman’s landscapes and aesthetic relevance 219
Classic formalism and postmodern landscape appreciation 221
Formal descriptions and ordinary descriptions 222
Other factual landscape descriptions 224
The analogy with art argument 226
Nominal descriptions 228
Imaginative descriptions and cultural embeddedness 230
Mythological landscape descriptions 232
Literary landscape descriptions 235
The analogy with art argument again 237
Conclusion 239
Notes 240
Index 243
viii
ILLUSTRATIONS
1 Peacock Skirt, by Aubrey Beardsley (1894) 22
2 The Grand Tetons, Wyoming 56
3 Asphalt Rundown, by Robert Smithson (1969), Rome 154
4 Time Landscape, by Alan Sonfist (1965–78), New York City 162
5 Willow in the Japanese garden, Portland 171
6 A traditional farmstead, Minnesota 180
7 The new agricultural landscape, Saskatchewan 180
8 Autumn Foliage, by Tom Thomson (1916) 198
9 The AT&T Building, by Philip Johnson/John Burgee (1980–83), New
York City
200
10 Ship Rock and the Long Black Ridges, New Mexico 235
PREFACE
The material in this volume spans a period of roughly twenty years and reflects my
continuing interest in the aesthetics of the environment.
A number of the chapters of the volume have been previously published as essays
in books or journals. Except for slight changes required to make corrections,
eliminate redundancies, or indicate connections, these essays are reprinted much as
they initially appeared. I have elected this alternative both because it best maintains
the integrity and quality of the individual pieces and because I think that even in
their original form, the essays come together to constitute a unified line of thought.
The introductory chapters for the two parts of the volume, Chapters 1 and 8,
present overviews and help to further unify the material. Moreover, the notes for
these two chapters provide extensive cross-referencing among the remaining
chapters and position them within the current literature in the field. In addition to
Chapters 1 and 8, two other chapters, Chapters 2 and 14, have not previously
appeared in print.
Allen Carlson
Edmonton, Canada, 1998
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I acknowledge and thank the editors and the publishers of the following books and
journals for permission to use material that originally appeared in them: For portions
of the general Introduction and of Chapter 1, by permission of, respectively, Basil
Blackwell, Routledge, and Oxford University Press, D. Cooper (ed.) A Companion
to Aesthetics, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1992, pp. 142–4; E.Craig (ed.) The Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London, Routledge, 1998, vol. 6, pp. 731–5; and
M.Kelly (ed.) The Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, New York, Oxford University Press,
1998, vol. 3, pp. 346–9. For Chapters 3 and 9, by permission of the University of
Illinois Press, The Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1979, vol. 13, pp. 99–114 and
1976, vol. 10, pp. 69–82. For Chapters 4, 5, and 12, by permission of the
University of Wisconsin Press, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1979, vol.
37, pp. 267–76; 1981, vol. 40, pp. 15–27, and 1985, vol. 43, pp. 301–12. For
Chapter 6, by permission of Environmental Philosophy, Inc., Environmental Ethics,
1984, vol. 6, pp. 5–34. For Chapter 7, by permission of Cambridge University
Press, S.Kemal and I.Gaskell (eds) Landscape, Nature Beauty and the Arts,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 199–227. For Chapter 10, by
permission of the University of Calgary Press, The Canadian Journal of Philosophy,
1986, vol. 16, pp. 635–50. For Chapter 11, by permission of Oxford University
Press, The British Journal of Aesthetics, 1997, vol. 37, pp. 47–56. For Chapter 13, by
permission of Editions Rodopi B.V., M.Mitias (ed.) Philosophy and Architecture,
Amsterdam, Rodopi, 1994, pp. 141–64.
I also express my appreciation to the following by the courtesy of whom it was
possible to include illustrations 2, 3, 4, 8, and 9: respectively, Corbis/ Ansel Adams
Publishing Rights Trust, The John Weber Gallery, Alan Sonfist, The National
Gallery of Canada, and American Telephone and Telegraph.
I thank the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada and the
University of Alberta for financial support for the writing of some of the material in
this volume.
I also thank my editors at Routledge for their assistance and advice.
Above all, I thank and express my appreciation to my friends and acquaintances
in the discipline, to my colleagues in the Department of Philosophy at the
University of Alberta, and to the members of my family for their support and
encouragement.
INTRODUCTION
Aesthetics and the environment
What is “environmental aesthetics”?
Aesthetics is the area of philosophy that concerns our appreciation of things as they
affect our senses, and especially as they affect them in a pleasing way. As such it
frequently focuses primarily on the fine arts, the products of which are traditionally
designed to please our senses. However, much of our aesthetic appreciation is not
confined to art, but directed toward the world at large. We appreciate not only art,
but also nature—broad horizons, fiery sunsets, and towering mountains. Moreover,
our appreciation reaches beyond pristine nature to our more mundane
surroundings: the solitude of a neighborhood park on a rainy evening, the chaos of a
bustling morning marketplace, the view from the road. Thus, there is a need for an
aesthetics of the environment, for in such cases our aesthetic appreciation
encompasses our surroundings: our environment. The environment may be more or
less natural, large or small, mundane or exotic, but in each such case it is an
environment that we appreciate. Such appreciation is the subject matter of
environmental aesthetics.
The nature of environmental aesthetics
The fact that the focus of aesthetic appreciation is an environment signals several
important dimensions of such appreciation which in turn determine the nature of
environmental aesthetics. The first of these dimensions follows from the very fact
that the object of appreciation, the “aesthetic object,” is our environment, our
surroundings. Thus, we as appreciators are immersed within the object of our
appreciation. This fact has a number of ramifications: not only are we in what we
appreciate but what we appreciate is also that from which we appreciate. If we
move, we move within the object of our appreciation and thereby change our
relationship to it and at the same time change the object itself. Moreover, since it is
our surroundings, the object of appreciation impinges upon all our senses. As we
occupy it or move through it, we see, hear, feel, smell, and perhaps even taste it. In
short, the experience of the environmental object of appreciation from which
aesthetic appreciation must be fashioned is initially intimate, total, and engulfing.
These dimensions of our experience are intensified by the unruly and chaotic
nature of the object of appreciation itself. It is not the more or less discrete, stable,
and self-contained object of traditional art, but rather an environment.
Consequently, not only does it change as we move within it, it changes of its own
accord. Environments are constantly in motion, in both the short and long term. If
we remain motionless, the wind yet brushes our face and the clouds yet pass before
our eyes. And with time changes continue without limit: night falls, days pass,
seasons come and go. Moreover, environments not only move through time, they
extend through space, and again without limit. There are no boundaries for our
environment; as we move, it moves with us and changes, but does not end. Indeed,
it continues unending in every direction. In other words, the environmental object
of appreciation is not “framed” as are traditional works of art, neither in time as are
dramatical works or musical compositions nor in space as are paintings or
sculptures.
These differences between environments and traditional artistic objects relate to a
deeper difference between the two. Works of art are the products of artists. The
artist is quintessentially a designer, creating a work by embodying a design in an
object. Thus, works of art are tied to their designers both causally and conceptually:
what a work is and what it means follows from its designer and its design. However,
environments typically are not the products of designers and typically have no
design. Rather they come about “naturally,” they change, grow, and develop by
means of natural processes. Or they come about by means of human agency, but
even then only rarely are they the result of a designer embodying a design. In short,
the paradigm of the environmental object of appreciation is unruly in yet another
way: neither its nature nor its meaning are determined by a designer and a design.
The upshot is that in our aesthetic appreciation of the world at large we are
confronted by, if not intimately and totally engulfed in, something that forces itself
upon all our senses, is constantly in motion, is limited neither in time nor in space,
and is constrained concerning neither its nature nor its meaning. We are immersed
in a potential object of appreciation and our task is to achieve aesthetic appreciation
of that object. Moreover, the appreciation must be fashioned anew, with neither the
aid of frames, the guidance of designs, nor the direction of designers. Thus, in our
aesthetic appreciation of the world at large we must begin with the most basic
questions, those of exactly what to aesthetically appreciate and how to appreciate it.
These questions set the agenda for environmental aesthetics; the field essentially
concerns the issue of what resources, if any, are available for answering them.
The two basic orientations in environmental aesthetics
The questions of what and how to aesthetically appreciate in an environment
generate a number of different approaches, but at the most fundamental level two
main points of view can be identified. The first may be characterized as subjectivist
or perhaps as skeptical. In essence, it holds that since in the appreciation of
environments we seemingly lack the resources normally involved in aesthetic
xiii
appreciation, these questions cannot be properly answered. In other words, since we
lack resources such as frames, designs, and designers as well as the guidance they
provide, then we must embrace either subjectivism or skepticism: either there is no
appropriate or correct aesthetic appreciation of environments or such appreciation
as there is, is not real aesthetic appreciation. Concerning the world at large, as
opposed to works of art, the closest we come to appropriate aesthetic appreciation is
simply to open ourselves to being immersed, respond as we will, and enjoy what we
can. And the question of whether or not the resultant experience is appropriate in
some sense, or even aesthetic in any sense, is not of any importance.
A second basic point of view may be characterized as objectivist. In essence, it
argues that, in addressing the what and how questions, there are in fact two
resources to draw upon: the appreciator and the object of appreciation. Thus, roles
that are played in the appreciation of traditional art objects by designer and design
must be played in the aesthetic appreciation of an environment by either or both of
these two resources. In such appreciation the role of designer is typically taken up by
the appreciator and that of design by the object. In other words, in our aesthetic
appreciation of the world at large we as appreciators typically play the role of artist
and let the world provide us with something like a design. Thus, when confronted
by an environment, we select the senses relevant to its appreciation and set the
frames that limit it in time and space. Moreover, as designer plays off against design,
so too in selecting and setting we play off against the nature of the environment we
confront. In this way the environment by its own nature provides the analogue of a
design—we might say it provides its own design. Thus, it offers the necessary
guidance in light of which we, by our selecting and setting, can appropriately
answer the questions of what and how to appreciate. We thereby fashion our
initially engulfing if not overwhelming experience of an environment into appropriate
and genuine aesthetic appreciation.
In disputes between subjectivist or skeptical positions and more objectivist ones,
the burden of proof typically falls on the latter. To make its case, the objectivist
account must be elaborated and supported by arguments and examples. The basic
idea of the objectivist point of view is that our appreciation is guided by the nature
of the object of appreciation. Thus, information about the object’s nature, about its
genesis, type, and properties, is necessary for appropriate aesthetic appreciation. For
example, in appreciating a natural environment such as an alpine meadow, it is
important to know, for instance, that it survives under constraints imposed by the
climate of high altitude. With such knowledge comes the understanding that
diminutive size in flora is an adaptation to such constraints. This knowledge and
understanding guides our framing of the environment so that, for example, we avoid
imposing inappropriately large frames, which may cause us simply to overlook
miniature wild flowers. In such a case we might neither appreciatively note their
remarkable adjustment to their situation nor attune our senses to their subtle
fragrance, texture, and hue. Similarly, in appreciating human-altered environments
such as those of modern agriculture, knowledge about, for example, the functional
utility of cultivating huge fields devoted to single crops is aesthetically relevant. Such
xiv
knowledge encourages us to enlarge and adjust our frames, our senses, and even our
attitudes. As a result we may more appreciatively accommodate the vast uniform
landscapes that are the inevitable result of such farming practices.
The scope of environmental aesthetics
Whether they endorse a subjectivist or an objectivist point of view, both basic
orientations in environmental aesthetics recognize the array of special problems that
confronts the field. Similarly, both recognize the expansive scope of the field itself.
The scope may be characterized in terms of three continuums.
On the first, the subject matter of environmental aesthetics stretches from
pristine nature to the very limits of the most traditional art forms, and by some
accounts even expands to include the latter. On this continuum the things treated
by environmental aesthetics range from wilderness areas, through rural landscapes
and countrysides, to cityscapes, neighborhoods, market places, shopping centers,
and beyond. Thus, within the genus of environmental aesthetics fall a number of
different species, such as the aesthetics of nature, landscape aesthetics, the aesthetics
of cityscapes and urban design, and perhaps the aesthetics of architecture, if not that
of art itself.
The second continuum in terms of which the scope of environmental aesthetics
may be characterized ranges over size. Many environments that are typical objects of
our aesthetic appreciation, especially those that surround and threaten to engulf us,
are very large: a dense old growth forest, a seemingly endless field of wheat, the
downtown of a big city. But environmental aesthetics also focuses on smaller and
more intimate environments, such as our backyard, our office, and our living room.
And perhaps the scope extends even to diminutive environments, such as we may
encounter when we turn over a rock or when traveling with a microscope into a
drop of pond water. Such tiny environments, although not physically surrounding,
are yet totally engaging.
The third continuum is closely related to the second. It ranges from the
extraordinary to the ordinary, from the exotic to the mundane. Just as
environmental aesthetics is not limited to the large, it is likewise not limited to the
spectacular. Ordinary scenery, commonplace sights, and our day-to-day experiences
are also proper objects of aesthetic appreciation. As such they not only fall under the
scope of environmental aesthetics, but also, in light of becoming objects of aesthetic
appreciation, hopefully become somewhat less ordinary.
In spite of the expansive scope of environmental aesthetics, a basic assumption of
the field is that every environment, natural, rural, or urban, large or small, ordinary
or extraordinary, offers much to see, to hear, to feel, much to aesthetically
appreciate. In short, the different environments of the world at large are as
aesthetically rich and rewarding as are works of art. Nonetheless, there are, as noted,
special issues in aesthetic appreciation posed by the very nature of environments, by
the fact that they are our surroundings, that they are unruly and chaotic objects of
appreciation, and that we are plunged into them without appreciative guidelines.
xv
The chapters that follow embrace this basic assumption and recognize these special
issues. They address the issues from an objectivist point of view.
xvi
Part I
THE APPRECIATION OF NATURE
2
1
THE AESTHETICS OF NATURE
A brief historical overview
In the Western world there has been since antiquity a tradition of viewing art as the
mirror of nature. However, the idea of aesthetically appreciating nature itself is
sometimes traced to a less ancient origin: Petrarch’s novel passion for climbing
mountains simply to enjoy the prospect. Yet even if the aesthetic appreciation of
nature only dates from the dawn of the Renaissance, its development from that time
to the present has been uneven and episodic. Initially, nature’s appreciation as well
as its philosophical investigation were hamstrung by religion. The reigning religious
tradition could not but deem nature an unworthy object of aesthetic appreciation,
for it saw mountains as despised heaps of wreckage left by the flood, wilderness
regions as fearful places for punishment and repentance, and all of nature’s workings
as poor substitutes for the perfect harmony lost in humanity’s fall. It took the rise of
a secular science and equally secular art forms to free nature from such associations
and thereby open it for aesthetic appreciation. Thus, in the Western world the
evolution of aesthetic appreciation of nature has been intertwined with both the
objectification of nature achieved by science and the subjectification of it rendered
by art.
Although the scientific objectification of nature had earlier origins, the
connection between aesthetic appreciation of nature and scientific objectivity dates
from early in the eighteenth century. At that time, British aestheticians initiated a
tradition that gave theoretical expression to this connection. Empiricist thinkers,
such as Joseph Addison and Francis Hutcheson, took nature rather than art as the
ideal object of aesthetic experience and developed the notion of disinterestedness as
the mark of such experience. In the course of the century, this notion was elaborated
such as to exclude from aesthetic experience an ever-increasing range of associations
and conceptualizations. Thus, the objects of appreciation favored by this tradition,
British landscapes, were, by means of disinterested aesthetic appreciation, eventually
severed not only from religious associations, but from any appreciator’s personal,
moral, and economic interests. The upshot was a mode of aesthetic appreciation
that looked upon the natural world with an eye not unlike the distancing,
objectifying eye of science. In this way, the tradition laid the groundwork for the
idea of the sublime. By means of the sublime even the most threatening of nature’s
manifestations, such as mountains and wilderness, could be distanced and
appreciated, rather than simply feared and despised.
However, the notion of disinterestedness not only laid the groundwork for the
sublime, it also cleared the ground for another, quite different idea, that of the
picturesque. This idea secured the connection between aesthetic appreciation of
nature and the subjective renderings of nature in art. The term “picturesque
literally means “picture-like” and indicates a mode of appreciation by which the
natural world is divided into artistic scenes. Such scenes aim in subject matter or in
composition at ideals dictated by the arts, especially poetry and landscape painting.
Thus, while disinterestedness and the sublime stripped and objectified nature, the
picturesque dressed it in a new set of subjective and romantic images: a rugged cliff
with a ruined castle, a deep valley with an arched bridge, a barren outcropping with
a crofter’s cottage. Like disinterestedness and the sublime, the picturesque had its
roots in the theories of the early eighteenth century aestheticians, such as Addison,
who thought that what he called the “works of nature” were more appealing when
they resembled works of art. However, picturesque appreciation did not culminate
until later in the century when it was popularized primarily by William Gilpin and
Uvedale Price. At that time, it became the reigning aesthetic ideal of English tourists
who pursued picturesque scenery in the Lake District and the Scottish Highlands.
Indeed, the picturesque remains the mode of aesthetic appreciation associated with
the form of tourism that sees and appreciates the natural world primarily in light of
renderings of nature typical of travel brochures, calendar photos, and picture
postcards.
After the close of the eighteenth century, the picturesque lingered on as a popular
mode of aesthetic appreciation of nature. However, the philosophical study of the
aesthetics of nature, after the flowering of that century, went into steady decline.
Many of the main ideas, such as the idea of the sublime, the notion of
disinterestedness, and the theoretical centrality of nature rather than art, reached
their climax with Kant. In his third critique some of these ideas received such
exhaustive treatment that a kind of closure was seemingly achieved. Following Kant,
a new world order was initiated by Hegel. In this world, art was a means to the
Absolute, and it rather than nature was destined to became the favored subject of
philosophical aesthetics.
However, even as the theoretical study of the aesthetics of nature declined, a new
view of nature was initiated that eventually gave rise to a different kind of aesthetic
appreciation. This mode of appreciation has its roots in the North American
tradition of nature writing, as exemplified by Henry David Thoreau. In the middle
of the nineteenth century, it was reinforced by the work of George Perkins Marsh
and his recognition that humanity is the major cause of the destruction of nature’s
beauty. It achieved its classic realization at the end of the century with American
naturalist John Muir. Muir saw all nature and especially wild nature as aesthetically
beautiful and found ugliness only where nature was subject to human intrusion.
4 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
These ideas strongly influenced the North American wilderness preservation
movement and continue to shape the aesthetic appreciation of nature associated
with contemporary environmentalism. This kind of appreciation may be called
positive aesthetics.
1
In so far as positive aesthetic appreciation eschews humanity’s
marks on the natural landscape, it is somewhat the converse of picturesque
appreciation with its delight in signs of human presence. Thus, it has become the
rival of the picturesque as the popular mode of aesthetic appreciation of nature,
although contemporary nature appreciation frequently involves a somewhat uneasy
balance between the two different modes.
In spite of the developments in popular appreciation of nature in the nineteenth
and twentieth century, however, philosophical aesthetics, with few exceptions,
ignored nature throughout most of this period. In the nineteenth century Schelling
and a scattering of thinkers of the Romantic Movement considered the aesthetics of
nature to some extent, and in the first half of the twentieth century George
Santayana and John Dewey each discussed it. But, by and large, in so far as
aesthetics was pursued, it was completely dominated by an interest in art. Thus, by
the mid-twentieth century, within the analytic tradition, philosophical aesthetics
was virtually equated with philosophy of art. The major textbook in aesthetics at
this time was subtitled Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism and major aesthetics
anthologies bore titles such as Art and Philosophy and Philosophy Looks at the Arts.
2
Moreover, when aesthetic appreciation of nature was mentioned, it was treated, by
comparison with that of art, as a messy, subjective business of little philosophical
significance. However, in the second half of the twentieth century this situation was
destined to change.
A brief overview of contemporary positions
Many of the issues in contemporary work on the aesthetics of nature are foreshadowed
in one article: Ronald W. Hepburn’s seminal “Contemporary Aesthetics and the
Neglect of Natural Beauty.
3
After noting that by essentially reducing aesthetics to
the philosophy of art, analytic aesthetics virtually ignores the natural world,
Hepburn sets the agenda for the discussion of the late twentieth century. He argues
that aesthetic appreciation of art frequently provides misleading guidelines for our
appreciation of nature. Yet he observes that there is in the aesthetic appreciation of
nature, as in appreciation of art, a distinction between appreciation which is only
trivial and superficial and that which is serious and deep. He furthermore suggests
that with nature such serious appreciation may require different approaches that can
accommodate not only nature’s indeterminate and varying character, but also both
our multi-sensory experience and our diverse understanding of it.
The contemporary discussion of the aesthetics of nature thus stresses different
approaches to or models for the appreciation of nature: models intended to capture
the essence of appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature. Certain more traditional
models that are rather directly related to the aesthetic appreciation of the arts are
seemingly inadequate. Two such models may be called the object model and the
THE AESTHETICS OF NATURE 5
landscape model. The former pushes nature in the direction of sculpture and the
latter treats it as similar to landscape painting. Thus, the object model focuses
aesthetic appreciation primarily on natural objects and dictates appreciation of such
objects rather as we might appreciate pieces of abstract sculpture, mentally or
physically extracting them from their contexts and dwelling on their formal
properties. On the other hand, the landscape model, following in the tradition of
the picturesque noted in the first section of this chapter, mandates appreciation of
nature as we might appreciate a landscape painting. This requires seeing it to some
extent as a two-dimensional scene and again dwelling largely on formal properties.
Neither of these models fully realize serious, appropriate appreciation of nature for
each distorts the true character of nature. The former rips natural objects from their
larger environments while the latter frames and flattens them into scenery.
Moreover, in focusing mainly on formal properties, both models neglect much of
our normal experience and understanding of nature.
4
Although the aesthetic appreciation of the arts does not directly provide adequate
models for the appreciation of nature, it yet suggests some of what is required in a
more adequate model. In serious, appropriate aesthetic appreciation of works of art,
it is essential that we appreciate works as what they in fact are and in light of
knowledge of their real natures. Thus, for instance, serious, appropriate aesthetic
appreciation of the Guernica (1937) requires that we appreciate it as a painting and
moreover as a cubist or neo-cubist painting, and therefore that we appreciate it in
light of our knowledge of paintings in general and of cubist paintings in particular.
This suggests a third model for the aesthetic appreciation of nature, the natural
environmental model. This model, which I develop throughout Part I of this
volume, recommends two things. First, that, as in our appreciation of works of art,
we must appreciate nature as what it in fact is, that is, as natural and as an environment.
Second, it recommends that we must appreciate nature in light of our knowledge of
what it is, that is, in light of knowledge provided by the natural sciences, especially
the environmental sciences such as geology, biology, and ecology. The natural
environmental model thus accommodates both the true character of nature and our
normal experience and understanding of it.
5
Nonetheless, the natural environmental model may be thought not to
characterize our appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature completely accurately.
Although it does not, as the object and the landscape models, distort nature itself, it
may yet be thought to somewhat misrepresent our appreciation of nature. Its
emphasis on scientific knowledge gives such appreciation a highly cognitive and
what may be judged an overly intellectual quality. In contrast to the cognitive
emphasis of the natural environmental model, a fourth model, the engagement model,
stresses the contextual dimensions of nature and our multi-sensory experience of it.
Viewing the environment as a seamless unity of organisms, perceptions, and places,
the engagement model beckons us to immerse ourselves in our natural environment
in an attempt to obliterate traditional dichotomies such as subject and object, and
ultimately to reduce to as small a degree as possible the distance between ourselves
6 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
and nature. In short, aesthetic experience is taken to involve a total immersion of
the appreciator in the object of appreciation.
6
The engagement model calls for the absorption of the appreciator into the
natural environment. Perhaps in doing so it goes too far. There are two main
difficulties. First, in attempting to eliminate any distance between ourselves and
nature, the engagement model may lose that by reason of which the resultant
experience is aesthetic. As noted in the first section of this chapter, within the
Western tradition the very notion of the aesthetic is conceptually tied to
disinterestedness and the idea of distance between the appreciator and the
appreciated, The second difficulty is that in attempting to obliterate dichotomies
such as that between subject and object, the engagement model may also lose the
possibility of distinguishing between trivial, superficial appreciation and that which
is serious and appropriate. This is because serious, appropriate appreciation revolves
around the object of appreciation and its real nature, while superficial appreciation
frequently involves only whatever the subject happens to bring to the experience. In
short, without the subject/object distinction, aesthetic appreciation of nature is in
danger of degenerating into little more than a subjective flight of fancy.
Another view that also seems to diverge from the natural environmental model is
the arousal model. This model challenges the central place the natural
environmental model grants to scientific knowledge in aesthetic appreciation of
nature. The arousal model holds that we may appreciate nature simply by opening
ourselves to it and thus being emotionally aroused by it. The view contends that this
less intellectual, more visceral experience of nature is a way of legitimately
appreciating nature without involving any knowledge gained from science. Unlike
the engagement model, this model does not call for a total immersion in nature, but
only for an emotional relationship with it based on our common, everyday
knowledge and experience of it. Consequently, in contrast to the engagement
model, the arousal model does not lose the right to call its experience of nature
aesthetic. Nor does it undercut the distinction between trivial and serious
appreciation of nature, even though the appreciation it stresses may be more the
former than the latter. However, the contrast between the arousal model and the
natural environmental model is less clear. If we recognize our scientific knowledge
of the natural world as only a finer-grained and theoretically richer version of our
common, everyday knowledge of it, and not as something essentially different in
kind, then the difference between the arousal model and the natural environmental
model is mainly one of emphasis. Both models track the appreciation of nature,
although the arousal model focuses on the more common, less cognitively rich, and
perhaps less serious end of the continuum.
7
A more fundamental challenge to the natural environmental model comes from
what may be called the mystery model of nature appreciation. This view holds that
the natural environmental model, in requiring that we must have knowledge of
what we appreciate, has no place for the way in which nature is alien, aloof, distant,
and unknowable. It contends that the only appropriate experience of nature is a
sense of mystery involving a state of appreciative incomprehension, a sense of not
THE AESTHETICS OF NATURE 7
belonging to and of being separate from nature. However, the mystery model faces
major difficulties. With only mystery and aloofness, there seems to be no grounding
for appreciation of any kind, let alone aesthetic appreciation. The mystery and
aloofness of nature is a gulf, an emptiness, between us and nature; it is that by which
we are separate from nature. Thus, mystery itself cannot constitute a means by
which we can attain any appreciation of nature whatsoever. In short, insofar as
nature is unknowable, it is also beyond aesthetic appreciation. However, even
though mystery and aloofness cannot support appreciation, they can support
worship. Thus, perhaps the mystery model should be characterized not as an
aesthetic of nature, but rather as a religious approach to nature. If this is the case,
then rather than revealing a dimension of our appropriate aesthetic appreciation of
nature, the mystery model leaves the realm of the aesthetic altogether.
8
If the mystery model of nature appreciation moves such appreciation outside the
realm of the aesthetic, it does so unintentionally. However, the possibility that our
appreciation of nature is not aesthetic is expressly embraced as the central tenet of
the nonaesthetic model of nature appreciation. This view constitutes a radical
alternative to all other models in explicitly claiming that nature appreciation is not a
species of aesthetic appreciation. It holds that aesthetic appreciation is
paradigmatically appreciation of works of art and is minimally appreciation of
artifacts, of that which is human-made. Thus, in this view the appreciation of
nature itself cannot be aesthetic appreciation of any kind whatsoever.
9
However,
such a view is deeply problematic. The view finds some support in the tendency in
analytic aesthetics noted in the first section of this chapter, that is, the tendency to
reduce all of aesthetics to philosophy of art. Yet the view remains essentially
counterintuitive. Many of our fundamental paradigms of aesthetic appreciation are
instances of appreciation of nature, such as our appreciation of the radiance of a
glowing sunset, the grace of a bird in flight, or the simple beauty of a flower.
Moreover, the Western tradition in aesthetics, not to mention other traditions, such
as the Japanese, is committed to a doctrine that explicitly excludes the nonaesthetic
model of nature appreciation: the doctrine that, as one writer puts it, anything that
can be viewed can be viewed aesthetically.
10
There is nonetheless a grain of truth contained in the nonaesthetic model of
nature appreciation that is worth preserving. The nonaesthetic model makes a virtue
of what the mystery model encounters unintentionally: the fact that the more
removed, the more separate, something is from humankind and its artifactualization,
the more problematic is its aesthetic appreciation. The limiting case, inadvertently
illuminated by the mystery model, is the complete impossibility of aesthetically
appreciating the totally unknowable. The insight contained in the nonaesthetic
model is thus that some degree of artifactualization is necessary for aesthetic
appreciation. However, what this model fails to recognize is that our human
conceptualization and understanding of nature is itself a minimal form of
artifactualization. And although minimal, it is yet adequate to underwrite aesthetic
appreciation. To aesthetically appreciate the natural world, we do not need to
actually make it, as we make works of art; nor do we need to conceptualize it in
8 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
artistic categories, as is done by the object and landscape models. When we cast the
conceptual net of common-sense and scientific understanding over nature we do
enough to it to make possible its aesthetic appreciation. This fact lends support to
some other models, such as the natural environment model, for it suggests that
granting a special place in nature appreciation to at least our common-sense and
scientific knowledge of nature may be a necessary condition for providing an
adequate account of serious, appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature.
However, the realization that human conceptualization and understanding is a
form of artifactualization adequate for underwriting genuine aesthetic appreciation
of nature opens the door to further possibilities. The conceptual net of common-sense
and scientific understanding is not the only one we cast over nature. There are also
numerous other nets woven by human culture in its many forms—nets woven not
only by art, but also by literature, folklore, religion, and myth. This realization
suggests the possibility of what may be called a postmodern model of nature
appreciation. Such a view would compare nature to a text, contending that in
reading a text we appropriately appreciate not just the meaning its author intended,
but any of various meanings that it may have acquired or that we may find in it.
And, moreover, none of these possible meanings has priority; no reading of a text is
privileged. Thus, on such a postmodern model, whatever cultural significance
nature may have acquired and that we may find in it, the rich and varied deposits
from our art, literature, folklore, religion, and myth, would all be accepted as proper
dimensions of our aesthetic appreciation of nature. And of such dimensions none
would be given priority; no particular appreciation would be privileged as more
serious or more appropriate than any other.
11
The possibility of a postmodern model of nature appreciation focuses attention
on the many layers of human deposit that overlay pure nature. These layers range
from the thin film of common sense, through the rich stratum of science, to the
abundant accumulations of culture. In our encounters with nature we confront this
diversity and a postmodern model would eagerly welcome it all. In sharp contrast,
some other models, such as the engagement model and the mystery model, strive
toward attempting to appreciate pure, unadulterated nature, to look on nature bare,
as Euclid looked on beauty. But the nonaesthetic model demonstrates that to go too
far in this direction is to go beyond the realm of the aesthetic, making any aesthetic
appreciation of nature impossible. Nonetheless, contained in the purist’s inclination
is the antidote for the potential excesses of a postmodern model. To achieve a
balanced understanding of the situation, we must keep in mind that, as with
appreciation of art, serious appreciation of nature means appreciating it as what it in
fact is; and yet at the same time we must recognize that this also means appreciating
nature as what it is for us. This idea limits yet enriches what is involved in
appropriate aesthetic appreciation. Contra a postmodern model, it is not the case
that just any fanciful reverie we happen to bring to nature will do as well as anything
else; and contra the purist, nature is what it is for us, is what we have made of it. To
miss or deny this latter fact is to miss or deny much of the richness that serious,
appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature has to offer.
THE AESTHETICS OF NATURE 9
The idea that nature is what it is for us, is what we have made of it, widens the
scope of appropriate aesthetic appreciation, but it also constrains any view such as a
postmodern model. In part this is because neither nature nor we are one unitary
thing. It follows that not all of humankind’s cultural deposit is aesthetically
significant either to all parts of nature or for all of humankind. For any particular
part of nature and for any particular appreciator, some of the cultural overlay is
relevant, is indeed necessary for serious appreciation, while much of it is not, is
indeed little better than fanciful daydreams. In light of this, perhaps what might be
called a pluralist model of nature appreciation should supplant a postmodern
model. A pluralist model would accept the diversity and the richness of the cultural
overlay in which a postmodern model delights. However, such a model would also
recognise, first, that for any particular part of nature only a small part of that
cultural overlay is really relevant to serious, appropriate appreciation, and, second,
that for any particular appreciator only a small part of the overlay can truly be
claimed as his or her own. A pluralist model would endorse diversity, but yet would
hold that in appropriate aesthetic appreciation, not all nature either can or should
be all things to all human beings.
12
Although a pluralist model would thus restrict the role of our cultural overlay in
appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature, any such restriction need not apply
equally to all layers of the human deposit. Perhaps the more basic layers, those of
common sense and science, are dimensions of appropriate appreciation of all of
nature by any of its appreciators. Thus, even in light of the possibility of a pluralist
model, models such as the arousal model and the natural environmental model
maintain a special place as general guides to appropriate aesthetic appreciation of
nature. This is because these models concentrate on the most fundamental layers of
the human overlay, those constituting the very foundations of our experience and
understanding of nature. However, there may be other layers relevant to our
appreciation of nature that are equally universal, although they may constitute the
spires rather than the foundations of the human deposit. Such layers are the focus of
the metaphysical imagination model of nature appreciation. According to this view,
our imagination interprets nature as revealing metaphysical insights: insights about
the whole of experience, about the meaning of life, about the human condition,
about humankind’s place in the cosmos. Thus, this model includes in appropriate
aesthetic appreciation of nature those abstract meditations and speculations about
the true nature of reality that our encounters with nature frequently engender in
us.
13
The metaphysical imagination model invites us to entertain in our aesthetic
appreciation of nature deep meditations and possibly wild speculations, but again the
question of what is and what is not relevant arises. Which of such meditations and
speculations are only trivial and fanciful and which are serious and sustainable? In
essence, the question is again that of what does and what does not actually focus on
and reveal nature as it in fact is. However, in the context of the metaphysical
imagination model, this question arises as a general and profound question about
the real nature of the natural world. Thus, the metaphysical imagination model
10 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
indicates a new agenda for the aesthetics of nature, for it suggests that in order to
ultimately adjudicate among the different models of aesthetic appreciation of
nature, we must first resolve more fundamental metaphysical issues about the true
character of nature and about our proper place in its grand design.
14
The new agenda for the aesthetics of nature indicated by the metaphysical
imagination model points to the need to address fundamental issues about the
nature of the natural world and our place in it. Thus, this agenda suggests that
primary consideration should be given to those models of aesthetic appreciation of
nature that most directly deal with such issues. As noted in the first section of this
chapter, within the Western world the development of the aesthetic appreciation of
nature has been closely intertwined with the growth of the natural sciences. And, of
course, within the Western world, it is science that is taken to most successfully
address fundamental issues about the true character of the natural world and
humanity’s place in it. Consequently, the new agenda points to the centrality of that
model which ties appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature most closely to
scientific knowledge: the natural environmental model.
15
The natural environmental model: some further ramifications
In addition to directly speaking to the new agenda for the aesthetics of nature, the
natural environmental model has a number of other ramifications worth noting.
Some of these concern what is called applied aesthetics, in particular popular
appreciation of nature as practiced not only by tourists but by each of us in our
daily pursuits. As noted in the first section of this chapter, such appreciation
frequently involves a somewhat uneasy balance between two different modes: on the
one hand, that flowing from the tradition of the picturesque and currently
embodied in artistic and cultural models, such as the landscape model, and, on the
other, the positive aesthetics mode growing from the tradition of thinkers such as
Thoreau and Marsh and fully realized in John Muir. The balance between the two
modes of appreciation is to some degree tipped in favor of the latter by the natural
environmental model in that this model provides theoretical underpinnings for
positive aesthetics. When nature is aesthetically appreciated in virtue of the natural
and environmental sciences, positive aesthetic appreciation is singularly appropriate,
for, on the one hand, pristine nature—nature in its natural state—is an aesthetic
ideal and, on the other, as science increasingly finds, or at least appears to find,
unity, order, and harmony in nature, nature itself, when appreciated in light of such
knowledge, appears more fully beautiful.
16
Other ramifications of the natural environmental model are more directly
environmental and ethical. Many of the other models for the aesthetic appreciation
of nature are frequently condemned as totally anthropocentric, as not only anti-
natural but also arrogantly disdainful of environments that do not conform to
artistic and cultural ideals and preconceptions. The root source of these
environmental and ethical concerns is that such models, as noted in the second
section of this chapter, do not always encourage appreciation of nature for what it is
THE AESTHETICS OF NATURE 11
and for the qualities it has. However, since the natural environmental model bases
aesthetic appreciation on a scientific view of nature, it thereby endows aesthetic
appreciation of nature with a degree of objectivity that helps to dispel
environmental and moral criticisms, such as the charge of anthropocentrism.
Moreover, the possibility of an objective basis for aesthetic appreciation of nature
also holds out promise of more direct practical relevance in a world increasingly
engaged in environmental assessment.
17
Individuals making such assessments,
although typically not worried about anthropocentrism, are yet frequently reluctant
to acknowledge the relevance and importance of aesthetic considerations, regarding
them simply as at worst completely subjective whims or at best only relativistic,
transient, and soft-headed cultural ideals. Recognizing that aesthetic appreciation of
nature has scientific underpinnings helps to meet such doubts.
Another consequence concerns the discipline of aesthetics itself. The natural
environmental model, in rejecting artistic and other related models of nature
appreciation in favour of a dependence on common sense/scientific knowledge,
provides a blueprint for aesthetic appreciation in general. This model suggests that
in aesthetic appreciation of anything, be it people or pets, farmyards or
neighborhoods, shoes or shopping malls, appreciation must be centered on and
driven by the real nature of the object of appreciation itself.
18
In all such cases, what
is appropriate is not an imposition of artistic or other inappropriate ideals, but
rather dependence on and guidance by means of knowledge, scientific or otherwise,
that is relevant given the nature of the thing in question.
19
This turn away from
irrelevant preconceptions and toward the real nature of objects of appreciation
points the way to a general aesthetics that expands the traditional conception of the
discipline, which, as noted in the first section of this chapter, has been for much of
this century narrowly equated with the philosophy of art. The upshot is a more
universal aesthetics. This is the field of study, now generally termed environmental
aesthetics, that is delineated in the general introduction to this volume. Its relevance
to the natural world is investigated in Part I of the volume; its application beyond
the realm of nature is pursued in Part II.
Lastly, in initiating a more universal and object-centered environmental
aesthetics, the natural environmental model aids in the alignment of aesthetics with
other areas of philosophy, such as ethics, epistemology, and philosophy of mind, in
which there is increasingly a rejection of archaic, inappropriate models and a new-
found dependence on knowledge relevant to the particular phenomena in question.
For example, the natural environmental model, in its rejection of appreciative
models condemned as anthropocentric, parallels environmental ethics in the latter’s
rejection of anthropocentric models for the moral assessment of the natural world
and the replacement of such models with paradigms drawn from the environmental
and natural sciences. The general challenge is that we confront a natural world that
allows great liberty concerning the ways and means of approaching it, and that we
must therefore find the right models in order to treat it appropriately. The aesthetic
dimension of this challenge is the primary focus of the remaining chapters of the
first part of this volume.
12 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
Notes
1 I discuss positive aesthetics in more detail in “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,”
Environmental Ethics, 1984, vol. 6, pp. 5–34 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6).
Muir’s view is well exemplified in his Atlantic Monthly essays collected in Our National
Parks, New York, Houghton Mifflin, 1916. For an introduction to the nature of
picturesque appreciation, see M.Andrews, The Search for the Picturesque, Stanford,
Stanford University Press, 1989.
2 The volumes referred to here are Monroe C.Beardsley’s important text, Aesthetics:
Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism, New York, Harcourt, Brace & World, 1958,
and the first two major anthologies in analytic aesthetics, W.E.Kennick (ed.) Art and
Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics, New York, St Martin’s Press, 1964 and Joseph
Margolis (ed.) Philosophy Looks at the Arts: Contemporary Readings in Aesthetics, New
York, Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1962. It is remarkable that even with a total of 1,527
pages among them, none of these volumes, each a classic of its kind, so much as
mentions the aesthetics of nature.
3 Ronald W.Hepburn, “Contemporary Aesthetics and the Neglect of Natural Beauty,”
in Bernard Williams and Alan Montefiore (eds) British Analytical Philosophy, London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1966, pp. 285–310. Ronald W.Hepburn, “Aesthetic
Appreciation of Nature,” in Harold Osborne (ed.) Aesthetics in the Modern World,
London, Thames and Hudson, 1968, pp. 49–66, is a shorter version of the same
article. Also see Ronald W.Hepburn, “Trivial and Serious in Aesthetic Appreciation of
Nature,” in Salim Kemal and Ivan Gaskell (eds) Landscape, Natural Beauty, and the
Arts, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 65–80.
4 I critique the object and the landscape models in more detail in “Appreciation and the
Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–
76 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4). For an updated version of this essay, see
“Aesthetic Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” in S.Armstrong and R.
Botzler (eds) Environmental Ethics: Divergence and Convergence, Second Edition, New
York, McGraw Hill, 1998, pp. 122–31 or, for a shorter version, see the same title in
S.Feagin and P.Maynard (eds) Aesthetics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1997, pp.
30–40.
5 The initial development of the natural environment model is in “Appreciation and the
Natural Environment,” op. cit., (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4) and in
“Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Objectivity,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
1981, vol. 40, pp. 15–27 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 5).
6 The original and best development of the engagement model is in Arnold Berleant,
The Aesthetics of Environment, Philadelphia, Temple University Press, 1992. See also
Berleant’s Art and Engagement, Philadelphia, Temple University Press, 1991 and Living
in the Landscape: Toward an Aesthetics of Environment, Lawrence, University Press of
Kansas, 1997. I discuss some of the philosophical underpinnings of the engagement
model in “Beyond the Aesthetic,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1994, vol. 52,
pp. 239–41 and “Aesthetics and Engagement,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1993, vol.
33, pp. 220–27.
7 The arousal model is presented in Noel Carroll, “On Being Moved By Nature:
Between Religion and Natural History,” in Kemal and Gaskell, opt. cit., pp. 244–66.1
discuss this model in detail and develop the suggestions made here in “Nature,
THE AESTHETICS OF NATURE 13
Aesthetic Appreciation, and Knowledge,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1995,
vol. 53, pp. 393–400.
8 The mystery model is found in Stan Godlovitch “Icebreakers: Environmentalism and
Natural Aesthetics,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 1994, vol. 11, pp. 15–30. I discuss
the mystery model more fully in “Appreciating Godlovitch,” Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism, 1997, vol. 55, pp. 55–7 and “Nature, Aesthetic Appreciation, and
Knowledge,” op. cit.
9 The nonaesthetic model, under the name the Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic, is
outlined in Don Mannison, “A Prolegomenon to a Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic,” in
Don Mannison, Michael McRobbie, and Richard Routley (eds) Environmental
Philosophy, Canberra, Australian National University, 1980, pp. 212–16. A similar
position is defended in Robert Elliot, “Faking Nature,” Inquiry, 1982, vol. 25, pp. 81–
93. But for a revised position see Robert Elliot, Faking Nature: The Ethics of
Environmental Restoration, London, Routledge, 1997. I discuss this kind of approach
in “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,” op. cit. (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6)
and “Appreciating Art and Appreciating Nature,” in Kemal and Gaskell, op. cit., pp.
199–227 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 7).
10 See Paul Ziff, “Anything Viewed,” in Antiaesthetics: An Appreciation of the Cow with
the Subtile Nose, Dordrecht, Reidel, 1984, pp. 129–39.
11 Although the postmodern model seems a recent innovation, it was suggested over one
hundred years ago by George Santayana in The Sense of Beauty, [1896], New York,
Collier, 1961, p. 99. He claims that the natural landscape is “indeterminate” and must
becomposed by each of us by beingpoetized by our day-dreams, and turned by
our instant fancy into so many hints of a fairyland of happy living and vague
adventure” before “we feel that the landscape is beautiful.” I discuss the postmodern
model in “Between Nature and Art” (in this volume, Chapter 8) and in “Landscape
and Literature” (in this volume, Chapter 14). I consider postmodern architecture in
“Existence, Location, and Function: The Appreciation of Architecture,” in M. Mitias
(ed.) Philosophy and Architecture, Amsterdam, Rodopi, 1994, pp. 141–64 (reproduced
in this volume, Chapter 13).
12 Some themes of the pluralist model have been suggested to me by the work of Yrjo
Sepanmaa, especially his The Beauty of Environment, Second Edition, Denton,
Texas, Environmental Ethics Books, 1993. I endorse certain aspects of this model in
“Landscape and Literature” (in this volume, Chapter 14).
13 The metaphysical imagination model is outlined in Ronald W.Hepburn, “Landscape
and the Metaphysical Imagination,” Environmental Values, 1996, vol. 5, pp. 191–204.
14 Since, as noted, Hepburn’s “Contemporary Aesthetics and the Neglect of Natural
Beauty,” op. cit., set the initial agenda for the contemporary discussion of the
aesthetics of nature and since the metaphysical imagination model is one of his most
recent contributions to the field, it is most fitting that this model should set a new
agenda for future discussion.
15 Perhaps a paradigm exemplification of aesthetic appreciation enhanced by natural
science is Aldo Leopold’s A Sand County Almanac, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
1949. Leopold’s aesthetics are elaborated in “The Land Aesthetic,” in J.B.Callicott
(ed.) Companion to A Sand County Almanac, Madison, University of Wisconsin Press,
1987, pp. 157–71. The centrality of science in aesthetic appreciation of nature is
challenged in Y.Saito, “Is There a Correct Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature?,” Journal
of Aesthetic Education, 1984, vol. 18, pp. 35–46. I discuss her concerns in “Saito on
14 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
the Correct Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1986,
vol. 20, pp. 8593. For further discussion of the role of science, see H.Rolston, “Does
Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature Need to be Science Based?,” British Journal of
Aesthetics, 1995, vol. 35, pp. 374–86 and M.Budd, “The Aesthetic Appreciation of
Nature,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1996, vol. 36, pp. 207–22, as well as Y. Saito,
“The Aesthetics of Unscenic Nature,” S.Godlovitch, “Evaluating Nature
Aesthetically,” C.Foster, “The Narrative and the Ambient in Environmental
Aesthetics,” E.Brady, “Imagination and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” M.
M.Eaton, “Fact and Fiction in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” and H.Rolston,
“Aesthetic Experience in Forests,” all in A.Berleant and A.Carlson (eds) The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism: Special Issue: Environmental Aesthetics, 1998, vol. 56, pp.
101–66.
16 I consider positive aesthetics and its relationship to the rise of science in “Nature and
Positive Aesthetics,” op. cit, (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6).
17 I discuss objectivity in appreciation of nature in “Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and
Objectivity,” op. cit. (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 5) and in “On the
Possibility of Quantifying Scenic Beauty,” Landscape Planning, 1977, vol. 4, pp. 131–
72. I briefly overview some of the issues in landscape assessment research in
“Landscape Assessment,” in M.Kelly (ed.) Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, New York,
Oxford University Press, 1989, Vol. 3, pp. 102–5.
18 I apply these ideas to other kinds of cases in Part II of this volume, especially in “On
the Aesthetic Appreciation of Japanese Gardens,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1997,
vol. 37, pp. 47–56 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 11), “On Appreciating
Agricultural Landscapes,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1985, vol. 43, pp.
301–12 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 12), and “Existence, Location, and
Function: The Appreciation of Architecture,” in Mitias, op. cit. (reproduced in this
volume, Chapter 13).
19 I develop the idea of an object-centered aesthetics in “Appreciating Art and
Appreciating Nature,” in Kemal and Gaskell, op. cit., pp. 199–227 (reproduced in
this volume, Chapter 7) and throughout Part II of this volume, especially in “Between
Nature and Art” (this volume, Chapter 8).
THE AESTHETICS OF NATURE 15
16
2
UNDERSTANDING AND AESTHETIC
EXPERIENCE
Aesthetic experience on the Mississippi
In Life on the Mississippi Mark Twain remarks:
The face of the water, in time, became a wonderful book—a book
that was a dead language to the uneducated passenger, but which told
its mind to me without reserve, delivering its most cherished secrets as
clearly as if it uttered them with a voice… In truth, the passenger who
could not read this book saw nothing but all manner of pretty pictures
in it, painted by the sun and shaded by the clouds, whereas to the
trained eye these were not pictures at all, but the grimmest and most
dead-earnest of reading matter.
Now when I had mastered the language of this water… I had made a
valuable acquisition. But I had lost something, too. I had lost
something which could never be restored to me while I lived. All the
grace, the beauty, the poetry had gone out of the majestic river! I still
kept in mind a certain wonderful sunset which I witnessed when
steamboating was new to me. A broad expanse of the river was turned
to blood; in the middle distance the red hue brightened into gold,
through which a solitary log came floating, black and conspicuous; in
one place a long, slanting mark lay sparkling upon the water; in another
the surface was broken by boiling, tumbling rings, that were as many-
tinted as an opal; where the ruddy flush was faintest, was a smooth spot
that was covered with graceful circles and radiating lines, ever so
delicately traced; the shore on our left was densely wooded, and the
somber shadow that fell from this forest was broken in one place by a
long, ruffled trail that shone like silver; and high above the forest wall a
clean-stemmed dead tree waved a single leafy bough that glowed like a
flame in the unobstructed splendor that was flowing from the sun.
There were graceful curves, reflected images, woody heights, soft
distances; and over the whole scene, far and near, the dissolving lights
drifted steadily, enriching it, every passing moment, with new marvels
of coloring.
I stood like one bewitched. I drank it in, in a speechless rapture…
But as I have said, a day came when…if that sunset scene had been
repeated, I should have looked upon it without rapture, and should
have commented upon it, inwardly, after this fashion: The sun means
that we are going to have wind to-morrow; the floating log means that
the river is rising, small thanks to it; that slanting mark on the water
refers to a bluff reef which is going to kill somebody’s steamboat one of
these nights, if it keeps on stretching out like that; those tumbling
“boils” show a dissolving bar and a changing channel there; the lines
and circles in the slick water over yonder are a warning that that
troublesome place is shoaling up dangerously; that silver streak in the
shadow of the forest is the “break” from a new snag, and he has located
himself in the very best place he could have found to fish for
steamboats; that tall dead tree, with a single living branch, is not going
to last long, and then how is a body ever going to get through this blind
place at night without the friendly old landmark?
No, the romance and the beauty were all gone from the river.
1
In this passage, Twain describes two different experiences of the river. The first,
when steamboating was new to him and he saw the river as would an “uneducated
passenger,” is an experience of “all manner of pretty pictures, painted by the sun and
shaded by the clouds.” The second, when he had “mastered the language of this
water” and he looked upon the river with a “trained eye,” is an experience in which
the pretty pictures are replaced by an understanding of the meaning of the river. Twain
suggests that the two experiences are mutually exclusive, or at least that each makes
the other difficult, if not impossible. On the one hand, the uneducated passenger
sees “nothing but” pretty pictures because he or she cannot read the language of the
river. On the other, Twain, once he had learned to understand this language, had
“lost something which could never be restored”—“All the grace, the beauty, the
poetry had gone out of the majestic river!”
The first experience Twain describes, that of the grace, the beauty, and the poetry of
the river, is of the kind that is typically called aesthetic experience. The second is of
the kind that may be characterized as cognitive; it involves an understanding of
meanings achieved in virtue of knowledge gained through education or training.
Thus, a significant question posed by Twain’s remarks is the question of whether or
not aesthetic experience and cognitive experience are in conflict in the way in which
he seemingly suggests that they are. Is it the case that, without knowledge and
understanding of that which we experience, we, like the uneducated passenger, may
experience it aesthetically? And, more important, is it the case that once we have
acquired such knowledge and understanding the possibility of aesthetic experience is
in some way destroyed—and that we, like Twain, have then “lost something which
could never be restored”?
18 UNDERSTANDING AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
To address these issues, we need to examine more carefully Twain’s conception of
the nature of aesthetic experience. Twain says that without knowing the language of
the river, the uneducated passenger sees nothing but pretty pictures. However, his
account of his own aesthetic experience of the river before he had acquired this
knowledge of the river’s language reveals an experience more cultivated than simply
seeing pretty pictures. It is an experience of overpowering beauty which “bewitches”
him, reducing him to a “speechless rapture.” Moreover, his description of the scene
that evokes this rapture is primarily in terms of two kinds of things. First, he describes
“marvels of coloring” such as “the river…turned to blood,…the red hue brightened
into gold,” “rings…as many-tinted as an opal,” a “trail that shone like silver,” and a
“bough that glowed like a flame in the unobstructed splendor that was flowing from
the sun.” Second, he describes what may be called marvels of form, such as “a long,
slanting mark…sparkling upon the water,” “the surface broken by boiling, tumbling
rings,” and “a smooth spot…covered with graceful circles and radiating lines, ever so
delicately traced.” In short, Twain’s conception of aesthetic experience is that of an
intense emotional state evoked by the appreciation of striking combinations of
colors, lines, and shapes. Twain’s experience is both more refined and in a sense
sparser than that of seeing pretty pictures.
Formalism and aesthetic experience
If this is a correct characterization of Twain’s conception of aesthetic experience, we
may now inquire as to why, given this conception, he seemingly holds that an
aesthetic experience of a thing is in conflict with knowledge yielding an
understanding of its meaning. However, such an inquiry is hampered by the fact
that other than a few scattered remarks such as those quoted here, Twain does not have
much to say about aesthetic matters. Consequently, perhaps this inquiry can be
most fruitfully pursued by considering Twain’s views in light of a familiar theory of
art—a theory to which his views are remarkably similar. The theory is what is
known as the formalist theory of art; it is associated with the so-called “art for art’s
sake movement” which was fashionable around the turn of the century. The theory
receives its best-known treatment in the writings of two British art critics, Clive Bell
and Roger Fry.Bell’s development of the theory is especially helpful in attempting to
understand Twain’s point of view.
In the tradition of classic philosophy of art, Bell develops the formalist theory as a
theory providing a definition of art in terms of an essential quality, a quality, as he
puts it, “common and peculiar to all members” of the class of works of art.
2
This
essential quality he calls “significant form” and characterizes as aesthetically moving
“relations and combinations of lines and colors.”
3
Moreover, he holds that such
moving combinations of lines and colors evoke in “anyone capable of feeling it” a
particular kind of emotion which he terms the “aesthetic emotion.”
4
Thus, Bell’s
account of aesthetic experience is essentially like that of Twain in that the
experience is constituted by a heightened emotional state evoked by the formal
aspects of objects. Just as Twain speaks of his experience of being moved to
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 19
“speechless rapture” by the forms and colors of the river, Bell speaks of his “thrilling
raptures,” saying of himself that “in those moments I lose myself in that infinitely
sublime state of mind to which pure visual form transports me.”
5
And although Bell
takes the experience of art to be the paradigm of this kind of formalist aesthetic
experience, he also, like Twain, conceives of the aesthetic appreciation of nature in
similar terms. He claims that to achieve “a thrill indistinguishable from that which
art gives” an appreciator must see the landscape not “as fields and cottages” but
rather contrive “to see it as a pure formal combination of lines and colours.”
6
Bell’s account of the aesthetic experience suggests at least one way of
understanding why Twain might believe that aesthetic experience is in conflict with
knowledge yielding an understanding of meaning. Bell sharply distinguishes that
which is essential to art, the significant form of a work, from its content. Moreover,
he holds that while significant form evokes aesthetic emotion, content evokes only
what he calls the emotions of life, our common emotional states unrelated to
aesthetic emotion. As he puts it: “…he who contemplates a work of art inhabits a
world with an intense and peculiar significance of its own; that significance is
unrelated to the significance of life. In this world the emotions of life find no
place.
7
However, for Bell the content of a work of art is its representational content
which, in evoking the emotions of life, can detract from the intense, peculiar, and
unrelated aesthetic emotion. Therefore, the content of a work is both irrelevant to
and potentially destructive of aesthetic appreciation. In a well-known passage Bell
declares: “The representative element in a work of art may or may not be harmful;
always it is irrelevant.”
8
And since the representational content of a work is, in one
sense, the meaning of the work, the aesthetic appreciation of a work is thereby
necessarily severed from any understanding of that meaning and the knowledge
required to achieve such understanding. The upshot is that, in Bell’s words, “to
appreciate a work of art we need bring with us nothing from life, no knowledge of
its ideas and affairs, no familiarity with its emotions. Art transports us from the
world of man’s activity to a world of aesthetic exaltation. For a moment we are shut
off from human interests; our anticipations and memories are arrested; we are lifted
above the stream of life.”
9
Thus, in formalism we have a theory of art which provides the following account
of the conflict Twain finds between aesthetic experience and understanding:
aesthetic experience involves only the appreciation of form and excludes any
attention to content; the former requires no knowledge yielding understanding of
meaning and, although the latter does require such knowledge, since it is excluded
from aesthetic appreciation, whatever knowledge is needed to understand the
meaning of content is at best irrelevant and at worse harmful to aesthetic
appreciation. On this position aesthetic appreciation is a sparse, pure experience
stripped of any associations with representational content and of any meanings it
embodies. However, in order to maintain this narrow conception of aesthetic
experience and to thereby account for Twain’s conflict, this position requires that
the distinction it draws between form and content be sharp, unequivocal, and
impermeable. Only if the distinction is such, does it effectively rule out knowledge
20 UNDERSTANDING AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
yielding understanding of meaning and put such understanding in essential
opposition to pure aesthetic appreciation. Thus, it is necessary to examine this
distinction more closely in order to determine whether or not it is viable and strong
enough to account for Twain’s conflict.
To investigate the form/content distinction, let us consider an example that, in spite
of its representational content, is yet highly formal and should therefore put the
distinction in its best light. Consider a work such as Aubrey Beardsley’s The Peacock
Skirt (1894), one of his well-known illustrations for Oscar Wilde’s Salome. The
work is a line drawing in back and white and depicts two individuals facing one
another, one of whom is wearing a large, flowing skirt resembling a peacock’s spread
tail feathers. If we briefly describe each of the form and the content of this work on
three different levels—that of the basic elements, the relationships among these
elements, and the more general overall quality of the work—then The Peacock Skirt
yields a form/content distinction something along the following lines. On the
content side of the ledger we have representational content primarily consisting of:
first, representations of two human beings, one of the human beings wearing a skirt
resembling a peacock’s tail; second, the two human beings represented as facing one
another and talking, perhaps whispering, to one another; and, third, a general
quality of refinement and elegance, but perhaps with a suggestion of something
sinister or even evil. On the form side of the ledger we have primarily the following:
first, as basic elements, two major shapes, one larger and rather pear-shaped and a
second roughly rectangular, the former essentially in outline and the latter with a lined
pattern throughout, and each consisting of black-and-white color and numerous
lines; second, as relationships of these elements, the former shape is dominant and
to the left of the composition and the latter recessive and to the right, while the
white color is the background color with the black largely concentrated at the
bottom of the composition and to a lesser extent at the top and along the right side;
third, as general quality, a composition that is sparse, yet graceful, unified, and
balanced.
Given this form/content distinction, the formalist theory holds that the aesthetic
appreciation of The Peacock Skirt consists of only that which is on the form side of
our ledger and that that which is on the content side is irrelevant and perhaps even
harmful to such appreciation. The aesthetic experience of The Peacock Skirt is
limited to the appreciation of the two major shapes together with the lines and
colors that comprise them, the intricate relationships among these shapes, lines, and
colors, and the grace, unity, and balance to which these elements and relationships
give rise. But, we must ask, is such pure aesthetic appreciation possible and is the
notion of such appreciation even intelligible? Part of the problem is that this kind of
appreciation seems at least psychologically very difficult, if not impossible. Exactly
how are we to manage such appreciation? Psychologically speaking, how do we draw
this sharp, unequivocal, and impermeable form/content distinction? How can we
even see the shape of a human being without also seeing that it represents a human
being and thereby understanding its meaning. Such appreciating of form without
content can be facilitated by manoeuvres such as the following: turning the work
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 21
upside down, moving far enough away from it such that its representations blur into
abstract forms, squinting one’s eyes so as to similarly blur the images, taking off
one’s glasses, if one wears glasses, or even just getting very tired or drunk. But is
Illustration 1 Peacock Skirt, by Aubrey Beardsley (1894).
22 UNDERSTANDING AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
there not something wrong with a position that requires that we put either the work
or ourselves in some kind of altered state in order to achieve aesthetic appreciation?
Seemingly, the notion of aesthetic experience embodied in such a position is
bordering on unintelligibility and incoherence. However, if confronted with such
worries, Bell and Twain could simply, as they say, bite the bullet, holding that no
one ever said that aesthetic appreciation was easy and, moreover, that the very
difficulty of appreciating form without content even supports their own position,
for it makes clear exactly how content can be harmful and how the understanding
of meanings can destroy the possibility of aesthetic experience.
However, there are other difficulties with the formalist form/content distinction
that are less easily put aside. Look again at The Peacock Skirt and consider its formal
qualities such as its unified and balanced composition. Now imagine attempting to
aesthetically appreciate it as the formalist theory of art requires, removing your
glasses or squinting your eyes if necessary. However, to the extent that you achieve
formalist aesthetic appreciation of the work, the work itself will appear less unified
and balanced. Seemingly the unity evaporates in part because, as formalist aesthetic
appreciation is achieved, the white center of the larger shape becomes a part of the
background rather than a figure, and this sets free both the black patches at the top
of the work and the large concentration of black at the bottom. This in turn
undercuts the balance of the work by unstabilizing the relationships between the
two major shapes and between the different areas of black, making the whole
composition bottom-heavy. However, as long as aesthetic appreciation includes
understanding of content, the unity and the balance of the composition are
maintained, seemingly because the very fact that two human beings are represented
stabilizes the two major shapes and moreover gives a powerful focal point in the
human faces at the top of the work, which focal point is sufficient to balance the
heavy black peacock skirt at the bottom. In a similar way, in Christian works of art
balance is sometimes achieved between many large shapes and one small cross
shape, not by means of formal elements and relationships, but rather by means of the
meanings that the shapes possess. In short, in works such as The Peacock Skirt the
overall formal quality of the work of art is dependent not only on formal elements
and relationships but on content elements and relationships as well. Apparently the
formalist’s putatively sharp, unequivocal, and impermeable distinction between form
and content has some cracks.
Moreover, it is not only the overall formal quality of a work that frequently
depends on content. As our consideration of The Peacock Skirt suggests, without
appreciation of representational content, the larger pear-like shape begins to
disintegrate. However, the situation is in fact more serious than this. Without
appreciation of the two major shapes of the work as representations of two human
beings, seemingly there are no grounds for even saying that the work has two major
shapes, rather than four or five or seven or seven hundred shapes. Imagine counting
the shapes in The Peacock Skirt or in any representational work of art without
reference to its content. This is like attempting to count the things in your study
without having a means of identifying what constitutes a thing. It seems that the
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 23
very identity of the formal elements of a work of art such as The Peacock Skirt
depends essentially upon the content of the work. The former cannot even be
identified, let alone aesthetically appreciated, without reference to the latter. Thus,
the formalist’s sharp, unequivocal, and impermeable distinction between form and
content is shown to be not simply cracked, but thoroughly porous, if it exists at all.
In short, the form/content distinction simply cannot be successfully maintained in
the way in which the formalist theory of art attempts to draw it; and the lean, formalist
conception of absolutely pure aesthetic experience that depends upon this
distinction is indeed exposed as incoherent.
Where does all this leave our attempt to understand Twain’s observations
concerning his two experiences of the river and his suggestion that there is a conflict
between them? We have found that the formalist way of drawing the form/content
distinction leads to incoherence. Therefore, the attempt, by means of this
distinction, to exclude all knowledge facilitating the understanding of meaning from
aesthetic experience is shown to be ungrounded. Even with the narrow formalist
conception of aesthetic experience, which Bell and Twain share, no necessary
conflict between aesthetic experience and understanding is established. In fact, the
contrary seems to be the case: a certain level and kind of knowledge facilitating the
understanding of meaning is apparently necessary in order to make any kind of
aesthetic appreciation possible—even sparse formalist aesthetic appreciation. But in
light of these findings we must ask: if Twains narrow conception of aesthetic
experience does not after all provide the resources for an account of the conflict he
finds between aesthetic experience and understanding, then what, if anything, will?
Disinterestedness and aesthetic experience
To find the answer to this question, perhaps we need to consider the other
dimension of Twain’s observations, that is, the second of the two experiences he
describes—not his aesthetic experience of the river, but the experience he had after
he had “mastered the language of this water” and looked upon it with a “trained
eye”—the experience in which moving combinations of colors, lines, and shapes are
replaced by understanding of the meaning of the river. Concerning this second kind
of experience it is important to note the nature of the meanings involved. In this
experience of the river, meaning pertains to matters such as rising water, hidden
reefs, changing channels, dangerous shoals, new snags, and blind spots; in short, the
meaning the riverboat pilot must understand in order to prevent the river from
“killing his steamboat.” Twain notes that the language of the river he has learned is
“never one that you could leave unread without loss,” adding that the “passenger
who could not read it was charmed with a peculiar sort of faint dimple on [the
water’s] surface…; but to the pilot that was an italicized passage;…for it meant that
a wreck or a rock was buried there that could tear the life out of the strongest vessel
that ever floated. It is the faintest and simplest expression that water ever makes, and
the most hideous to a pilot’s eye.”
10
24 UNDERSTANDING AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
In the way in which considering the formalist theory of art facilitated our
examination of Twain’s conception of aesthetic experience, considering another
important tradition in aesthetic theory may help clarify the significance of what we
may now call a “steamboat pilot experience” of the river. This is the tradition which
attempts to analyze aesthetic experience in terms of a distinct kind of mental state
typically described as one of disinterestedness. A significant contemporary advocate
of disinterestedness as an essential feature of aesthetic experience is Jerome Stolnitz.
Stolnitz traces this tradition to certain eighteenth-century British and Scottish
thinkers, three of whom are noteworthy here: the Third Earl of Shaftesbury
(Anthony Cooper), Francis Hutcheson, and Archibald Alison. Stolnitz suggests that
the concept of disinterestedness relevant to aesthetic appreciation gradually
developed over the eighteenth century in something like the following manner.
First, Shaftesbury introduces the idea as a way of characterizing the experience of
beauty, but initially his conception of disinterestedness is, relatively speaking,
theoretically lightweight and primarily negative, not unlike the contemporary idea of
a disinterested party—that is, an individual having no particular personal or selfish
interest in a situation. Similarly, Shaftesbury contrasts a disinterested stance toward
an object with using it for some purpose. Second, Hutcheson elaborates Shaftesbury’s
conception, expanding the idea so as to exclude not simply personal and self-serving
utilitarian interest, but also interest of a more general nature and in particular
cognitive interest. Third, the notion reaches its full theoretical development in the
thoughts of Alison who treats disinterestedness as a particular “state of mind” which
he characterizes in a famous passage as one of being “vacant and unemployed.”
11
Contemporary theoreticians of disinterestedness, such as Stolnitz, have in many
respects followed Alison’s account.
12
In light of even these extremely sketchy remarks about disinterestedness, it is clear
that if aesthetic experience is analyzed in terms of disinterestedness in either the
second or the third sense, then there is indeed a necessary conflict between aesthetic
experience and any experience involving an understanding of meanings by means of
knowledge gained through education or training. The second conception of
disinterestedness attributed to Hutcheson appears to explicitly exclude any such
cognitive dimensions from aesthetic experience, and Alison’s vacant and
unemployed state of mind would seemingly exclude that and much more.
Moreover, in each case it is a conceptual matter: any experiences involving such
understanding of meaning will not be aesthetic as a result of the very analysis of
what it is to be an aesthetic experience. Thus, in light of these notions of
disinterestedness, Twain’s suggestion of a conflict between his two experiences could
be explained and grounded after all. However, there are at least two problems with
such an account. First, although Twain’s idea of aesthetic experience is, as noted, a
quite narrow, formalist conception that could be underwritten by one or the other of
these theoretically vigorous notions of disinterestedness, there is no reason to think
that Twain subscribes to such notions. Perhaps the uneducated passenger who sees
nothing but pretty pictures has a vacant and unemployed mind, but, as also noted,
Twain’s aesthetic experience involves both more and less than pretty pictures. Second
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 25
and more important, those considerations by means of which we previously
demonstrated that the coherence of even the sparsest aesthetic appreciation requires
a certain level and kind of knowledge facilitating understanding also count against
the coherence of a conception of aesthetic experience constrained by these robust
notions of disinterestedness. In short, perhaps a mind that is truly vacant and
unemployed or even one that simply excludes all cognitive dimensions can have no
aesthetic experience at all—or at least none such as Twain attributes to himself.
However, what about the essentially negative conception of disinterestedness
attributed to Shaftesbury, the notion not so different from the contemporary, non-
theoretical idea of disinterestedness? On the position that aesthetic experience is
disinterested in this sense, an individual will apparently not have an aesthetic
experience of an object if he or she has some particular personal or self-serving
utilitarian interest in it. Even though this position is theoretically weaker than the
other two, it is yet adequate for addressing Twain’s conflict between his two
experiences of the river. Here is where it is significant that Twain’s second
experience is a “steamboat pilot experience.” Such an experience is a paradigm of the
kind that this position claims is in conflict with aesthetic appreciation. The pilot’s
particular understanding of the meanings of the water, the understanding of hidden
reefs, changing channels, dangerous shoals, new snags, and the like, is exactly the
kind of self-serving utilitarian interest in the river that seemingly interferes with
aesthetic experience, indeed perhaps even destroys the possibility of such experience.
The pilot is only using the river for his or her own purposes, and this apparently
makes aesthetic appreciation of it difficult, if not impossible. If nothing else, reading
the language of the water in order to successfully utilize the river is for the pilot such
an all-important and all-consuming interest that this will, at least in practice, if not
in theory, exclude all other experiences of it. We must remember that the penalty
for a pilot’s failing to be single-mindedly obsessed by the language of the river can
be the “killing of his steamboat.”
As noted, however, this position is theoretically weaker than those involving the
other two senses of disinterestedness. Part of the weakness lies in the fact that it need
not be taken as an analysis of aesthetic experience requiring a commitment to a
special state of mind. Rather, it may be taken as embodying only an empirical
observation about the actual relationship between aesthetic appreciation and certain
kinds of interests, such as those of a steamboat pilot. But given this, is it yet strong
enough to really explain the conflict Twain finds between his two experiences of the
river? Concerning this question, two points are relevant. On the one hand, as
suggested above, the position, even if only empirical, yet clearly accounts for the
conflict Twain reports, that is, his inability to aesthetically appreciate the river when
he instead reads the language of the water as would a steamboat pilot. On the other
hand, however, Twain claims that having mastered the language of the water, he has
“lost something which could never be restored” to him in his lifetime. Is not, we
might ask, an analysis of the nature of aesthetic experience rather than simply an
empirical observation required to account for the finality of Twain’s loss? In light of
the strength of his claim, perhaps a conceptual point is required after all. However,
26 UNDERSTANDING AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
if so, perhaps such a point about the role of steamboat pilot, rather than about
aesthetic experience, is adequate. That is to say, to be a steamboat pilot, or at least to
be a good one, may conceptually require that one single-mindedly engage in the all-
consuming interest in the language of the water, which interest as a matter of fact
excludes aesthetic experience of the river. If Twain has indeed lost something that
can never be restored in his lifetime, perhaps it is only his ability, when confronted
by the river, to take up any role other than the role of good steamboat pilot.
Conclusion
In conclusion, it must be admitted that our treatment of Twain’s marvelous
description of this one facet of his life on the Mississippi does not account for
something we initially thought suggested by it, that is, a conflict between aesthetic
experience and cognitive experience in general. However, although Twain’s remarks
suggest a general conflict, he is not, given his focus on the particular experience of
the steamboat pilot, committed to any such conflict. Moreover, that he is not so
committed is just as well, for we have discovered, first, in our consideration of the
formalist theory of art, that defending any such general conflict leads to incoherence
and, second, in our consideration of disinterestedness, that defending such a conflict
is not necessary in order to explain observations such as Twain’s. And if we can
account for the observations of an individual as astute and perceptive as Twain
without committing him to an incoherent and unnecessary position, that is
probably some indication that we are on the right track.
Notes
1 Mark Twain, Life on the Mississippi [1883], New York, Penguin, 1984, pp. 94–6.
2 Clive Bell, Art [1913], New York, G.P.Putnam’s Sons, 1958, p. 17. For a more
general examination of formalism, formal qualities, and appreciation of nature, see
“Formal Qualities in the Natural Environment,Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1979,
vol. 13, pp. 99–114 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 3). I also discuss these issues
in “On the Possibility of Quantifying Scenic Beauty,” Landscape Planning, 1977, vol.
4, pp. 131–72.
3 Bell, op. cit, p.17.
4 Ibid., p.17.
5 Ibid., p. 30.
6 Ibid., p. 45.
7 Ibid., p. 28.
8 Ibid., p. 27.
9 Ibid., p. 27.
10 Twain, op. cit., p. 94.
11 Archibald Alison, Essays on the Nature and Principles of Taste [1790], Third Edition,
Edinburgh, Archibald Constable and Company, 1812, vol. I, p. 10. The relevant
sources for Shaftesbury and Hutcheson are, respectively, Anthony, Earl of Shaftesbury,
Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, etc. [1711], John M.Robertson (ed.),
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 27
Gloucester, Massachusetts, Peter Smith, 1963 and Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry
Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design. [1725], Peter Kivy (ed.), The Hague,
Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.
12 See Jerome Stolnitz, “Of the Origins of ‘Aesthetic Disinterestedness,’” The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1961, vol. 20, pp. 131–43. For Stolnitz’s own position on
disinterestedness, see Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Criticism: A
Critical Introduction, Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 1960. For a fuller discussion of his
position, see my “Appreciating Art and Appreciating Nature,” in S.Kemal and I.
Gaskell (eds) Landscape, Natural Beauty, and the Arts, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1993, pp. 199–227 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 7). I also
consider the ramifications of disinterestedness in “Between Nature and Art” (in this
volume, Chapter 8).
28 UNDERSTANDING AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
3
FORMAL QUALITIES IN THE NATURAL
ENVIRONMENT
Formal qualities and formalism
Following up our introduction to formalism in Chapter 2, in this chapter I consider
the significance of formal qualities—in particular, in the aesthetic appreciation and
evaluation of the natural environment. The topic is of interest for at least two
reasons. The first is that there is a marked emphasis on formal qualities in much of
the current non-theoretical research in environmental aesthetics. The second is that
recent philosophical discussion of the aesthetics of the natural environment suggests
that the whole question of formal aesthetic qualities in the natural environment is
more perplexing than it at first appears.
Initially, it is useful to introduce a notion of “formal qualities” somewhat more
precise than the intuitive notion relied upon in Chapter 2. Writers in philosophical
aesthetics have identified and classified the aesthetic qualities of objects in various
ways. Two groupings of qualities about which there is some agreement, however,
are sensory or sensuous qualities and formal or design qualities. The former are
qualities of textures, colors, and lines of objects, such as the smoothness and luster
of a polished stone or the sharpness and sparkle of a crystal. Sensory qualities are
worth noting here in that their specification aids in the clarification of formal
qualities. This is so in part because textures, lines, and colors combine in relations to
create the shapes, patterns, and designs that constitute the perceived form of an
object. It is the qualities of such forms, such as their being unified or chaotic,
balanced or unbalanced, harmonious or confused, that I call formal qualities. It
follows that formal qualities are qualities that objects or combinations of objects have
in virtue of that which constitutes their forms. This includes not only their shapes,
patterns, and designs, but also their textures, lines, and colors.
At this point it is also useful to further clarify the notion of formalism, especially
as it is employed in the third section of this chapter. This can be done by reference
to the above-mentioned aspects of objects. Concerning aesthetic appreciation,
formalism holds that such appreciation is to be directed toward those aspects—
textures, lines, colors and resultant shapes, patterns, and designs—that constitute
the form of the object. Concerning aesthetic value, formalism holds that the formal
qualities of an object, which it has in virtue of these aspects, are the only qualities
relevant to the aesthetic value of that object. An object is aesthetically good in virtue
of having formal qualities such as unity and balance—or more sophisticated
variations such as “organic unity” or “variety in unity”—and aesthetically bad in
virtue of having formal qualities such as disharmony or lack of integration.
Formal qualities in current work in environmental aesthetics
As suggested above, there is an emphasis on formal qualities in much current work
in environmental aesthetics. The work in question originates in fields such as
geography, forestry management, recreation planning, and landscape architecture.
The overall aim of much of this work is to identify, classify, evaluate, or measure
quantifiably the aesthetic dimension of the natural environment. For example,
researchers hope or claim to identify and map large areas of “scenic value,” to
classify and appraise “visual landscape qualities,” to evaluate and compare
quantitatively the “aesthetic quality of different landscapes,” and to “quantify scenic
beauty.”
1
To accomplish all this it is important to have a clear understanding of
concepts such as “scenic value,” “the aesthetic quality of the landscape,” and “scenic
beauty.” It is in the understanding of these concepts that much research seemingly
assumes an account of aesthetic appreciation and value which is heavily, if not
exclusively, dependent upon formal qualities.
It is useful to briefly illustrate this point. The emphasis on formal qualities is
attributable to researchers who describe and promote “the possibility and
usefulness” of seeing “the managed forest in terms of design factors: form, contrast,
distance, color, light, and angle of view.”
2
This direction has apparently become the
policy of the US National Forest Service. Its training document, which is the “basic
text to illustrate the concepts, elements, and principles” of the Forest Service’s
landscape management program, describes “form, line, color, and texture” as the
four main elements in any landscape and suggests principles such as “contrast,”
“axis,” and “convergence” to analyze these elements. Concerning aesthetic
appreciation, the aesthetic dimension of the environment—or, as it is put in the
document, the “character of a landscape”—is defined as “the overall impression
created by its unique combination of visual features (such as land, vegetation, water,
and structures) as seen in terms of form, line, color, and texture.” As for aesthetic
value, it is suggested that the overall “scenic quality” of landscapes should be
evaluated mainly in terms of the “variety” or “diversity” of these four formal
elements.
3
Thus aesthetic appreciation is directed toward those elements that
constitute the perceived form of a landscape, and aesthetic evaluation of “scenic
quality” is elaborated by reference to certain formal qualities that arise from these
elements.
The emphasis of formal qualities is also evident in research that attempts
to measure the environment’s aesthetic quality. An excellent example is the work of
E.L.Shafer. He and his colleagues have attempted to measure quantitatively the
“aesthetic quality of different landscapes” by trying to identify and measure
“quantitative features in a landscape” which “affect its aesthetic appeal.” Whether such
30 FORMAL QUALITIES IN THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT
an attempt can be successful is not important here; what is important is the
methodology utilized. It involves dividing photographs of landscapes into different
“zones”—sky and clouds, water, immediate trees and shrubs, immediate other
features, distant trees and shrubs, and so forth—and measuring the perimeters and
areas of such zones. The perimeter and area measurements are then fed into an
equation in order to calculate the aesthetic preferability or aesthetic appeal of the
landscapes.
4
What is significant about this methodology is its assumption that the
“aesthetic quality of different landscapes” can be measured by means of measuring
formal aspects of photographs. The zones to be measured are initially identified in
terms of content (e.g., distant trees and shrabs), but the actual measurements are of
certain shapes and lines and of the relationships holding between these shapes and
lines. Being measurements of those elements that constitute form, they can at most
indicate that a given combination of shapes and lines has formal qualities such as
balance or proportion. In short, the attempt is to calculate the “aesthetic quality of
different landscapes” in terms of form and formal qualities.
Background on the significance assigned to formal qualities
Some background is useful to help explain this emphasis on formal qualities. First to
be mentioned is the rather recent popularity enjoyed by formalism in art and art
criticism. As noted in Chapter 2, formalism as a theory of art and of art criticism was
promoted early in this century by Clive Bell, Roger Fry, and other critics.
Moreover, although the position has been subjected to extensive criticism by art
critics and aestheticians, it has nonetheless had great influence on both the initial
acceptance and the continued development of various degrees of abstraction in art.
Hand in hand with these developments came the willingness and the ability on the
part of both critics and the general public to respond to the more formal dimensions
in art and to think of aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic value in terms of form and
formal qualities. These developments were essentially healthy since previously the
formal dimensions of art had perhaps not been adequately appreciated. And now
vigorously growing new artistic traditions, different schools of criticism, and
opposing theories of art have combined to achieve a balanced appreciation of the
formal dimensions of art along with its other dimensions.
For our purposes, however, it is most important to note that formalism was
promoted not only in art, but also concerning the natural environment. As we saw
in Chapter 2, Bell, for example, suggests that when the artist sees non-art objects in
“moments of inspiration” or “moments of aesthetic vision,” he or she sees them as
“pure forms.” At one point he speculates:
All of us, I imagine, do, from time to time, get a vision of material objects as
pure forms. We see things as ends in themselves, that is to say, and at such
moments it seems possible, and even probable, that we see them with the eye
of an artist. Who has not, once at least in his life, had a sudden vision of
landscape as pure form? For once, instead of seeing it as fields and cottages, he
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 31
has felt it as lines and colors. In that moment has he not won from material
beauty a thrill indistinguishable from that which art gives? And, if this be so,
is it not clear that he has won from material beauty the thrill that, generally,
art alone can give, because he has contrived to see it as a pure formal
combination of lines and colors? May we go on to say that, having seen it as
pure form, having freed it from all casual and adventitious interests, from all
that it may have acquired from its commerce with human beings, from all its
significance as a means, he has felt its significance as an end in itself?
5
The implication here is clear: If we are to appreciate the natural environment
aesthetically, we must “see it as a pure formal combination of lines and colors.”
Thus formalism was initially accepted as being as appropriate for the natural
environment as it was for art. And although formalism concerning the natural
environment developed somewhat more slowly than it did concerning art, the
former (at least as a distinct emphasis on formal qualities) has stayed with us longer
than the latter. I suspect this is so in part because, as noted in Chapter 1, until very
recently there have not been many new traditions, different schools of criticism, or
opposing theories with respect to the aesthetics of the natural environment. In this
area formalism has not been placed in proper perspective, as it has in the arts;
instead it has remained a relatively uncontested and popular point of view. As a
result, formalism is not only taken for granted as the basis for much empirical
research, but a version of it also emerges in some of the more theoretical discussions.
Thus we find individuals today saying essentially what Bell says in the above quote.
For example, in discussing a criterion for scenic beauty one such individual, writing
exactly a half century after Bell, states:
Preoccupation with purpose is in fact no aid, but a deterrent to landscape
appreciation. The man who has to consider what things are used for is least
likely to note their shapes, colors and patterns. To exalt his judgment is to
promote a complacent inattention to appearance, an abnegation of esthetic
response.
6
A second factor that may explain the assumed importance of formal qualities in the
aesthetics of the natural environment is also closely related to a development in art
and art appreciation. This is the rise of landscape painting and its effects on
aesthetic appreciation. This development is at least in part responsible for a certain
mode of perceiving and aesthetically appreciating the natural environment, the core
of which is the landscape model of nature appreciation introduced in Chapter 1. This
mode of appreciation is clearly evident in what is sometimes called the “scenery
cult.”
7
Essentially, it encourages perceiving and appreciating the natural
environment as if it were a landscape painting, that is, as a certain kind of prospect
seen from a specific standpoint. The mode of appreciation was exemplified in the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries in the use of the “Claude-glass,” a small, tinted,
convex mirror named for the landscape artist. Tourists used the mirror to view the
32 FORMAL QUALITIES IN THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT
landscape, finding that it, as a travel book of the day put it, removes objects “great
and near” “to a due distance, and shews them in the soft colors of nature, and most
regular perspective the eye can perceive;” the glass gives “the finished picture, in
highest coloring, and just perspective.”
8
Likewise, modern tourists reveal their
preferences for this same mode of appreciation by frequenting “scenic viewpoints,”
where the actual space between tourists and the prescribed “view,” as well as the
position of the viewpoint itself, often enhances elements of color and perspective.
Moreover, modern tourists also seek “the finished picture, in highest coloring, and
just perspective.” It can be found in the “scene” framed in the viewfinders of their
cameras and in the resultant Kodachrome slides, as well as in the ever-popular
formally composed postcards of the “scene.” The point is that, as one commentator
puts it, “the taste has been for a view, for scenery, [for] a prospect.”
9
The significance of the scenery cult for our interests here is that the related mode
of appreciation accentuates overall form and formal qualities and thus implicitly
guides the appreciator towards these qualities in the appreciation of the natural
environment. In the carefully composed landscape paintings—and even in their poor
cousins, the postcard reproductions—form-constituting elements, resultant overall
form, and formal qualities such as balance, proportion, and organization are of
considerable importance. These formal aspects are rightly appreciated in, and
contribute significantly to the aesthetic value of, such art works and reproductions.
Consequently, when tourists attempt to perceive and appreciate the natural
environment as if it were a landscape painting, they are guided toward the formal
dimensions. The Claude-glass, the camera viewfinder, and the scenic viewpoint all
help make the environment look more like landscape art as they tone down harsh
contrasts, make detail less evident, accentuate overall relations and patterns, and
more or less provide limits for the scene. But in all this the form and formal
qualities of the environment are enhanced at the expense of the natural
environment’s other aesthetically significant qualities. In this way the scenery cult
not only promotes the aesthetic appreciation of the natural environment (as has
been widely recognized); it also promotes a certain kind of aesthetic appreciation—
appreciation with a formalist bias.
The way in which the scenery cult promotes formal qualities in the aesthetic
appreciation of the natural environment has an interesting parallel in current
research. The difference is that this research emphasizes formal qualities not by
adopting a specific mode of appreciation, but by utilizing a certain kind of
substitute for the natural environment—the photograph. Much research, such as
that of Shafer mentioned above, uses photographs of the environment as “stand-ins
that make research easier, quicker, and less expensive. It is important to note,
however, that the use of photographs affects aesthetic appreciation. The
photograph, like the Claude-glass and the camera viewfinder, makes detail less
evident, accentuates overall relations and patterns, and provides limits for the scene.
Moreover, the components of a photograph are shapes, colors, lines, and patterns
and not the trees, shrubs, and rocks that compose the natural environment. Thus it
is easier and more “natural” for individuals to perceive the natural environment in
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 33
terms of shapes, lines, colors and patterns when they are presented with a
photograph of it than when they are in the environment itself. The upshot is that if
one plans and executes research in environmental aesthetics in terms of photographs
rather than the actual environment, a concentration on form-constituting elements
and formal qualities becomes a natural approach. Moreover, such an approach
appears even more natural given the historical prominence of artistic formalism and
the larger context of the scenery cult with its attendant mode of appreciation.
Formal qualities in the natural environment
The preceding section suggests that the emphasis on formal qualities in the natural
environment is related to and influenced by traditional formalism in art. In view of
this, one way of approaching the issue of the significance of formal qualities in the
aesthetic appreciation and evaluation of the natural environment might be to consider
the plausibility of formalism concerning art. I make some suggestions along these
lines in Chapter 2, but do not take this tack here, for I believe enough has been said
in that chapter and in the literature in general to show the implausibility of such a
formalism.
10
Rather, I approach the issue of the significance of formal qualities by
considering what seems to be implicitly assumed by the views and positions
discussed above. This is the assumption that formal qualities have at least the same
place and importance in our aesthetic appreciation and evaluation of the natural
environment as they have in the appreciation and evaluation of art. Consideration
of this, in turn, requires examining some differences between the natural
environment and works of art.
Further consideration of the scenery cult and the use of photographs is helpful in
this regard as these two factors tend to obscure some differences between the natural
environment and works of art. Let us first consider the scenery cult. This cult, as
noted, puts the accent on perceiving and appreciating the natural environment as if
it were a landscape painting, that is, as a certain kind of prospect seen from a
specific standpoint. The mode of appreciation involved divides the environment
into scenes or blocks of scenery, each of which is to be viewed from a particular
point by a viewer who is separated by an appropriate spatial (and emotional)
distance. Thus a drive through a national park is not unlike a stroll through a gallery
of landscape paintings; we stop at each viewpoint as we pause before each painting.
Seen in this light, the scenery cult seems to have some rather questionable
aspects. These begin to become clear when it is realized that viewing the
environment as if it were a landscape painting means viewing it as a static,
essentially two-dimensional representation. This requires the reduction of the
environment to a scene or view. But the environment is not a scene, not a
representation, not static, and not two-dimensional. The point is that the mode of
appreciation of the scenery cult requires the appreciation of the environment not as
what it is and with the qualities it has, but as something which it is not and with
qualities it does not have. Consequently, when focused on the natural environment,
the scenery cult provides a mode of appreciation that is inappropriate to the actual
34 FORMAL QUALITIES IN THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT
nature of the object of appreciation. This lack of “fit” between the mode and the
object of appreciation is certainly an aesthetic deficiency of the scenery cult.
11
A
similar case of deficiency would arise if we appreciated people aesthetically as if they
were only photographs or portraits of themselves. More common cases are viewing
sculpture as if it were painting or observing a “happening” as if it were a play. The
appropriate mode of appreciation for sculpture calls on us to touch it, to walk
around it, to physically position ourselves in relation to it; for the happening, to
participate in it actively, to be part of it.
Because of this deficiency, the scenery cult obscures a significant difference
between landscape paintings and the natural environment. A painting, unlike the
natural environment, is to be appreciated from a specific point external to it and
with only one sense, the sense of sight. This difference is also obscured by the other
factor mentioned previously, that is, the use of photographs in empirical research.
When a photograph is used as a “stand-in” for the actual environment, the mode of
appreciation of the scenery cult is in essence forced on the appreciator. He or she
views the object of appreciation only with his or her sense of sight and from a
specific external point, because the “stand-in,” the photograph, must be so viewed.
There is no point in smelling or touching the photograph, or in walking around it;
and one cannot, of course, walk around in it. But with the actual object of appreciation
—the natural environment—all these things are not only possible, they are also
appropriate and have a very real point. The point is that they contribute to the full,
rich aesthetic appreciation that the natural environment both allows and
encourages. Whether we realize it or not, we are necessarily in the natural
environment when we appreciate it aesthetically, and often we are moving around in
it and around parts of it. Ronald Hepburn puts the point as follows:
On occasion he [the spectator] may confront natural objects as a static,
disengaged observer; but far more typically the objects envelop him on all
sides. In a forest, trees surround him; he is ringed by hills, or he stands in the
midst of a plain. If there is movement in the scene, the spectator may himself
be in motion and his motion may be an important element in his aesthetic
experience.
12
Thus aesthetic appreciation of the natural environment is not simply a matter of
looking at objects or “views” from a specific point. Rather, it is being “in the midst
of them, moving in regard to them, looking at them from any and every point and
distance and, of course, not only looking, but also smelling, hearing, touching,
feeling. It is being in the environment, being a part of the environment, and
reacting to it as a part of it. It is such active, involved aesthetic appreciation, rather
than the formal mode of appreciation nurtured by the scenery cult and encouraged
by photographs, that is appropriate to the natural environment.
13
Before the ramifications of this point are pursued, another difference between art
and the natural environment—one having to do with the objects of appreciation
rather than with appropriate modes of appreciation—needs to be examined. Again
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 35
the scenery cult is revealing. It encourages perceiving and appreciating the natural
environment as if it were a landscape painting, and it traditionally depended on
devices such as the Claude-glass and more recently on the camera viewfinder to
achieve this. Such devices are important because they help “frame,” and compose
within the frame, a section of the actual environment. In a similar way, landscape
painters rely on the diminishing glass and the motive cutter in deciding on
landscape subjects. The latter device is said to “help to determine the exact
proportions, or limits of a subject best” and is equipped with “a sliding crossbar to be
moved until the right proportions have been found.”
14
The point is that if we wish
to discern a potential landscape painting in the natural environment or to perceive
and appreciate that environment as if it were a landscape painting, the relevant part
of the environment must be framed or cut apart from the rest in some manner. This
is because of an obvious but important difference between traditional art objects and
the natural environment: the former, but not the latter, are framed or delineated in
some formal way.
15
This difference is not only de-emphasized by the scenery cult,
but is also obscured by the use of photographs and slides as both a means of
conducting empirical research and a way of (vicariously) appreciating the natural
environment. Photographs and slides, like traditional works of art, are framed and,
depending on the skill of the photographer, are poorly or well composed within that
frame.
The presence or absence of a frame has significance for formal qualities. For
example, traditional art objects are (or are not) unified or balanced within their frames
and in relation to their frames. This is obvious not only from the art objects
themselves, but also from the way individuals are taught to create them. Art
students are urged to think of their works not just as designs or compositions
simpliciter, but as being designed into a frame or composed within a frame. They are
taught to pay attention to the “negative spaces” within their works, that is, the
shapes formed by the outside edges of their designs and shapes and the inside edges
of the frame. The point is that when an object such as a traditional work of art is
framed in some way, formal qualities are in large part determined by the frame.
Consequently, since the frame is static and the object is appreciated within its
frame, its formal qualities are an important determinate aspect of the work itself.
Formal qualities in art, therefore, can be easily appreciated and evaluated; in fact
they must be in order to achieve full appreciation and correct evaluation of the work.
As for the natural environment, consider the following example. Near Jasper,
Alberta, Canada, there are six cabins with large windows overlooking a majestic,
mountain-ringed lake. To one standing outside these cabins, the natural
environment appears neither balanced nor unbalanced, neither unified nor chaotic.
But to one sitting inside one of them across from a window, the view framed by the
window is striking in its balance and unity; to one standing across from the
window, however, the view is partly destroyed by a lack of balance resulting from
the top of the window frame obscuring the peak of the highest mountain. This
example suggests a distinction between the natural environment and any particular
framed view of that environment. It further suggests that it is the latter rather than
36 FORMAL QUALITIES IN THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT
the former that can be properly said to have formal qualities. As the example shows,
the natural environment itself only appears to have formal qualities when, in one
way or another, a person imposes a frame upon it and thus formally composes the
resultant view. And in such a case it is the framed view that has the qualities.
Moreover, the formal qualities of such a view will vary depending upon the frame
and the viewer’s position. In fact, for any part of the environment there are a near
infinity of possible frames and positions that would in turn produce a near infinity
of different formal qualities in a near infinity of different views. The natural
environment itself might at best be seen as only a “source” of different views, each with
somewhat different formal qualities. Given this situation, it might be concluded
that insofar as the natural environment has formal qualities, they are qualities with a
certain built-in indeterminateness, making them difficult to appreciate and
accordingly a relatively insignificant aspect of the aesthetic appreciation and
evaluation of that environment.
16
I think that the above position is essentially correct as far as it goes. However, I
also think that a somewhat stronger position—that the natural environment as such
does not possess formal qualities—is worth considering. The argument for this
stronger position can be developed from the earlier conclusion that the appropriate
mode of aesthetic appreciation of the natural environment is the active, involved
appreciation of one who is in the environment, being a part of and reacting to it.
This conclusion is significant in that it is inconsistent with framing the
environment. In framing a section of the environment, one must become a static
observer who is separate from that section and who views it from a specific external
point. But one cannot be engaged in the appropriate active, involved appreciation
while maintaining the static, external point of view required for framing. In short,
one cannot both be in the environment that one appreciates and frame that
environment; if one appreciates the environment by being in it, it is not a framed
environment that one appreciates. Consequently, framing itself must be seen as an
inappropriate way of attempting to aesthetically appreciate and evaluate the natural
environment. Without imposing a frame on the natural environment, however, it is
not possible to see it as having formal qualities. Framing may allow the environment
to be seen as having certain indeterminate formal qualities; without framing, the
environment seemingly has no formal qualities, indeterminate or otherwise. Thus,
when appreciated in the appropriate mode, the natural environment as such has no
formal qualities to appreciate.
I do not think that the above is a very surprising or implausible conclusion.
Seeing its plausibility only requires reflection on the nature of formal qualities and
on the nature of the natural environment. The former predominate in those areas of
art where imposed restraints and limits allow them to be made manifest. The natural
environment, by contrast, has a certain openness and indeterminateness that makes
it an unlikely place to find formal qualities. This has been recognized by landscape
painters who have emphasized that in order to create a landscape painting (to which
formal qualities are, of course, significant), an artist cannot simply copy the
landscape faithfully. Rather, he or she must compose the work such that formal
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 37
qualities arise. The landscape painter Adrian Stokes, in a text on landscape painting,
offers the following advice:
A subject in nature, which has been chosen on account of the appeal it makes
to the artist, can rarely be cut out from its surroundings in such a way that the
composition is not in need of change or modification. It must be invested
with some quality of rhythm or symmetry. To copy each part faithfully, even
in truthful relation to other parts, is not sufficient. All things must be
considered together as forming portions of one design, one harmonious
whole.
17
Santayana, a philosopher with a sense of beauty, also notes that the landscape itself
“has no real unity.” He makes a point similar to that of Stokes, although his
philosophical bent draws him to a further conclusion:
The natural landscape is an indeterminate object: it almost always contains
enough diversity to allow the eye a great liberty in selecting, emphasizing, and
grouping its elements, and it is furthermore rich in suggestion and in vague
emotional stimulus. A landscape to be seen has to be composed…then we feel
that the landscape is beautiful. This is a beauty dependent on reverie, fancy,
and objectified emotion. The promiscuous natural landscape cannot be
enjoyed in any other way.
18
The implication of Santayana’s remarks is clear (and consistent with what I have
argued). The natural environment cannot be appreciated and valued in terms of
formal beauty, that is, the beauty of formal qualities; rather, it must be appreciated
and valued in terms of its other aesthetic dimensions—its various non-formal
aesthetic qualities and, according to Santayana, especially its expressive emotional
qualities: “The promiscuous natural landscape cannot be enjoyed in any other
way.”
19
Conclusion
If Santayana’s insight and what I have argued are correct, the conclusions to be
drawn are clear enough. The assumption that formal qualities have the same place
and importance in the aesthetic appreciation and evaluation of the natural
environment as they do in the appreciation and evaluation of art must be
abandoned, for the natural environment is such that formal qualities have relatively
little place and importance. Consequently, the emphasis should be removed from
formal qualities and, as Santayana suggests, placed on the nonformal aesthetic
qualities of the natural environment. It is thus evident that much current research,
such as that noted in the second section of this chapter, which emphasizes formal
qualities to the near exclusion of other aesthetic qualities, is not only progressing on
an inappropriate basis, but is misleading concerning the nature of aesthetic
38 FORMAL QUALITIES IN THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT
appreciation and evaluation of the natural environment. If we are fully to appreciate
our natural environment and evaluate its aesthetic dimension wisely, then we, and
those carrying out research, must look in other directions.
Notes
1 Aims such as these are evident in much research in this area. See, for example, Elwood
L.Shafer, Jr. and James Meitz, It Seems Possible to Quantify Scenic Beauty in
Photographs, USDA Forest Service Research Paper NE-162, Upper Darby,
Pennsylvania, USDA Northeastern Forest Experiment Station, 1970; Luna
B.Leopold, “Landscape Esthetics: How to Quantify the Scenics of a River Valley,”
Natural History, 1969, vol. 78, pp. 36–45; G.Wright, “Appraisal of Visual Landscape
Qualities in a Region Selected for Accelerated Growth,” Landscape Planning, 1974,
vol. 1, pp. 307–27; and K.D. Fines, “Landscape Evaluation: A Research Project in
East Sussex,” Regional Studies, 1968, vol. 2, pp. 41–55. For a general review of the
literature in this area together with a good selected bibliography, see E.H.Zube,
“Scenery as a Natural Resource: Implications of Public Policy and Problems of
Definition, Description, and Evaluation,” Landscape Architecture, 1973, vol. 63, pp.
125–32. I develop a fuller critique of this research, focusing especially on the work of
Shafer and his colleagues, in “On the Possibility of Quantifying Scenic Beauty,”
Landscape Planning, 1977, vol. 4, pp. 131–72.
2 Robert H.Twiss and R.Burton Litton, “Research on Forest Environmental Design,”
Proceedings: Society of American Foresters, Washington, DC, Society of American
Foresters, 1967, p. 209. In the same proceedings, see also Litton and Twiss, “The
Forest Landscape: Some Elements of Visual Analysis,” pp. 212–14.
3 USDA Forest Service, National Forest Landscape Management, Volume I, USDA
Handbook no. 434, Washington, D.C., Government Printing Office, 1972, pp. 7, 23–
47; and National Forest Landscape Management, Volume II, USDA Handbook no.
462, Washington, DC, Government Printing Office, 1973, pp. 2, 12.
4 For a full account of this methodology, see Shafer and Meitz, op. cit., and Elwood L.
Shafer, Jr., John F.Hamilton, Jr., and Elizabeth A.Schmidt, “Natural Landscape
Preferences: A Predictive Model,” Journal of Leisure Research, 1969, vol. 1, pp 1–19.
5 Clive Bell, Art [1913], New York, G.P.Putnam’s Sons, 1958, p. 45.
6 David Lowenthal, “Not Every Prospect Pleases: What Is Our Criterion for Scenic
Beauty?,” Landscape, 1962–63, vol. 12, pp. 19–23. This quote is from p. 22.
7 See Christopher Hussey, The Picturesque, London, G.P.Putnam’s Sons, 1927 or E.
W.Manwaring, Italian Landscape in XVIII Century England, New York, Oxford
University Press, 1925. For a brief discussion, see R.Rees, “The Scenery Cult:
Changing Landscape Tastes over Three Centuries,” Landscape, 1975, vol. 19, pp. 39–
47.
8 Thomas West, Guide to the Lakes, London, 1778, as quoted in J.T.Odgen, “From
Spatial to Aesthetic Distance in the Eighteenth Century,” Journal of the History of
Ideas, 1974, vol. 35, pp. 63–78. This quote is from pp. 66–7.
9 R.Rees, “The Taste for Mountain Scenery,History Today, 1975, vol. 25, pp. 305–12.
This quote is from p. 312. I consider the mode of appreciation outlined in this
paragraph in more detail in “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” The Journal
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 39
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–76 (reproduced in this volume,
Chapter 4).
10 Concerning art, the case against formalism is nicely developed in John Hospers,
Meaning and Truth in the Arts, Chapel Hill, University of North Carolina Press, 1946,
chap. 4 and Walter Abell, Representation and Form: A Study of Aesthetic Values in
Representational Art, New York, Charles Scribner’s, 1936, passim. Concerning the
natural environment, a significant consideration seems to be the role played in our
appreciation and evaluation by non-formal aesthetic qualities such as expressive
qualities and qualities such as gracefulness, delicacy, and garishness. On this point, see,
for example, R.W.Hepburn, “Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” in H.Osborne (ed.)
Aesthetics in the Modern World, London, Thames and Hudson, 1968; R.A. Smith and
C.M.Smith, “Aesthetics and Environmental Education,Journal of Aesthetic
Education, 1970, vol. 4, pp. 125–40; M.Sagoff, “On Preserving the Natural
Environment,” Yale Law Journal, 1974, vol. 84, pp. 205–67; Fines, op. cit.; Yi-Fu
Tuan, “Man and Nature; An Eclectic Reading” Landscape, 1966, vol. 15, pp. 30–6.
11 Cf.Hepburn, op. cit., pp. 60–5.
12 Ibid., p. 51.
13 I develop the ramifications of these observations more fully in “Appreciation and the
Natural Environment,” op. cit. (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4).
14 Adrian Stokes, Landscape Painting, London, Seeley, Service & Co., 1925, p. 214.
15 Cf.Hepburn, op. cit., pp. 51–2.
16 This appears to be the position of Hepburn, ibid., pp. 52–60 and especially p. 59, and
of Smith and Smith, op. cit., pp. 134–7. Hepburn notes that “natural aesthetic
objects” lack “full determinateness and stability.” This leads him to the conclusion
that “any aesthetic quality in nature is always provisional,” but he further argues that
certain formal qualities highly valued in the arts—for example, unity—are simply not
equally significant in the aesthetic appreciation of nature and, consequently, that the
aesthetic appreciation of nature cannot be restricted to consideration of formal
qualities (pp. 52–3). Smith and Smith conclude that the “feature of being an
ingredient in the perceptual field…makes it difficult to experience in nature the kind
of formal unity, balance, proportion or self-enclosedness that are so important to the
proper perception of works of art,” which explains “why it would be inappropriate…to
respond to nature as one would to a work of art, that is, in terms of its formal
properties of design” (p. 134).
17 Stokes, op. cit., p. 64.
18 George Santayana, The Sense of Beauty [1896], New York, Collier, 1961, p. 99.
19 Cf.Sagoff, op. cit., passim. Although he does not discuss formal qualities as such,
Sagoff seemingly holds a position similar to that of Santayana and to the one which we
have reached here. He attempts “to explain the aesthetic value of natural
environments” by considering “only the expressive qualities of these environments and
not their beauty, considered formally” (p. 248).
40 FORMAL QUALITIES IN THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT
4
APPRECIATION AND THE NATURAL
ENVIRONMENT
The appreciation of art
With art objects there is a straightforward sense in which we know both what and
how to aesthetically appreciate. We know what to appreciate in that, first, we can
distinguish a work and its parts from that which is not it nor a part of it. And,
second, we can distinguish its aesthetically relevant aspects from its aspects without
such relevance. We know that we are to appreciate the sound of the piano in the
concert hall and not the coughing that interrupts it; we know that we are to
appreciate that a painting is graceful, but not that it happens to hang in the Louvre.
In a similar vein, we know how to appreciate in that we know whatacts of
aspection” to perform concerning different works. Paul Ziff says:
…to contemplate a painting is to perform one act of aspection; to scan it is to
perform another; to study, observe, survey, inspect, examine, scrutinize, etc.,
are still other acts of aspection… I survey a Tintoretto, while I scan an
H.Bosch. Thus I step back to look at the Tintoretto, up to look at the Bosch.
Different actions are involved. Do you drink brandy in the way you drink
beer?
1
It is clear that we have such knowledge of what and how to aesthetically appreciate.
It is, I believe, also clear what the grounds are for this knowledge. Works of art are
our own creations; it is for this reason that we know what is and what is not a part of
a work, which of its aspects are of aesthetic significance, and how to appreciate them.
We have made them for the purpose of aesthetic appreciation; in order for them to
fulfil this purpose this knowledge must be accessible. In making an object we know
what we make and thus its parts and its purpose. Hence in knowing what we make
we know what to do with that which we make. In the more general cases the point
is clear enough: in creating a painting, we know that what we make is a painting. In
knowing this we know that it ends at its frame, that its colors are aesthetically
important, but where it hangs is not, and that we are to look at it rather than, say,
listen to it.
All this is involved in what it is to be a painting. Moreover, this point holds for more
particular cases as well. Works of different particular types have different kinds of
boundaries, have different foci of aesthetic significance, and perhaps most important
demand different acts of aspection. In knowing the type we know what and how to
appreciate. Ziff again:
Generally speaking, a different act of aspection is performed in connection
with works belonging to different schools of art, which is why the
classification of style is of the essence. Venetian paintings lend themselves to
an act of aspection involving attention to balanced masses: contours are of no
importance, for they are scarcely to be found. The Florentine school demands
attention to contours, the linear style predominates. Look for light in a
Claude, for color in a Bonnard, for contoured volume in a Signorelli.
2
I take the above to be essentially beyond serious dispute, except as to the details of
the complete account. If it were not the case, our complementary institutions of art
and of the aesthetic appreciation of art would not be as they are. We would not have
the artworld that we do. But the subject of this chapter is not art nor the artworld.
Rather it is the aesthetic appreciation of nature. The question I wish to investigate is
the question of what and how to aesthetically appreciate concerning the natural
environment. It is of interest since the account that is implicit in the above remarks,
and that I believe to be the correct account for art, cannot be applied to the natural
environment without at least some modification. Thus initially the questions of
what and how to appreciate concerning nature appear to be open questions.
Some artistic models for the appreciation of nature
In this section I consider the two artistic paradigms that were introduced in
Chapter 1: the object model and the landscape model. These paradigms seem prima
facie applicable as models for the appreciation of the natural environment. In
considering them I follow tradition in that these paradigms are ones that have been
offered as or assumed to be appropriate models for the appreciation of nature.
However, as suggested in Chapter 1, these models are not as promising as they
initially appear to be.
The first artistic paradigm is the object model. In the artworld
nonrepresentational sculpture best fits this model of appreciation. When we
appreciate such sculpture we appreciate it as the actual physical object that it is. The
qualities to be aesthetically appreciated are the sensuous and design qualities of the
actual object and perhaps certain abstract expressive qualities. The sculpture need
not represent anything external to itself; it need not lead the appreciator beyond
itself; it may be a self-contained aesthetic unit. Consider a Brancusi sculpture—for
example, the famous Bird In Space (1919). It has no representational connections
with the rest of reality and no relational connections with its immediate
42 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
surroundings and yet it has significant aesthetic qualities. It glistens, has balance and
grace, and expresses flight itself.
Clearly it is possible to aesthetically appreciate an object of nature in the way
indicated by this model. For example, we may appreciate a rock or a piece of
driftwood in the same way as we appreciate a Brancusi sculpture: we actually or
contemplatively remove the object from its surroundings and dwell on its sensuous
and design qualities and its possible expressive qualities. Moreover, there are
considerations that support the plausibility of this model for appreciation of the
natural environment. First, natural objects are in fact often appreciated in precisely
this way: mantel pieces are littered with pieces of rock and driftwood. Second, the
model fits well with one feature of natural objects: such objects, like the Brancusi
sculpture, do not have representational ties to the rest of reality. Third and most
important, the model involves an accepted, traditional aesthetic approach. As
Francis Sparshott notes: “When one talks of the aesthetic this or that, one is usually
thinking of it as entering into a subject/object relation.”
3
In spite of these considerations, however, I think there are aspects of the object
model that make it inappropriate for nature. Santayana, in discussing the aesthetic
appreciation of nature (which he calls the love of nature) notes that certain
problems arise because the natural landscape has “indeterminate form.” He then
observes that although the landscape contains many objects which have determinate
forms, “if the attention is directed specifically to them, we have no longer what, by a
curious limitation of the word, is called the love of nature.”
4
I think this limitation
is not as curious as Santayana seems to think it is. The limitation marks the
distinction between appreciating nature and appreciating the objects of nature. The
importance of this distinction is seen by realizing the difficulty of appreciating
nature by means of the object model. For example, on one understanding of the
object model, the objects of nature when so appreciated become “ready mades” or
“found art.” The artworld grants “artistic enfranchisement” to a piece of driftwood
just as it has to Duchamp’s urinal, Fountain (1917), or to the real Brillo cartons
discussed by Arthur Danto.
5
If this magic is successful the result is art. Questions of
what and how to aesthetically appreciate are answered, of course, but concerning art
rather than nature; the appreciation of nature is lost in the shuffle. Appreciating
sculpture which was once driftwood is no closer to appreciating nature than is
appreciating a totem pole that was once a tree or a purse that was once a sow’s ear.
In all such cases the conversion from nature to art (or artifact) is complete; only the
means of conversion are different.
There is, however, another understanding of how the object model applies to the
objects of nature. On this understanding natural objects are simply (actually or
contemplatively) removed from their surroundings, but they do not become art,
they remain natural objects. Here we do not appreciate the objects qua art objects,
but rather qua natural objects. We do not consider the rock on our mantel a
readymade sculpture, we consider it only an aesthetically pleasing rock. In such a
case, as the example of non-representational sculpture suggests, our appreciation is
limited to the sensuous and design qualities of the natural object and perhaps a few
APPRECIATION AND THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT 43
abstract expressive qualities: our rock has a wonderfully smooth and gracefully
curved surface and expresses solidity.
The above suggests that, even when it does not require natural objects to be seen
as art objects, the object model imposes a certain limitation on our appreciation of
natural objects. The limitation is the result of the removal of the object from its
surroundings that the object model requires in order even to begin to provide answers
to questions of what and how to appreciate. But in requiring such a removal the
object model becomes problematic. The object model is most appropriate for those
art objects which are self-contained aesthetic units. These objects are such that neither
the environment of their creation nor the environment of their display are
aesthetically relevant: the removal of a self-contained art object from its
environment of creation will not vary its aesthetic qualities and the environment of
display of such an object should not affect its aesthetic qualities. However, natural
objects possess what we might call an organic unity with their environments of
creation: such objects are a part of and have developed out of the elements of their
environments by means of the forces at work within those environments. Thus the
environments of creation are aesthetically relevant to natural objects. And for this
reason the environments of display are equally relevant in virtue of the fact that
these environments will be either the same as or different from the environments of
creation. In either case the aesthetic qualities of natural objects will be affected.
Consider again our rock: on the mantel it may seem wonderfully smooth and
gracefully curved and expressive of solidity, but in its environment of creation it will
have more and different aesthetic qualities—qualities that are the product of the
relationship between it and its environment. It is here expressive of the particular
forces that shaped and continue to shape it and displays for aesthetic appreciation its
place in and its relation to its environment. Moreover, depending upon its place in
that environment it may not express many of those qualities, for example, solidity—
that it appears to express when on the mantle.
I conclude that the object model, even without changing nature into art, faces a
problem as a paradigm for the aesthetic appreciation of nature. The problem is a
dilemma: either we remove the object from its environment or we leave it where it
is. If the object is removed, the model applies to the object and suggests answers to
the questions of what and how to appreciate. But the result is the appreciation of a
comparatively limited set of aesthetic qualities. On the other hand, if the object is
not removed, the model seemingly does not constitute an adequate model for a very
large part of the appreciation that is possible. Thus it makes little headway with the
what and how questions. In either case the object model does not provide a
successful paradigm for the aesthetic appreciation of nature. It appears after all not a
very “curious limitation” that when our attention is directed specifically toward the
objects in the environment it is not called the love of nature.
The second artistic paradigm for the aesthetic appreciation of nature is that which
I call in Chapter 1 the landscape model. In the artworld this model of appreciation
is illustrated by landscape painting; in fact the model probably owes its existence to
this art form. In one of its favored senses “landscape” indicates a prospect—usually a
44 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
grand prospect—seen from a specific standpoint and distance; a landscape painting
is frequently a representation of such a prospect.
6
When aesthetically appreciating
landscape paintings (or any representative paintings, for that matter) the emphasis is
not on the actual object (the painting) nor on the object represented (the actual
prospect); rather it is on the representation of the object and its represented features.
Thus in landscape painting the appreciative emphasis is on those qualities which
play an essential role in representing a prospect: visual qualities related to coloration
and overall design. These are the qualities that are traditionally significant in
landscape painting and that are the focus of the landscape model of appreciation. We
thus have a model of appreciation that encourages perceiving and appreciating
nature as if it were a landscape painting, as a grand prospect seen from a specific
standpoint and distance. It is a model that centers attention on those aesthetic
qualities of color and design that are seen and best seen at a distance.
As noted in Chapter 3 in connection with formalism, the landscape model as
embodied in the scenery cult has been historically significant in our aesthetic
appreciation of nature.
7
The landscape model is the direct descendant of the scenery
cult’s key concept: the picturesque. This term literally means ‘picturelike’ and
indicates a mode of appreciation by which the natural world is divided into scenes,
each aiming at an ideal dictated by art, especially landscape painting. The concept
guided the aesthetic appreciation of eighteenth-century tourists as they pursued
picturesque scenery with the help of the “Claude-glass.” Named after landscape
artist Claude Lorrain, this small, tinted, convex mirror helped tourists see the
landscape as they would art. Thomas West’s popular guidebook to the Lake District
(first published in 1778) says of the glass:
…where the objects are great and near, it removes them to a due distance, and
shews them in the soft colors of nature, and most regular perspective the eye
can perceive, art teach, or science demonstrate…to the glass is reserved the
finished picture, in highest coloring, and just perspectives.
8
And as also noted in Chapter 3, the influence of the scenery cult continues into the
present as modern tourists similarly reveal their preferences for the landscape model
of appreciation by frequenting “scenic viewpoints” where the actual space between
tourists and the prescribed “view” often constitutes “a due distance” which aids the
impression of “soft colors of nature, and the most regular perspective the eye can
perceive, art teach, or science demonstrate. And the “regularity” of the perspective
is often enhanced by the positioning of the viewpoint itself. Moreover, modern
tourists also desire “the finished picture, in highest coloring, and just perspective”;
whether this be the “scene” framed and balanced in the camera’s viewfinder, the
result of this in the form of a Kodacolor print, or the “artistically” composed
postcard and calendar reproductions of the “scene” that often attract more
appreciation than that which they “reproduce.” Geographer R.Rees has described
the situation as follows:
APPRECIATION AND THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT 45
…the taste has been for a view, for scenery, not for landscape in the original
Dutch—and present geographical—meaning of term, which denotes our
ordinary, everyday surroundings. The average modern sightseer, unlike many
of the Romantic poets and painters who were accomplished naturalists, is
interested not in natural forms and processes, but in a prospect.
9
It is clear that in addition to being historically important, the landscape model, like
the object model, gives us at least initial guidelines as to what and how to appreciate
in nature. We are to appreciate the natural environment as if it were a landscape
painting. The model requires dividing the environment into scenes or blocks of
scenery, each of which is to be viewed from a particular point by a viewer separated
by the appropriate spatial (and emotional?) distance. A drive through the country is
not unlike a walk through a gallery of landscape paintings. When seen in this light,
this model of appreciation causes a certain uneasiness in a number of thinkers.
Some, such as ecologist Paul Shepard, seemingly believe this kind of appreciation of
the natural environment so misguided that they entertain doubts about the wisdom
of any aesthetic approach to nature.
10
Others find the model to be ethically suspect.
For example, after pointing out that the modern sightseer is interested only in a
prospect, Rees concludes:
In this respect the Romantic Movement was a mixed blessing. In certain
phases of its development it stimulated the movement for the protection of
nature, but in its picturesque phase it simply confirmed our anthropocentrism
by suggesting that nature exists to please as well as to serve us. Our ethics, if
the word can be used to describe our attitudes and behavior toward the
environment, have lagged behind our aesthetics. It is an unfortunate lapse
which allows us to abuse our local environments and venerate the Alps and
the Rockies.
11
What has not been as generally noted, however, is the point emphasized in the
previous chapter. This is that this model of appreciation is suspect not only
on ethical grounds, but also on aesthetic grounds. The model requires us to view the
environment as if it were a static representation that is essentially “two
dimensional.” It requires the reduction of the environment to a scene or view. But
what must be kept in mind is that the environment is not a scene, not a
representation, not static, and not two dimensional. The point is that the model
requires the appreciation of the environment not as what it is and with the qualities
it has, but rather as something that it is not and with qualities it does not have. The
model is in fact inappropriate to the actual nature of the object of appreciation.
Consequently it not only, as with the object model, unduly limits our appreciation
—in this case to visual qualities related to color and overall design—it also misleads
it. Ronald Hepburn puts this point in a general way:
46 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
Supposing that a person’s aesthetic education…instills in him the attitudes,
the tactics of approach, the expectations proper to the appreciation of art
works only, such a person will either pay very little aesthetic heed to natural
objects or else heed them in the wrong way. He will look—and of course look
in vain—for what can be found and enjoyed only in art.
12
An environmental model for the appreciation of nature
I conclude that the landscape model, like the object model, is inadequate as a
paradigm for the aesthetic appreciation of nature. However, the reason for its
inadequacy is instructive. The landscape model is inadequate because it is
inappropriate to the nature of the natural environment. Perhaps to see what and
how to appreciate in the natural environment, we must consider the nature of that
environment more carefully. In this regard there are two rather obvious points that I
wish to emphasize. The first is that the natural environment is an environment; the
second is that it is natural.
When we conceptualize the natural environment as “nature” I think we are
tempted to think of it as an object. When we conceptualize it as “landscape” we are
certainly led to thinking of it as scenery. Consequently perhaps the concept of the
“natural environment” is somewhat preferable. At least it makes explicit that it is an
environment that is under consideration. The object model and the landscape model
each in its own way fail to take account of this. But what is involved in taking this
into account? Here I initially follow up some remarks made by Sparshott. He
suggests that to consider something environmentally is primarily to consider it in
regard to the relation of “self to setting,” rather than “subject to object” or “traveler
to scene.
13
An environment is the setting in which we exist as a “sentient part”; it is
our surroundings. Sparshott points out that as our surroundings, our setting, the
environment is that which we take for granted, that which we hardly notice—it is
necessarily unobtrusive. If any one part of it becomes obtrusive, it is in danger of
being seen as an object or a scene, not as our environment. As Sparshott says:
“When a man starts talking about ‘environmental values’ we usually take him to be
talking about aesthetic values of a background sort.”
14
The aesthetic values of the environment being primarily background values has
obvious ramifications for the questions of what and how to appreciate. Concerning
the question of what to appreciate this suggests the answer “everything,” for in an
essentially unobtrusive setting there seems little basis for including and excluding. I
return to this point shortly. Concerning the question of how to appreciate, the answer
suggested is in terms of all those ways in which we normally are aware of and
experience our surroundings. Sparshott notes that “if environmental aspects are
background aspects, eye and ear lose part of their privilege” and goes on to mention
smell, touch, and taste, and even warmth and coolness, barometric pressure and
humidity as possibly relevant.
15
This points in the right direction, but, as Sparshott
also notes, it seems to involve a difficulty—that “the concept of the aesthetic tugs in
a different direction”—the direction of the subject/object relation involving
APPRECIATION AND THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT 47
primarily the visual scrutiny of an aesthetic object.
16
However, I do not think this
difficulty need be as serious as Sparshott seems to think. I suspect the apparent
tension here is not due to the concept of the aesthetic being necessarily tied to the
subject/object relation or to the visual, but rather is due to its being antithetical to
the appreciation of anything only as unobtrusive background. To confirm this we
need to consider the concept of the aesthetic as it is elaborated by John Dewey in
Art as Experience.
17
Dewey’s concept is such that anything that is aesthetically
appreciated must be obtrusive; it must be foreground, but it need not be an object
and it need not be seen (or only seen). Moreover, to assume that that which is
aesthetically appreciated need be an object or only seen is to confine aesthetic
appreciation to either the object model or the landscape model, which, as we have
noted, impose unacceptable limitations on the aesthetic appreciation of the natural
environment.
I suggest then that the beginning of an answer to the question of how to
aesthetically appreciate an environment is something like the following. We must
experience our background setting in all those ways in which we normally
experience it, by sight, smell, touch, and whatever. However, we must experience it
not as unobtrusive background, but as obtrusive foreground. What is involved in
such an “act of aspection” is not completely clear. Dewey gives us an idea in remarks
such as:
To grasp the sources of esthetic experience it is…necessary to have recourse to
animal life below the human scale… The live animal is fully present, all there,
in all of its actions: in its wary glances, its sharp sniffing, its abrupt cocking of
ears. All senses are equally on the qui vive.
18
And perhaps the following description by Yi-Fu Tuan gives some further
indication:
An adult must learn to be yielding and careless like a child if he were to enjoy
nature polymorphously. He needs to slip into old clothes so that he could feel
free to stretch out on the hay beside the brook and bathe in a meld of physical
sensations: the smell of the hay and of horse dung; the warmth of the ground,
its hard and soft contours; the warmth of the sun tempered by breeze; the
tickling of an ant making its way up the calf of his leg; the play of shifting leaf
shadows on his face; the sound of water over the pebbles and boulders, the
sound of cicadas and distant traffic. Such an environment might break all the
formal rules of euphony and aesthetics, substituting confusion for order, and
yet be wholly satisfying.
19
Tuan’s account as to how to appreciate fits well with our earlier answer to the
question of what to appreciate, namely everything. This answer, of course, will not
do. We cannot appreciate everything; there must be limits and emphases in our
aesthetic appreciation of nature as there are in our appreciation of art. Without such
48 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
limits and emphases our experience of the natural environment would be only “a
meld of physical sensations” without any meaning or significance. It would be a
Jamesian “blooming, buzzing confusion” that truly substituted “confusion for
order” and, I suspect contra to Tuan, would not be wholly satisfying.
20
Such
experience would be too far removed from our aesthetic appreciation of art to merit
the label “aesthetic” or even the label “appreciation.” Consider again the case of art.
In this case, as noted in the first section of this chapter, the boundaries and foci of
aesthetic significance of works of art are a function of the type of art in question,
e.g., paintings end at their frames and their colors are significant. Moreover, I
suggested that our knowledge of such matters is due to art works being our
creations. Here it is relevant to note the second point that I wish to emphasize
about natural environments: they are natural. The natural environment is not a
work of art. As such it has no boundaries or foci of aesthetic significance that are
given as a result of our creation nor of which we have knowledge because of our
involvement in such creation.
The fact that nature is natural—not our creation—does not mean, however, that
we must be without knowledge of it. Natural objects are such that we can discover
things about them that are independent of any involvement by us in their creation.
Thus, although we have not created nature, we yet know a great deal about it. This
knowledge, essentially common-sense/scientific knowledge, seems to me the only
viable candidate for playing the role concerning the appreciation of nature that our
knowledge of types of art, artistic traditions, and the like plays concerning the
appreciation of art. Consider the aesthetic appreciation of an environment such as
that described by Tuan. We experience the environment as obtrusive foreground—
the smell of the hay and of the horse dung, the feel of the ant, the sound of the
cicadas and of the distant traffic all force themselves upon us. We experience a
“meld of sensationsbut, as noted, if our state is to be aesthetic appreciation rather
than just the having of raw experience, the meld cannot be simply a “blooming,
buzzing confusion.” Rather it must be what Dewey called a consummatory
experience: one in which knowledge and intelligence transform raw experience by
making it determinate, harmonious, and meaningful. For example, in order for
there to be aesthetic appreciation we must recognize the smell of the hay and that of
the horse dung and perhaps distinguish between them; we must feel the ant at least
as an insect rather than as, say, a twitch. Such recognizing and distinguishing results
in certain aspects of the obtrusive foreground becoming foci of aesthetic significance.
Moreover, they are natural foci appropriate to the particular natural environment
we are appreciating. Likewise our knowledge of the environment may yield certain
appropriate boundaries or limits to the experience. For example, since we are
aesthetically appreciating a certain kind of environment, the sound of cicadas may
be appreciated as a proper part of the setting, while the sound of the distant traffic is
excluded much as we ignore the coughing in the concert hall.
What I am suggesting is that the question of what to aesthetically appreciate in the
natural environment is to be answered in a way analogous to the similar question
about art. The difference is that in the case of the natural environment the relevant
APPRECIATION AND THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT 49
knowledge is the common-sense/scientific knowledge that we have discovered about
the environment in question. This knowledge gives us the appropriate foci of
aesthetic significance and the appropriate boundaries of the setting so that our
experience becomes one of aesthetic appreciation. If to aesthetically appreciate art
we must have knowledge of artistic traditions and styles within those traditions, to
aesthetically appreciate nature we must have knowledge of the different
environments of nature and of the systems and elements within those
environments. In the way in which the art critic and the art historian are well
equipped to aesthetically appreciate art, the naturalist and the ecologist are well
equipped to aesthetically appreciate nature.
21
This point about what to appreciate in nature also has ramifications for how to
appreciate nature. In discussing the nature of an environment, I suggest that Tuan’s
description seems to indicate a general act of aspection appropriate for any
environment. However, since natural environments differ in type it seems that
within this general act of aspection there might be differences which should be
noted. To aesthetically appreciate an environment we experience our surroundings
as obtrusive foreground, allowing our knowledge of that environment to select
certain foci of aesthetic significance and perhaps exclude others, thereby limiting the
experience. But certainly there are also different kinds of appropriate acts of
aspection which can likewise be selected by our knowledge of environments. Ziff
tells us to look for contours in the Florentine school and for color in a Bonnard, to
survey a Tintoretto and to scan a Bosch. Consider different natural environments. It
seems that we must survey a prairie environment, looking at the subtle contours of
the land, feeling the wind blowing across the open space, and smelling the mix of
prairie grasses and flowers. But such an act of aspection has little place in a dense
forest environment. Here we must examine and scrutinize, inspecting the detail of
the forest floor, listening carefully for the sounds of birds, and smelling carefully for
the scent of spruce and pine. Likewise, the description of environmental
appreciation given by Tuan, in addition to being a model for environmental acts of
aspection in general, is also a description of the act of aspection appropriate for a
particular kind of environment—one perhaps best described as pastoral. Different
natural environments require different acts of aspection; and as in the case of what
to appreciate, our knowledge of the environment in question indicates how to
appreciate—that is, indicates the appropriate act of aspection.
The model I thus suggest for the aesthetic appreciation of nature is that which is
introduced in Chapter 1 as the natural environmental model. It involves recognizing
that nature is an environment and thus a setting within which we exist and that we
normally experience with our complete range of senses as our unobtrusive
background. But in order for our experience to be aesthetic requires unobtrusive
background to be experienced as obtrusive foreground. The result is the experience
of ablooming, buzzing confusion that in order to be appreciated must be
tempered by the knowledge we have discovered about the natural environment so
experienced. Our knowledge of the nature of the particular environments yields the
appropriate boundaries of appreciation, the particular foci of aesthetic significance,
50 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
and the relevant act or acts of aspection for that type of environment. We thus have
a model that begins to give answers to the questions of what and how to appreciate
in the natural environment and that seems to do so with due regard for the nature
of that environment. And this is important not only for aesthetic but also for moral
and ecological reasons.
Conclusion
In this chapter, in addressing the question of what and how to aesthetically
appreciate concerning nature, I contend that two traditional approaches, each of
which more or less assimilates the appreciation of nature to the appreciation of
certain art forms, leave much to be desired. However, the approach I suggest, the
natural environmental model, yet follows closely the general structure of our
aesthetic appreciation of art. This approach does not depend on an assimilation of
natural objects to art objects nor of landscapes to scenery, but rather on an
application of the general structure of aesthetic appreciation of art to something that
is not art. What is important is to recognize that nature is an environment and is
natural, and to make that recognition central to our aesthetic appreciation. Thereby
we will aesthetically appreciate nature for what it is and for the qualities it has. And
we will avoid being the person described by Hepburn who “will either pay very little
aesthetic heed to natural objects or else heed them in the wrong way,” who “will look
—and of course look in vain—for what can be found and enjoyed only in art.”
22
Notes
1 Paul Ziff, “Reasons in Art Criticism,” Philosophical Turnings, Essays in Conceptual
Appreciation, Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1966, p. 71.
2 Ibid. Ziff is mainly concerned with the way in which knowledge of types yields
different acts of aspection. For an elaboration of this point and its ramifications
concerning what is and is not aesthetically significant in a work, see K.Walton,
“Categories of Art,” Philosophical Review, 1970, vol. 79, pp. 334–67. How our
knowledge of art and the artworld yields the boundaries between art and the rest of
reality is interestingly discussed in A.Danto, “The Artistic Enfranchisement of Real
Objects, the Artworld,” Journal of Philosophy, 1964, vol. 61, pp. 571–84.
3 F.E.Sparshott, “Figuring the Ground: Notes on Some Theoretical Problems of the
Aesthetic Environment,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1972, vol. 6, p. 13.
4 George Santayana, The Sense of Beauty [1896], New York, Collier, 1961, p. 100.
5 Danto, op. cit., p. 579. On issues about turning objects into art, see the institutional
theory of art; the classic account is G.Dickie, Art and the Aesthetic, An Institutional
Analysis, Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1974.
6 This favored sense of “landscape” is brought out by Yi-Fu Tuan. See Topophilia, A
Study of Environmental Perception, Attitudes, and Values, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice
Hall, 1974, pp. 132–3, or “Man and Nature, An Eclectic Reading,” Landscape, 1966,
vol. 15, p. 30.
APPRECIATION AND THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT 51
7 For a good brief discussion of this point, see R.Rees, “The Scenery Cult: Changing
Landscape Tastes over Three Centuries,” Landscape, 1975, vol. 19. Note the following
remarks by E.H.Gombrich in “The Renaissance Theory of Art and the Rise of
Landscape,” Norm and Form: Studies in the Art of the Renaissance, London, Phaidon,
1971, pp. 117–18:
I believe that the idea of natural beauty as an inspiration of art…is, to
say the least, a very dangerous oversimplification. Perhaps it even
reverses the actual process by which man discovers the beauty of nature.
We call a scenery “picturesque”…if it reminds us of paintings we have
seen… Similarly, so it seems, the discovery of Alpine scenery does not
precede but follows the spread of prints and paintings with mountain
panoramas.
8Thomas West, Guide to the Lakes [1778], quoted in J.T.Ogden, “From Spatial to
Aesthetic Distance in the Eighteenth Century,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 1974,
vol. 35, pp. 66–7.
9 R.Rees, “The Taste for Mountain Scenery,” History Today, 1975, vol. 25, p 312.
10 Paul Shepard, The Tender Carnivore and the Sacred Game, New York, Scribner, 1973,
pp. 147–8. Shepard made this position more explicit at a lecture at Athabasca
University, Edmonton, Alberta, November 16, 1974.
11 Rees, “Mountain Scenery,” op. cit., p. 312. Ethical worries are also expressed by Tuan,
Topophilia, op. cit., Chapter 8, and R.A.Smith and C.M.Smith, “Aesthetics and
Environmental Education,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1970, vol. 4, pp. 131–2.
Smith and Smith put the point as follows:
Perhaps there is a special form of arrogance in experiencing nature
strictly in the categories of art, for the attitude involved here implies an
acceptance, though perhaps only momentarily, of the notion that
natural elements have been arranged for the sake of the man’s aesthetic
pleasure. It is possible that this is what Kant had in mind when he said
that in the appreciation of natural beauty one ought not assume that
nature has fashioned its forms for our delight and that, instead, “it is we
who receive nature with favor, and not nature that does us a favor.”
12 R.W.Hepburn, “Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” in H.Osborne (ed.) Aesthetics and
the Modern World, London, Thames and Hudson, 1968, p. 53. Hepburn argues that
our aesthetic appreciation of nature is enhanced by our “realizing” that an object is
what it is and has the qualities it has. See pp. 60–5.
13 Sparshott, op. cit., pp. 12–13. Sparshott also considers other possible relations not
directly relevant here. Moreover, I suspect he considers the “traveller to scene” relation
to be more significant than I do.
14 Ibid., pp. 17–18.
15 Ibid., p. 21.
16 Ibid., pp. 13–14, p. 21.
52 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
17 John Dewey, Art as Experience [1934], New York, G.P.Putnam’s Sons, 1958,
especially Chapter 3, “Having an Experience,” pp. 35–57.
18 Ibid., pp. 18–19.
19 Tuan, Topophilia, op. cit., p. 96.
20 William James, The Principles of Psychology [1890], Cambridge, Massachusetts,
Harvard University Press, 1983, p. 462.
21 I have in mind here individuals such as John Muir and Aldo Leopold. See, for
example, Muir’s Our National Parks, New York, Houghton Mifflin, 1916, or
Leopold’s A Sand County Almanac, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1949.
22 Hepburn, op. cit., p. 53.
APPRECIATION AND THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT 53
54
5
NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND
OBJECTIVITY
Nature and objectivity
In this chapter, I consider the view that some aesthetic judgments about nature and
natural objects (e.g., “The Grand Tetons are majestic”) are appropriate, correct, or
perhaps simply true; while others (e.g., “The Grand Tetons are dumpy”) are
inappropriate, incorrect, or perhaps simply false. If one accepts some such view, one
discovers that the opposition falls into two clearly distinguishable groups. On the
one hand, there are those who hold that such views are untenable concerning
aesthetic judgments in general, whether a judgment be about nature or about art—
whether it be “The Grand Tetons are majestic” or “Donatello’s David is dumpy.”
Such objectors often hold some version of a subjectivist, a relativist, and/or a
noncognitivist view about all so-called aesthetic judgments. On the other hand,
there are those who reject these latter views concerning aesthetic judgments about
art, but have serious reservations about rejecting them concerning such judgments
about nature. These objectors readily admit and often defend the view that a
statement such as, for example, “Guernica is dynamic is appropriate, correct, or
true, but find a statement such as “The Grand Tetons are majestic” somewhat
worrisome—at least in their theoretical moments, if not in their actual practice. The
remarks of this chapter are addressed to only the latter group of objectors. To
consider the issues raised by the former group would require not only a much more
substantial investigation, but also one with an essentially different focus.
Although the position of the latter group is quite common among aestheticians,
it can be properly discussed only by considering a concrete example. One such
example is found in Kendall Walton’s important essay “Categories of Art.”
1
I select
Walton’s position for consideration for two reasons. First, it presents a persuasive
and well-developed account of the truth and falsity of aesthetic judgments about
art, an account that does not directly apply to aesthetic judgments about nature, and
thus appears to necessitate a relativist view in regard to these judgments. Second, the
position is developed in such a way that it makes possible a clear understanding of
why aestheticians might hold an essentially objectivist view concerning aesthetic
judgments about art and yet a relativist view concerning those about nature. My
general point in considering Walton’s position is to demonstrate that a somewhat
analogous position does in fact apply to aesthetic judgments about nature. If this is
the case, then to the extent that positions of this general type underwrite the
objectivity of aesthetic judgments about art, the objectivity of aesthetic judgments
about nature is similarly underwritten.
Walton’s position
To begin we must have at our disposal a brief and schematic account of Walton’s
position together with his reservations concerning its applicability to aesthetic
judgments about nature.
2
Essentially Walton holds that the truth value of aesthetic
judgments about a work of art is a function of two things: first, the (nonaesthetic)
perceptual properties a work actually has, and second, the perceived status of such
perceptual properties when a work is perceived in its correct category or categories of
art. He provides evidence for the psychological claim that the aesthetic judgments
that seem true or false of a work are a function of the perceived status of its
perceptual properties, given any category in which the work is perceived; he argues
for the philosophical claim that the aesthetic judgments that are true or false of a work
are a function of the perceived status of its perceptual properties, given that the
work is perceived in its correct category or categories.
3
He then provides four
circumstances which count toward the correctness of perceiving a work in a category
(see below).
Illustration 2 The Grand Tetons, Wyoming (Courtesy of Corbis/Ansel Adams Trust).
56 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
The above sketch is most succinctly elaborated by means of an example. Consider
Guernica is awkward. If this aesthetic judgment is false, it is false as a function of
the perceptual properties of Guernica (1937), that is, its lines, colors, forms. With
this few would disagree. Walton goes further to point out that Guernica can be
perceived in different (perceptually distinguishable) categories of art.
4
It can be
perceived, for example, as a painting, as an impressionist painting, or as a cubist
painting. With respect to such categories of art, certain perceptual properties are
what Walton calls standard, contrastandard, and variable.
5
For example, flatness is
standard for all three of the above-mentioned categories, being colored is variable
for all three, but having predominately cube-like shapes is variable for the first,
contra-standard for the second, and standard for the third. The perceived status of
perceptual properties as standard, variable, or contra-standard is thus a function of
the category in which the work is perceived.
6
If Guernica is perceived as a cubist
painting, its cube-like shapes will be perceived as standard; if it is perceived as an
impressionist painting these same shapes will be perceived as contrastandard (or
possibly as variable). Walton’s psychological claim is that this perceived status
affects which aesthetic judgments seem true or false to a perceiver on an occasion.
Guernica is awkward” may seem a true judgment when the painting is seen in the
category of impressionist paintings, for its cube-like shapes will be perceived as
contra-standard (or variable) and thus as counting toward awkwardness. The same
judgment will seem false, however, when the painting is seen in the category of
cubist paintings, for then its cubelike shapes will be perceived as standard and
consequently as counting toward awkwardness no more than its flatness as a
painting, for example, is perceived as counting toward its representing flat objects.
7
But is “Guernica is awkward” really true or really false? Walton’s philosophical
claim is that this depends on the perceived status of the perceptual properties when
Guernica is perceived in its correct category. In this particular case the aesthetic
judgment in question is false because Guernica is correctly perceived as a cubist
painting; thus the perceived status of its cube-like shapes does not count toward
awkwardness. The four circumstances that count toward it being correct to perceive
Guernica as a cubist painting are:
that it has a relatively large number of properties standard with respect to cubism;
that it is a better painting when perceived as a cubist painting;
that Picasso intended or expected it to be perceived as a cubist painting;
that the category of cubist paintings was well established in and recognized by
the society in which Guernica was produced.
Walton argues that generalized versions of these four circumstances are relevant to
determining the correct category within which to perceive any work of art.
8
It follows from Walton’s account that, in order to determine the truth value of an
aesthetic judgment such as “Guernica is awkward,” it will not do simply to look at
Guernica, as it will if we wish to determine the truth value of “Guernica is colored.”
Rather, we must perceive Guernica in its correct category. This requires two kinds
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 57
of knowledge. First, the knowledge that certain factors make cubism its correct
category and consequently that cubism is its correct category; that is, certain factual
knowledge about the history and nature of twentieth-century art. And second, the
knowledge how to perceive Guernica as a cubist work; that is, certain practical
knowledge or skill that must be acquired by training and experience concerning the
category of cubist paintings and other related categories of art. In short, simply
“examining a work with the senses can by itself reveal neither how it is correct to
perceive it, nor how to perceive it that way.”
9
We are now in a position to consider the relevance of a Walton-like position to
aesthetic judgments about nature. Walton holds that his philosophical claim is not
applicable to most aesthetic judgments about nature, and that these judgments are
perhaps better understood in terms of what he calls the categoryrelative
interpretation. On this interpretation aesthetic judgments are relativized to any
category in which a person happens to perceive something. For example, if this
interpretation were applied to aesthetic judgments about works of art, then
judgments such asGuernica is awkward” and Guernica is not awkward” need not
be incompatible, for the first may amount to the judgment that “Guernica is
awkward as an impressionist painting,” and the second to the judgment that
Guernica is not awkward as a cubist painting.” Walton argues that, in regard to
aesthetic judgments about art, this interpretation is inadequate for it does not allow
such aesthetic judgments to be mistaken often enough. We say that the judgment
Guernica is awkward is simply wrong, false; we say that the individual making
such a judgment does not appreciate the work because he or she perceives it
incorrectly. Similarly, we say that judgments we ourselves made about works before
we appreciated them properly were simply false or wrong. But the category-relative
interpretation does not allow for these facts; thus, in order to accommodate them
we must accept that certain ways of perceiving works of art are correct and others
incorrect.
However, although Walton rejects the category-relative interpretation of
judgments about art, he proposes it for aesthetic judgments about nature. He says:
“I think that aesthetic judgments are in some contexts amenable to such category-
relative interpretations, especially aesthetic judgments about natural objects (clouds,
mountains, sunsets) rather than works of art.”
10
He suggests that we simply attribute
aesthetic properties to natural objects in the same way in which we could, or would
have to, concerning a work of art “about whose origins we know absolutely
nothing” and that we are, consequently, not “in a position to judge…
aesthetically.
11
Nature and culture
It should be clear that Walton’s account is a concrete example of one of the positions
mentioned at the beginning of this chapter: aesthetic judgments about art are true
or false and can be determined as such, but aesthetic judgments about nature are in
some sense subjective or relative. Walton has an essentially objectivist account of
58 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
aesthetic judgments about art and yet a relativist account of those about nature.
Concerning the latter, the implicit view is that such judgments are relative to the
way in which a perceiver happens to perceive a part of nature or a natural object on
a particular occasion. There seem to be no essentially correct or incorrect categories
in which to perceive nature, and thus with nature one can only attribute to it certain
aesthetic properties rather than judge which aesthetic properties it has. With nature
it appears to be a matter of aesthetically appreciating whatever one can and as much
as one can, but not a matter of getting it aesthetically right or wrong, not a matter of
making true or false aesthetic judgments.
This position has an initial implausibility that leads one to ask why Walton and
other aestheticians accept it. Its implausibility can be seen by noting that not only
do many aesthetic judgments about nature strike us as clearly true (e.g., “The Grand
Tetons are majestic”) or clearly false (e.g., “The Grand Tetons are dumpy”), but also
that many of such judgments seem to be paradigmatic aesthetic judgments—ones in
virtue of which we initially grasp aesthetic concepts (e.g., graceful gazelle, majestic
mountain, sublime sunset). In light of these considerations a position that bifurcates
the class of aesthetic judgments and suggests an essentially different and weaker
philosophical account of those about nature than of those about art seems
counterintuitive. If such an account is inadequate, it might be suggested that this is
due to the fact that, as explained in Chapter 1, aestheticians have until very recently
paid relatively little attention to the aesthetics of nature.
12
However, although it is
perhaps true that philosophers hold less adequate views about that to which they
give less attention, this cannot be the complete explanation for a position such as
that sketched above. There are more important reasons that can be made explicit by
further considering our example.
As we saw above, Walton provides four circumstances that count toward it being
correct to perceive a work in a given category of art. The latter two circumstances
are respectively that the artist who produced the work intended or expected it to be
perceived in a certain category or thought of it as being in that category, and that
the category in question is well established in and recognized by the society in which
the work is produced. These circumstances cannot count toward it being correct to
perceive parts of nature or natural objects in certain categories, for nature is not
produced by artists who intend or expect it to be perceived in certain ways and it is
not produced within certain societies. Consequently an important aspect of
Walton’s philosophical account is, as Walton says, “not readily applicable to most
judgments about natural objects.”
13
Essentially, this is because works of art are
produced by artists within societies and nature is not. Moreover, not only are works
of art the products of societies, but in a similar way so are the categories of art
themselves. Consequently, not only do the circumstances for a category being
correct not readily apply to nature, but the categories themselves do not apply. In
short, nature does not fit into categories of art.
These remarks enable us to see more clearly the basic reason why some
aestheticians hold an essentially objectivist view concerning aesthetic judgments
about art and a relativist view concerning those about nature. In short, it is because
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 59
the objectivity of the former class of aesthetic judgments is based on a certain kind of
account of the nature of aesthetic appreciation, aesthetic qualities, and/or aesthetic
objects. The relevant accounts are in some sense societal, institutional, or more
generally, cultural.
14
The two circumstances of Walton mentioned above make
reference to certain cultural facts and his categories are themselves culturally
established and maintained. It is the difficulty of bringing aesthetic judgments
about nature into the general framework of these cultural accounts that seemingly
leads aestheticians to abandon such judgments to relativism.
15
Once it is clear that cultural accounts of the aesthetic are the basic reason for a
bifurcated view of aesthetic judgments, we might be tempted to remedy the
situation by rejecting such accounts. However, although there are philosophical
problems with these accounts, I think this temptation should be resisted.
16
Cultural
accounts of the aesthetic are simply more promising than other alternatives.
Consequently, in regard to the aesthetics of nature, the interesting issue is the extent
to which we can develop an analogous account which applies to aesthetic judgments
about nature. In order to pursue this issue we must consider carefully the important
differences between art and nature that cultural accounts of the aesthetic force to
our attention. I have briefly indicated these differences in this section, but they need
to be further discussed if we are to move toward a unified account of aesthetic
judgments. I return to them shortly. Initially, however, it is fruitful to see exactly
how much of a cultural account roughly of the kind outlined by Walton does
directly apply to nature and how well it applies. This will allow us to see more
clearly exactly what and how much needs to be said about these differences in order
to achieve a unified account.
Nature and Walton’s psychological claim
Walton’s position embodies not only a philosophical claim but also a psychological
claim. The latter is the claim that the aesthetic judgments that seem true or false of a
work are a function of the perceptual status of its perceptual properties given any
category in which the work is perceived. I think that a similar psychological claim
can be demonstrated to hold for aesthetic judgments about nature. In fact Walton
presents one case which suggests that this is so:
A small elephant, one which is smaller than most elephants with which we are
familiar, might impress us as charming, cute, delicate, or puny. This is not
simply because of its (absolute) size, but because it is small for an elephant. To
people who are familiar not with our elephants but with a race of mini-
elephants, the same animal may look massive, strong, dominant, threatening,
lumbering, if it is large for a mini-elephant. The size of elephants is variable
relative to the class of elephants, but it varies only within a certain (not
precisely specifiable) range. It is a standard property of elephants that they do
fall within this range. How an elephant’s size affects us aesthetically depends,
60 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
since we see it as an elephant, on whether it falls in the upper, middle or
lower part of the range.
17
This case illustrates the application of the psychological claim to natural objects and
provides an example of a relevant category with properties standard, variable, and
contra-standard in respect to that category. The category is that of elephants, a
perceptually distinguishable category in which we do perceive certain natural objects
—under most conditions, elephants. With respect to this category, size is a variable
property while the limits of range on size is a standard property. Thus the small
elephant’s size is variable in this example. However, were the elephant small enough
to fall outside the limits set by the standard property—for example, the size of a large
mouse—its size would be contrastandard. In such a case, if we could still perceive it
in the category of elephants, other aesthetic judgments would seem true. In addition
to (or as opposed to) appearing delicate, it might appear frail or fragile. And it
would certainly strike us as being surprising or disconcerting—aesthetic properties
related to certain contra-standard perceptual properties. The point illustrated by this
case generally holds true for similar cases. Consider, for example, the aesthetic
judgments we take to be true of Shetland ponies (charming, cute) and Clydesdale
horses (majestic, lumbering). These judgments are made with respect to the category
of horses. Similarly a foal (calf, fawn, etc.) typically strikes us as delicate and nimble
when seen in the category of horses (cattle, deer, etc.), but a particularly husky one
may strike us as lumbering or perhaps awkward if seen in the category of foals (calves,
fawns, etc.).
In the above example, particular natural kinds (elephants, horses) constitute
categories that function psychologically as do categories of art; and our aesthetic
appreciation is directed toward a natural object. We also need, however, to consider
the application of the psychological claim to a somewhat different kind of example—
the aesthetic appreciation of landscapes or of natural environments. In discussing
the enriching of aesthetic appreciation, Ronald Hepburn describes the following
case:
Supposing I am walking over a wide expanse of sand and mud. The quality of
the scene is perhaps that of wild, glad emptiness. But suppose that I bring to
bear upon the scene my knowledge that this is a tidal basin, the tide being
out. I see myself now as virtually walking on what is for half the day sea-bed.
The wild, glad emptiness may be tempered by a disturbing weirdness.
18
This case may be elaborated as follows. Note that what is described is a change in
which aesthetic judgments seem true of the “wide expanse of sand and mud,” and
this change is a function of perceiving the expanse in different ways. Initially it is
apparently perceived as a beach, but then due to the realization that it is half the day
under the sea, it is perceived as a sea-bed. Here beach and sea-bed—along the tidal
basin—function as categories.
19
These categories are perceptually distinguishable in
terms of their perceptual properties, and we can and do perceive things such as a
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 61
“wide expanse of sand and mud” as in or as belonging to them. Moreover, such
perceiving is not a matter of inferring, but rather a matter of simply seeing the
expanse in the relevant categories given our experience and knowledge. It is a matter
of perceiving a number of perceptual properties characteristic of (standard for) these
categories combined into a single Gestalt (see footnote 6).
Once we recognize beach and sea-bed as categories, the aesthetic judgments that
Hepburn mentions can be accounted for in terms of standard, variable, and contra-
standard properties in respect to such categories. Perceiving the expanse in the
category of sea-beds (as opposed to beaches) results in its appearing to possess a
“disturbing weirdness.” The property of being relatively dry (or above water) and
thus such that it can be walked upon is a standard property with respect to beaches
and contra-standard with respect to sea-beds. Dryness is among those properties in
virtue of which such an expanse belongs to the category of beaches and which tends
to disqualify it from belonging to the category of sea-beds (see footnote 5). Thus
perceiving the expanse in the category of sea-beds results in its dryness (and the
walking upon it) being perceived as contra-standard. Contra-standard properties are
ones we tend to findshocking, disconcerting, startling, or upsetting, and thus results
the “disturbing weirdness.” The weirdness is the result not simply of the realization
that one is walking on a tidal basin, but of the experience of walking where it is, as
it were, contra-standard to walk, that is, in perceiving the wide expanse as a sea-bed
and perceiving oneself as walking upon that sea-bed.
Similarly, concerning properties that are standard, variable, and contrastandard in
respect to beaches we might explain the initial aesthetic judgment involving “wild,
glad emptiness.” As in the case of the size of elephants, the width and expansiveness
of, in this case, a beach is a variable property and the limits on the range of width
and expansiveness a standard property with respect to this category. Thus if the
“sand and mud” is, as suggested by the quote, quite wide and expansive, that is, in
the upper part of the range, the resultant aesthetic impression will be of a “wild, glad
emptiness.” On the other hand, had the expanse of sand and mud been in the lower
part of the range, the beach may have appeared warm and cozy or perhaps cramped
and confining. Of course, the actual aesthetic judgments that seem true will be a
function not only of these variable and standard properties of beaches, but also of
many others and, of course, of our other experiences with this category and the
properties that are standard, variable, and contra-standard with respect to it.
Other examples similar to the above could be provided. In fact I think reference
to the kind of categories in which we perceive natural objects and landscapes, and
the properties of standard, variable, and contra-standard with respect to such
categories, helps to explain which aesthetic judgments seem to be true or false
concerning much of nature—whether it be completely natural or modified by
humans. Reflection on our judgments about mountains, sunsets, and waving fields
of grain appears to bear this out.
20
However, rather than pursue further examples
that support this psychological claim, I now turn to the more important question of
the correctness of such judgments. In short, given the truth of the psychological
claim, I ask whether we should, with Walton and others, opt for the category-relative
62 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
interpretation of our aesthetic judgments about nature; or alternatively whether
there are persuasive arguments for considering certain categories of nature to be
correct and others incorrect, as is the case with categories of art. Given the
implausibility of a bifurcated account of aesthetic judgments, I assume that the
existence of such arguments constitutes adequate reason for rejecting the category-
relative interpretation.
The correct categories of nature
In the remainder of this chapter I sketch some arguments that give grounds for holding
that certain categories of nature are correct and others not. These arguments
support the conclusion suggested in the preceding chapter: that the correct
categories of nature are those given by the natural sciences. Before considering these
arguments, however, we should note that there is one obvious way in which certain
of such categories are correct and others not. It appears, for example, that the category
of elephants and not that of mice is the correct category for perceiving an elephant,
regardless of its size. Similarly, to perceive an elephant as a mountain, as a sunset, or
as a waving field of grain are clear cases of getting the incorrect category—if such
perceivings are even possible. These are easy cases, for in such cases the number of
perceptual properties standard with respect to the correct category are relatively
large in number—even a very small (or very large) elephant has considerably more
perceptual properties standard with respect to the category of elephants than with
respect to the category of mice (or mountains). In short, in such cases the correct
category is determined by something like Walton’s first circumstance for it being
correct to perceive a work of art in a given category—and determined by that alone.
The more difficult kind of case is that in which the perceptual properties of a natural
object or a part of nature do not by themselves clearly indicate a correct category.
Such a case is posed when, given the perceptual properties, it is yet plausible to
perceive an object in two or more mutually exclusive categories. Very simple
examples are perceiving a sea-anemone as a plant or as an animal, or perceiving a
whale as a fish or as a mammal. Yet, even with these examples, it may be argued that
perceptual properties are adequate to determine correctness of category—
depending, of course, on what properties count as perceptual.
In order to consider my first argument, however, it is not necessary to debate the
difficult issue of what counts as a perceptual property. Rather it is more fruitful to
simply assume that in such cases perceptual properties are not adequate to
determine correctness of category. Consequently, let us assume, for example, that
with perceptual properties alone it is plausible to perceive a whale either in the
category of fish or in the category of mammals. This makes plausible the claim that
for aesthetic judgments about whales there is no correct category, and that we must
therefore accept the category-relative interpretation of such judgments. We can see
why anyone with a Walton-like position might be moved to this view. Given our
assumption, Walton’s first circumstance does not determine a correct category and,
as already suggested, his third and fourth circumstances cannot determine a correct
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 63
category.
21
Whales are not produced by artists who intend them to be perceived in
certain categories and are not produced within societies. Whales do not fit into
categories of art. However, from these truisms, Walton and others apparently move
to the view that concerning nature we are completely without resources for
determining a correct category. As we have seen, Walton compares making aesthetic
judgments about nature with making aesthetic judgments about a work of art “about
whose origins we know absolutely nothing.
22
It is this move and the resulting conclusion that my first argument calls into
question. To see how this occurs we must note first that although whales and nature
in general do not fit into categories of art, they yet do fit, as noted in Chapter 4,
into a number of common-sense and/or “scientific” groups. A whale can be
perceived as a fish or as a mammal; as a whale or as, for example, a large porpoise; as
a blue whale or as a humpbacked whale. Hepburn’s expanse of sand and mud can be
perceived as a beach, as a tidal basin, or as a sea-bed. That nature in general can be
and is perceived in such biological and geological categories and that such categories
psychologically function in a way similar to categories of art is what has already been
established by the above discussion of the application of the psychological claim to
aesthetic judgments about nature. Once this is granted, we must next observe that
although nature is not produced by artists who intend it to be perceived in certain
categories and is not produced within certain societies, it does not follow that we
know nothing about it or more particularly that we do not know which categories
are correct for it. Works of art are produced within societies within which categories
are recognized and by artists who intend these to be correct categories; it follows
that certain categories are correct for a given work and that we can know which ones
are correct. But, as suggested in Chapter 4, human production is not the only key to
correctness of category. In general we do not produce, but rather discover, natural
objects and aspects of nature. Why should we therefore not discover the correct
categories for their perception? We discover whales and later discover that, in spite of
somewhat misleading perceptual properties, they are in fact mammals and not
fish.
23
It is plausible to claim that we have discovered the correct category in which
to perceive whales. In the first place, that whales are not of our production does not
count against this category being correct. In the second, it fits our intuitions about
the correct categorization or classification of whales if this issue is considered
independent of aesthetic issues. And, in the third place, this correctness of category
can function philosophically for aesthetic judgments about nature as the correctness
of categories of art functions for aesthetic judgments about art works. The only
significant difference is that, concerning the latter, the grounds for correctness are
the activities of artists and art critics, while concerning the former, they are the
activities of naturalists and scientists in the broadest sense. But given the differences
between art and nature, this is only to be expected.
The above line of thought takes us only so far in undercutting the plausibility of
the category-relative interpretation of aesthetic judgments about nature. One might
say that it at best shifts the burden of proof to those who defend such an
interpretation. Moreover, it is based on the (at best unclear) assumption that in a
64 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
case such as that of whales perceptual properties themselves do not determine the
correct category. Consequently we must consider some further arguments that do
more than shift the burden of proof and do not depend upon this assumption. To
find a realistic case in which perceptual properties are neutral concerning correctness
of category it is useful to envisage a situation where humans are involved. We, or
landscapers, sometimes construct (or reconstruct) landscapes that are perceptually
indistinguishable from natural landscapes. Consider a scenic coastline that appears
to be natural, but in fact has been created by human beings. Imagine that it has been
carefully planned and designed to be perceptually indistinguishable from a natural
coastline, but its construction involved the removal of buildings and parking lots, the
redistribution of great quantities of sand and soil, and the landscaping of the whole
area to blend with its surroundings.
24
It is in fact a large-scale artifact, but can, and
probably would, be perceived in the category of apparent (see footnote 19) natural
coastlines. In such a case perceptual properties alone clearly do not determine
whether it is correct to perceive the landscape as natural coastline or as artifact, yet
the question of which is the correct category can be raised. It is essentially the
question of whether it is correct to perceive the object as what it is (an artifact) or as
what it appears to be (a natural coastline). It is this form of the question to which I
address two additional lines of thought to the effect that certain categories in which
we perceive nature are correct and others not. The general direction of these
arguments is that it is correct to perceive an object in the category of what it is (as
opposed to what it appears to be) even in difficult cases where its perceptual
properties do not themselves count toward one or the other categories being correct
(or, if anything, suggest that the category of what it appears to be is correct).
The first of these two additional arguments can be made clear by imagining
another coastline. This is a coastline that is perceptually indistinguishable from the
above described coastline, but is natural rather than human-made. We can assume it
is the coastline that served as the model for the human-made one. Since the two
coastlines (call them N for natural and M for human-made) are perceptually
indistinguishable, there is one level at which our aesthetic appreciation of the two
will be identical. This is the level at which we appreciate only perceptual properties
such as the curves, lines, colors, shapes, and patterns of N and M. However, as
argued in Chapters 2 and 3, such exclusively formal aesthetic appreciation of nature
is problematic.
25
Moreover, as suggested in Chapter 4, there is also another, deeper
level at which aesthetic appreciation occurs.
26
At this level we appreciate not simply,
for example, the identical patterns of N and M, but such patterns under certain
descriptions. For example, the pattern of M can be described as indicating careful
design, as an exact copy of the pattern of N, or as the product of human ingenuity;
while the pattern of N can be described as typical of, say, North American Pacific
coastlines, as indicating a high-tide coastal formation, or as the product of the
erosion of the sea. It is clear that aesthetic appreciation of perceptual properties
under such descriptions constitutes an important part of aesthetic appreciation of
nature.
27
It essentially involves the contemplation of perceptual properties in light
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 65
of such descriptions and the appreciation of them as something in virtue of which
such descriptions are true.
Given the aesthetic relevance of these kinds of descriptions, it must be recognized
that the above descriptions of the patterns of N and M are such that those that are
true of N’s pattern are not true of M’s and vice versa. In fact for any such N and M
there are an infinite number of descriptions that are true of N and not of M and
vice versa. That any of such descriptions are aesthetically relevant in the way
suggested above is all that need be the case in order to establish the importance of
perceiving an object in the category of what it is as opposed to what it appears to be.
This can be seen by noting that if we, for example, perceive M in the category of
natural coastlines (what it appears to be) we become involved in one or both of the
following: first, failure to appreciate it under descriptions that are true of it, such as
its being carefully designed by humans; second, appreciation of it under descriptions
that are false of it, such as its being the result of the sea’s erosion. The first alternative
is undesirable as it constitutes a case of aesthetic omission. It is possible to
contemplate M in light of the description “being carefully designed by humans” and
moreover to appreciate it as something in virtue of which this is true, but these
possibilities are not likely to be achieved if M is perceived (only) in the category of
natural coastlines. The opportunity for such contemplation and appreciation is not
provided by perceiving M in this category. The second alternative is undesirable as
it constitutes a case of aesthetic deception. Perceiving M in the category of natural
coastlines, of course, provides the possibility of contemplating M in light of the
description “being the result of the sea’s erosion,” but this is a tenuous and
misleading contemplation. It is tenuous in that it is always in danger of being
destroyed by the knowledge of M’s true reality and it is misleading in that it directs
our contemplation away from this reality. Moreover, if we appreciate M as
something in virtue of which this description is true, we are simply mistaken; our
appreciation involves a false belief. On the other hand, if we perceive M in the
category of artifact or perceive N in the category of natural coastlines—the categories
of what each in fact is—then aesthetic omissions and aesthetic deceptions of the
kind described above need not occur.
There are two things to observe about the preceding argument. The first and
most important is that it provides grounds for construing the category of what
something is as the correct category and the category of what something only
appears to be as an incorrect category. The grounds are essentially that doing so
avoids both aesthetic omissions and aesthetic deceptions. Consequently, we have
reason to hold that even in cases where perceptual properties do not by themselves
determine correct and incorrect categories, there are yet grounds for this
determination and, therefore, grounds for rejecting the category-relative
interpretation of our aesthetic judgments about nature. The second is that this
conclusion depends neither upon the example involving very broad categories
(natural coastline versus artifact or human-made coastline) nor upon it involving
one “non-natural” category. As suggested earlier, these features of the example are
due to the desire for a realistic case in which perceptual properties themselves
66 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
cannot be construed as determining the correctness of one or the other category. In
this regard it is important to note that this same line of argument applies to, for
example, our earlier case involving the categories of beach, sea-bed, and tidal basin.
Different aesthetically relevant descriptions are true of the wide expanse of sand and
mud depending upon whether it is in fact a beach, a sea-bed, or a tidal basin. And
only perceiving the expanse in the category of what it is will avoid various aesthetic
omissions and deceptions. Consequently, in such cases, we similarly have grounds
for the determination of the correct category and for rejecting the category-relative
interpretation of aesthetic judgments.
The second argument for construing the category of what a natural object is as
the correct category and what it only appears to be as an incorrect category is in part
an ethical argument. It is essentially the contention that this is the best way to keep
our aesthetics and our ethics in harmony. Consider the aesthetic appreciation of a
Playboy centerfold model.
28
Whether or not this is considered aesthetic appreciation
of nature, there is a common line of argument concerning such aesthetic
appreciation. It is argued that this is to aesthetically appreciate the model not as
what she is (in the category of human beings), but only as what she here appears to
be or is presented as being (in the category of sex objects). And, the argument
continues, this is ethically suspect for to engage in such aesthetic appreciation is to
endorse and promote (in ourselves, if nowhere else) a sexist attitude toward woman.
I think this kind of argument has merit for the following reason: it is clear that we
do not aesthetically appreciate simply with our five senses, but rather with an
important part of our whole emotional and psychological selves. Consequently, what
and how we aesthetically appreciate cannot but play a role in the shaping of our
emotional and psychological being. This in turn helps to determine what we think
and do, and think it correct for ourselves and others to think and do. In short, our
aesthetic appreciation is a significant factor in shaping and forming our ethical
views.
If this argument has merit, it is especially pertinent to the aesthetic appreciation of
nature. If our aesthetic appreciation of nature helps to determine our ethical views
concerning nature, then our aesthetic appreciation of nature should be of nature as
it in fact is rather than as what it may appear to be. By aesthetically appreciating
nature for what it is, we will shape our ethical views such that there is the best
opportunity for making sound ethical judgments about matters of environmental
and ecological concern. Consider again the human-made coastline. What if we
discover that it causes environmental and ethical problems? Perhaps it greatly
decreases the possibility of successful upstream migration by spawning salmon, or
perhaps it causes an undercurrent that is exceedingly dangerous to swimmers. If we
perceive the coastline in the category of natural coastlines (and are entrenched in
doing so), a sound ethical view might involve noting that fish and human beings
have in such cases long accepted and met the challenges of nature. Consequently
perhaps we understandably conclude that we should let nature take its course and
swimmers take their chances. On the other hand, if we perceive the coastline in the
category of artifact or human-made coastline, a sound ethical view might involve
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 67
regarding our environmental and ethical responsibilities quite differently. Perhaps
we, ethically and ecologically, should construct a fish ladder up the coast (as has
been done to allow salmon migration around hydroelectric dams), and perhaps we,
ethically, should forbid swimmers to use the area. An actual case of this kind might
be the way in which ethical views about whales apparently alter as a function of
perceiving them as mammals rather than as fish. At the very least it appears that
some of the arguments advanced for preserving whales presuppose perceiving them
as mammals and aesthetically appreciating them as such. Strictly analogous
arguments could not be advanced for preserving, for example, sharks (although
different arguments could be).
This ethical line of argument does not by itself clearly establish that there are
correct and incorrect categories in which to perceive parts of nature or natural
objects nor does it clearly establish that the correct categories are the categories of
what things in fact are. However, it does, I think, establish that there is ethical merit
in regarding certain categories as correct and others as incorrect, and in regarding as
correct the categories of what things in fact are, or, as we described them earlier, the
common-sense and/or scientific categories that are determined by the naturalist and
the natural scientist. Consequently, if this argument together with the others offered
above give adequate grounds for claiming truth and falsity for our aesthetic
judgments of nature (rather than accepting the category-relative interpretation),
then these arguments help to establish a position that has additional merit. This is
the merit of bringing the interests and points of view of aesthetics, ethics, and
natural science together such that they reinforce one another, rather than stand in
opposition as they so often appear to do.
Conclusion
I conclude these remarks by further emphasizing one consequence of the position I
have attempted to establish. The consequence can be brought out by noting the
extent to which the position remains within the general confines of a cultural
account of the aesthetic. There is a difference of emphasis, of course. As noted in
Chapter 4, when the aesthetic appreciation of art is considered in light of a cultural
account, the relevant part of our culture is that embodied in and revealed by art
history and art criticism; when aesthetic appreciation of nature is so considered, on
the other hand, the relevant part of our culture is natural history and natural science.
Nonetheless, in the manner in which a cultural account of the aesthetic requires
knowledge of art history and art criticism to play an essential role in our aesthetic
judgments about art, likewise a cultural account requires knowledge of natural
history and natural science to play the same essential role in our aesthetic judgments
about nature. We can, of course, approach nature as we sometimes approach art,
that is, we can simply enjoy its forms and colors or enjoy perceiving it however we
may happen to. But if our appreciation is to be at a deeper level, if we are to make
aesthetic judgments that are likely to be true and to be able to determine whether or
not they are true; then we must know something about that which we appreciate. We
68 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
must know that certain factors make aspects of nature and natural objects belong to
certain categories and that they are therefore correctly perceived in these categories.
And we must know how to perceive those aspects of nature and natural objects in
the categories in question.
29
This reinforces the conclusion reached in Chapter 4:
that for significant aesthetic appreciation of nature, something like the knowledge
and experience of the naturalist is essential. It is not surprising that individuals such
as Muir, Ruskin, Audubon, and Leopold, who demonstrated an acute aesthetic
appreciation of nature in their paintings and writings, were not simply appreciators
of nature but also accomplished naturalists.
Notes
1 Kendall Walton, “Categories of Art,” Philosophical Review, 1970, vol. 79, pp. 334–
67.
2 The following necessarily brief sketch of Walton’s position fails to capture its detail
and subtlety. Footnotes 4 to 7 are designed to supplement the sketch to some extent.
3 Walton puts his psychological and his philosophical claims in terms of what aesthetic
properties a work seems to have or has, as opposed to in terms of what aesthetic
judgements appear to be or are true or false of it. I prefer the latter and nothing, I
believe, turns on this way of putting his position.
4 Walton, op. cit., pp. 338–9:
Such categories include media, genre, styles, forms, and so forth—for
example, the categories of paintings, cubist paintings, Gothic
architecture, classical sonatas, paintings in the style of Cezanne, and
music in the style of late Beethoven—if they are interpreted in such a way
that membership is determined solely by features that can be perceived
in a work when it is experienced in the normal manner.
The latter condition is what makes a category of art “perceptually
distinguishable.”
5 Ibid., p. 339:
A feature of a work of art is standard with respect to a (perceptually
distinguishable) category just in case it is among those in virtue of
which works in that category belong to that category—that is, just in case
the lack of that feature would disqualify, or tend to disqualify, a work
from that category. A feature is variable with respect to a category just
in case it has nothing to do with works belonging to that category; the
possession or lack of the feature is irrelevant to whether a work qualifies
for the category. Finally, a contra-standard feature with respect to a
category is the absence of a standard feature with respect to that category
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 69
—that is, a feature whose presence tends to disqualify works as
members of the category.
6 Ibid., p. 340
To perceive a work in a certain category is to perceive the “Gestalt” of
that category in the work. This needs some explanation, People familiar
with Brahmsian music—that is, music in the style of Brahms (notably,
works of Johannes Brahms)—or impressionist paintings can frequently
recognize members of these categories by recognizing the Brahmsian or
impressionist Gestalt qualities. Such recognition is dependent on
perception of particular features that are standard relative to these
categories, but it is not a matter of inferring from the presence of such
features that a work is Brahmsian or impressionist.
As is evident in the above and in footnote 4, Walton uses “perceive” in a
rather broad sense. I follow his usage throughout this chapter.
7 In general Walton’s view is that properties perceived as standard are aesthetically inert
or “contribute to a work’s sense of order, inevitability, stability, correctness” Ibid., p.
348; properties perceived as variable contribute to a work its representational,
symbolic, and expressive nature; and properties perceived as contra-standard
contribute to a work a shocking, disconcerting, startling, or upsetting nature. Ibid., see
pp. 343–54.
8 Ibid., see pp. 357–63.
9 Ibid., p. 367.
10 Ibid., p. 355.
11 Ibid., p. 365, my italics.
12 This has been noted in different ways by a number of writers. See, for example,
Ronald W.Hepburn, “Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” in H.Osborne (ed.)
Aesthetics in the Modern World, London, Thames and Hudson, 1968, pp. 49–66; Mary
Carman Rose, “Nature as an Aesthetic Concept,” British Journal of Aesthetics 1976,
vol. 16, pp. 3–12; Michael Hancher, “Poems Versus Trees: The Aesthetics of Monroe
Beardsley,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1972, vol. 31, pp. 181–91.
13 Walton, op. cit., p. 355.
14 It should be clear that the position concerning the aesthetics of nature that I here
exemplify by means of Walton’s article can also be seen as a natural consequence of
George Dickie’s institutional analysis of aesthetic objects (not simply of art). See Art
and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis, Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1974,
Chapters 7 and 8, especially p. 169 and pp. 198–200. I do not consider Dickie’s
analysis as he does not explicitly endorse a relativist position for aesthetic judgments
about nature. He does however make certain remarks that suggest it. For example:
“Where natural visual aesthetic objects are concerned, we can be content to appreciate
whatever happens to ‘fall together’ into a visual design” (Ibid., p. 169). In spite of such
comments, it is nonetheless clear from the concluding paragraphs of the book that
Dickie wishes to leave open the question of the status of the aesthetic appreciation of
70 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
nature. The view that I elaborate in this chapter constitutes a partial response to some
of the issues raised in those paragraphs.
15 As noted in Chapters 1 and 4, one means by which aesthetic judgments about nature
can be brought under cultural accounts of the aesthetic is in virtue of the practice of
perceiving nature as if it fits into certain kinds of artistic categories. There is, for
example, a tradition of perceiving landscapes as if they fit into various landscape-
painting categories. Paradoxically, however, such perceiving of landscapes seemingly
lends support to a category-relative interpretation of aesthetic judgments of nature, for
it is difficult to justify the claim that any such artistic categories are correct for nature,
rather than simply imposed upon nature. I think imposing such categories upon nature
poses certain difficulties that I discuss in “Appreciation and the Natural
Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–75
(reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4).
16 There is, of course, no lack of philosophical problems with cultural accounts of the
aesthetic. Some of the particular problems inherent in Dickie’s institutional analysis of
aesthetic objects are brought out in the following: Gary Iseminger, “Appreciation, the
Artworld, and the Aesthetic,” in L.Aagaard-Mogensen (ed.) Culture and Art, Atlantic
Highlands, Humanities Press, 1976, pp. 118–30; Robert McGregor, “Dickie’s
Institutionalized Aesthetic,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1977, vol. 17, pp. 3–13;
Michael Mitias, “The Institutional Theory of the Aesthetic Object,” The Personalist,
1977, vol. 58, pp. 147–55.
17 Walton, op. cit., pp. 350–1. Walton, I suspect, would agree that the psychological
claim applies to the aesthetic appreciation of nature. This is not only evidenced by his
use of the elephant example, but also by his remark to the effect that what the claim
purports “is obviously not an isolated or exceptional phenomenon, but a pervasive
characteristic of aesthetic perception” (p. 354).
18 Hepburn, op. cit., p. 55.
19 In discussing the psychological claim, the categories involved are, strictly speaking, the
categories of, for example, apparent beaches, apparent seabeds, or apparent elephants,
that is, the categories of things which because of their perceptual properties look like
beaches, sea-beds, or elephants. See Walton, op. cit., p. 339. Constant repetition of
“apparent” is not necessary as long as it is clear that the categories involved are
perceptually distinguishable (see footnote 4).
20 Mountains seem a particularly good case in point for testing the psychological claim.
See Marjorie Hope Nicolson’s classic work Mountain Gloom and Mountain Glory,
Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1959.
21 I do not mention Walton’s second circumstance, for I think it directly relevant in the
case of neither art nor nature. This is because it seems not to be a
circumstance constitutive of correctness as are the other circumstances. In contrast to
these, the second circumstance seems only to provide some evidence for correctness.
At best it might be construed as a “tie-breaking” consideration somewhat analogous to
the way in which simplicity is viewed in regard to theory testing. It is possible that this
is also the proper way in which to view the ethical considerations I discuss near the end
of this chapter.
22 Walton, op, cit., p. 364, my italics.
23 It may be held that the idea of discovering, for example, that a whale is in fact a
mammal is simplistic—that the more correct description is in terms of something such
as inventing and applying a conceptual system. Although I do not wish to assume any
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 71
such views here, to the extent that they are plausible, my general line of thought is
strengthened. Such views help to bring the categorization of art and the categorization
of nature more in line with one another.
24 I owe this example to Donald Crawford. Certain ideas in the present chapter were
initially developed as comments on Donald Crawford’s unpublished paper “Art and
the Aesthetics of Nature,” which was presented at the Pacific Division of the American
Society for Aesthetics at Asilomar, April 1980.1 thank Crawford and other
participants for valuable discussion of those ideas.
25 I bring out some of its problematic aspects in “Formal Qualities in the Natural
Environment,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1979, vol. 13, pp. 99–114 (reproduced
in this volume, Chapter 3).
26 Hepburn, op. cit., p. 62, notes:
Suppose the outline of our cumulus cloud resembles that of a basket of
washing, and we amuse ourselves in dwelling upon this resemblance.
Suppose that on another occasion we do not dwell on such freakish
aspects, but try instead to realize the inner turbulence of the cloud, the
winds sweeping up within and around it, determining its structure and
visible form. Should we not be ready to say that this latter experience
was less superficial than the other, that it was truer to nature, and for that
reason more worth having? If there can be a passage, in art, from easy
beauty to difficult and more serious beauty, there can also be such
passages in aesthetic contemplation of nature.
Compare Hepburn’s general remarks on pp. 60–4 with the argument that
follows.
27 Note, for example, the following remark by Aldo Leopold, “Conservation Esthetic”
[1953], in A Sand Country Almanac with Essays on Conservation from Round River, New
York, Random House, 1974, p. 285 (my italics):
Consider…a trout raised in a hatchery and newly liberated in an over-
fished stream… No one would claim this trout has the same value as a
wholly wild one caught out of some unmanaged stream in the high
Rockies. Its esthetic connotations are inferior, even though its capture
may require skill.
The inferior aesthetic “connotations” of one trout as opposed to the other can
only be a function of what descriptions are true of one as opposed to the
other.
28 This illustration was suggested to me by Donald Crawford.
29 I make suggestions concerning this issue in “Appreciation and the Natural
Environment,” op. cit. (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4).
72 NATURE, AESTHETIC JUDGMENT, AND OBJECTIVITY
6
NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
The development of positive aesthetics
In this chapter I examine the view that all the natural world is beautiful. According
to this view, the natural environment, insofar as it is untouched by man, has mainly
positive aesthetic qualities; it is, for example, graceful, delicate, intense, unified, and
orderly, rather than bland, dull, insipid, incoherent, and chaotic. All virgin nature,
in short, is essentially aesthetically good. The appropriate or correct aesthetic
appreciation of the natural world is basically positive and negative aesthetic
judgments have little or no place.
Such a view of the appropriate aesthetic appreciation of the natural world is
initially implausible. Concerning the aesthetic appreciation of art, for example, a
comparable view would not warrant serious consideration, for it is not the case that
all art is essentially aesthetically good; in such appreciation, negative aesthetic
judgments have a significant place. In spite of this initial implausibility, the view
that all virgin nature is essentially aesthetically good has numerous supporters,
particularly among those who have given serious thought to the natural
environment. Thus, it deserves careful consideration. In what follows I elaborate it
by reference to some historical and contemporary sources and examine various
justifications that may be offered for it.
The roots of the view may be traced to at least eighteenth-century ideas
concerning the primacy of natural beauty and the beauty of nature as a norm for
art.
1
In the nineteenth century it becomes explicit in the writings of landscape artists
and others concerned with nature. For example, 1821 marks landscape painter John
Constable’s much quoted comment: “I never saw an ugly thing in my life.”
2
At this
time the idea of nature as essentially beautiful is also interwoven with a developing
awareness of the negative effects of human intervention. Thus, in 1857 John Ruskin,
in giving counsel to landscape artists, can find the certainty of beauty only in that
which he takes to be beyond the reach of man:
Passing then to skies, note that there is this great peculiarity about sky
subject, as distinguished from earth subject;—that the clouds, not being much
liable to man’s interference, are always beautifully arranged. You cannot be
sure of this in any other features of landscape.
3
By the second half of the nineteenth century the view can also be found in the work
of individuals who are best described as environmental reformers. For example,
1864 dates the publication of George Marsh’s Man and Nature, which has been
described as “the fountainhead of the conservation movement” and “the beginning
of land wisdom in this country [the United States].
4
Here Marsh develops two
hypotheses—that “nature left alone is in harmony” and that man is “the great
disturber of nature’s harmonies.” Early in the book, he enumerates nature’s
“manifold blessings” for man. All, he points out, “must be earned by toil” and are
“gradually ennobled by the art of man,” with one exception—natural beauty. This
blessing is only disturbed, not ennobled, by man; for it, Marsh says, “unaided
nature make[s] provision.” He suggests that these beauties “that now, even in their
degraded state, enchant every eye” could be fully and universally appreciated “only
in the infancy of lands where all the earth was fair.”
5
The related ideas of man as the destroyer of nature’s beauty and of “all the earth”
as beautiful except for man’s influence are not limited to somewhat scholarly works
such as Man and Nature. By the end of the nineteenth century they are key notions
in movements of social reform. In public lectures given in the 1880s, artist, poet,
and social critic William Morris preaches:
For surely there is no square mile of earth’s inhabitable surface that is not
beautiful in its own way, if we men will only abstain from wilfully destroying
that beauty; and it is this reasonable share in the beauty of the earth that I
claim as the right of every man who will earn it by due labor.
6
At about the same time, writing in the Atlantic Monthly, John Muir promotes wild
land preservation with similar themes: “None of Nature’s landscapes are ugly so
long as they are wild… But the continent’s outer beauty is fast passing away.”
7
In the twentieth century these themes, although perhaps neither fully developed
nor completely entrenched, have gained a foothold in the public mind. David
Lowenthal, a geographer, characterizes the received opinion in our time as follows:
Nature is…thought preferable to artifice. The favored landscapes are wild;
landscapes altered or disturbed or built on by man are considered beneath
attention or beyond repair… Conservationist organizations contrast sordid
scenes dominated by man with lovely landscapes devoid of human activity…
The implication is clear: man is dreadful, nature is sublime.
8
The most recent expressions of the view that the natural world is essentially
aesthetically good are found in philosophical writings that address environmental
issues. Unlike artists and reformers, however, contemporary philosophers are not
given to absolute or universal claims. Nonetheless, there is what Leonard Fels
74 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
describes as one “basic assumption for aesthetic judgments.” It is “that anything
natural is probably good. Much that is natural is also thought of as inherently
beautiful.”
9
This attribution of aesthetic goodness, inherent beauty, or more
particular positive aesthetic qualities to all that is natural is illustrated by a number
of current discussions. For example, in considering the preservation of species, Lilly-
Marlene Russow, while expressing worries about “species such as the snail darter,”
claims that:
…aesthetic value can cover a surprising range of things: a tiger may be simply
beautiful; a blue whale is awe-inspiring; a bird might be decorative; an
Appaloosa is of interest because of its historical significance; and even a drab
little plant may inspire admiration for the marvelous way it has been adapted
to a special environment.
10
The same idea occurs in attempts to analyze the qualities and values that justify
preservation. For example, Kenneth Simonsen holds:
There is…something astonishing in this world which has been brought into
being by obscure if not blind forces… It is perhaps this realization which is at
the root of our wonder at wild things. Once this attitude comes to pervade our
response to nature, we feel more than admiring respect. Rather, for us, all wild
things become invested with a sense of awe.
11
Similarly, Holmes Rolston argues:
Wild nature has a kind of integrity… The Matterhorn leaves us in awe, but so
does the fall foliage on any New England hillside, or the rhododendron on
Roan Mountain. Those who linger with nature find this integrity where it is
not at first suspected, in the copperhead and the alligator, in the tarantula and
the morel, in the wind-stunted banner spruce and the straggly box elder, in the
stormy sea and the wintry tundra… This value is often artistic or aesthetic,
and is invariably so if we examine a natural entity at the proper level of
observation or in terms of its ecological setting. An ordinary rock in micro
section is an extraordinary crystal mosaic. The humus from a rotting log
supports an exquisite hemlock… Natural value is further resident in the
vitality of things, in their struggle and zest, and it is in this sense that we often
speak of a reverence for life, lovely or not. Or should we say that we find all
life beautiful.
12
Other contemporary writers defend a related but more moderate point of view,
arguing that although not every kind of thing in the natural world is aesthetically
good, being natural is nonetheless essentially connected with positive aesthetic
qualities and value. For example, Joseph Meeker, while suggesting that a “burned
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 75
forest is ugly because it represents a truncated system of growth,”
13
in general holds
that:
The human experience of beauty is rooted in natural forms and processes…
and our esthetic values are really no more—nor any less—than abstract
formulations of the natural… What is exclusively human is generally not
beautiful to us, and we find beauty in human art only when it is compatible with
forms and processes in nature.
14
The moderate view is developed in more detail by Robert Elliot. Elliot explicitly
states thatI do not want to be taken as claiming that what is natural is good and
what is non-natural is not. The distinction between natural and non-natural
connects with valuation in a much more subtle way than that.”
15
He elaborates:
“Sickness and disease are natural in a straightforward sense and are certainly not
good. Natural phenomena such as fires, hurricanes, volcanic eruptions can totally
alter landscapes and alter them for the worse.”
16
With this qualification, Elliot’s view
is that “the naturalness of a landscape is a reason for preserving it, a determinant of
its value… What the environmentalist insists on is that naturalness is one factor in
determining the value of pieces of the environment.”
17
He argues for this view by
reference to analogies between artistic fakes and “faked” nature.
18
Reflection on these and related themes in the aesthetic appreciation of nature has
led Aarne Kinnunen to sharply distinguish the aesthetics of nature from the
aesthetics of art. He claims the former is positive and the latter critical. Critical
aesthetics, he argues, allows for negative aesthetic criticism and is appropriate for
art, and for nature only when it has been affected by man. Positive aesthetics, on the
other hand, does not involve negative aesthetic judgment, but only the acceptance
and aesthetic appreciation of something for what it is. According to Kinnunen, the
aesthetics of nature is essentially positive in that all virgin nature is beautiful. He
writes:
…all untouched parts of nature are beautiful. To be able to enjoy nature
aesthetically is distinct from judgment. The aesthetics of nature is positive.
Negative criticism comes into play only when man’s part in affecting nature is
considered.
19
Kinnunen’s remarks summarize the pattern of thought I have elaborated here.
Consequently I label the view under consideration in this article the “positive
aesthetics” position.
Nature appreciation as non-aesthetic
In this and the following two sections I consider three possible justifications for
positive aesthetics. The first is the nonaesthetic view of nature appreciation
introduced in Chapter 1. This view holds that our appropriate appreciation of the
76 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
natural world is essentially as the positive aesthetics position indicates, except that it
is not genuinely aesthetic. Consequently, the initial implausibility of the position
vanishes: if the appreciation in question is not aesthetic, it need not involve the
critical, negative judgments so common in the aesthetic appreciation of art. Indeed,
the perceived lack of this judgmental element is taken as the reason for denying that
our appreciation of nature is aesthetic.
Of the individuals discussed in the previous section, Elliot most clearly represents
this point of view. He holds that “certain concepts which are frequently deployed in
aesthetic evaluation” can “usefully and legitimately be deployed in evaluations of the
environment.” He says, for example, that we might admire “the intricate and
delicate shadings in a eucalyptus forest” or “may be awed by a mountain.” Yet he
claims that such “responses to nature” do not “count as aesthetic responses.” His
reason for this lies in the aspect of appropriate aesthetic appreciation emphasized by
positive aesthetics. He notes an argument that “turns on the claim that aesthetic
evaluation has, as a central component, a judgmental factor” and contends that
according to this argument “the judgmental element in aesthetic evaluation serves to
differentiate it from environmental evaluation.” Of the judgmental factor, he says:
…an apparently integral part of aesthetic evaluation depends on viewing the
aesthetic object as an intentional object, as an artifact, as something that is
shaped by the purposes and designs of its author. Evaluating works of art
involves explaining them, and judging them, in terms of their author’s
intentions; it involves placing them within the author’s corpus of work; it
involves locating them in some tradition and in some special milieu. Nature is
not a work of art.
20
The basic line of argument may be reconstructed as follows: first, since the natural
world does not have the features sketched in this quote, environmental evaluation
cannot have the “apparently integral part of aesthetic evaluation” which depends
upon them. Thus, second, since environmental evaluation lacks this judgmental
element, it is not aesthetic evaluation. And, third, this in turn is grounds for
concluding that our responses to nature are not aesthetic responses. This conclusion
is not unique to Elliot. Its more general acceptance is suggested by Harold
Osborne’s observation that some contemporary aestheticians “doubt whether we are
talking about the same thing when we speak of natural beauty and the beauty of fine
art.”
21
I think Elliot’s conclusion is implausible. It stands in conflict with the commonly
held view that everything is open to aesthetic appreciation (although not necessarily
positive aesthetic appreciation).
22
If this common view is correct, it would at least be
odd if our appreciation of nature were never aesthetic appreciation and our responses
never aesthetic responses. This can be brought out by noting certain ramifications of
the view. For example, Paul Ziff not only includes non-artifacts, but every kind of
non-artifact within the scope of aesthetic appreciation. He uses unparadigmatic
examples as “a gator basking in the sun on a mud bank in a swamp” and “a mound
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 77
of dried dung.”
23
In a similar vein, environmentalist Neil Evernden assumes that an
“individual may achieve aesthetic involvement with a spruce bog, a prairie, or a
charred forest. The potential for this phenomenon is inherent in every landscape.”
24
Such diverse examples suggest the equality of all things as proper objects of aesthetic
appreciation. Ziff makes this explicit by a comparison between the appreciation of his
basking gatorand that of Leonardo Da Vinci’s Ginevra de Benci (1504), concluding
that “Anything that can be viewed can fill the bill of an object fit for aesthetic
attention and none does it better than any other.”
25
Moreover, certain more typical
instances of the appreciation of nature—for example, the appreciation of colorful
sunsets or delicate wild flowers—are usually thought to be paradigmatic instances of
aesthetic appreciation, instances in terms of which we acquire and understand the
concept of the aesthetic. To deny that these are cases of aesthetic appreciation comes
close to challenging the coherence of that concept.
Having briefly considered the conclusion, let us turn to the argument itself. The
argument is problematic at each of its three steps. First, in step three, even if
environmental evaluations are not aesthetic, it does not follow that responses to
nature are not aesthetic responses. Genuine aesthetic responses to nature might
occur independently of any evaluations of nature, or they might support
nonaesthetic environmental evaluations in something like the way in which genuine
taste responses (for example, tasting the sweetness of milk) can support non-taste
evaluations of what is tasted (for example, this milk is good to drink). Step three of
the argument seems to involve a non sequitur.
Second, in step two, even if environmental evaluations lack the “judgmental
element,” it does not follow that they are not aesthetic—at least not without more
argumentation. On the one hand, if the “judgmental element” refers to the critical,
negative judgments referred to in the positive aesthetics position, then it is possible
that positive aesthetics is simply correct—that all virgin nature is simply aesthetically
good. In this case the judgmental element simply does not arise in our appropriate
appreciation of nature. If we created a genre of art which gave rise to no negative
judgments, it would not follow that our appreciation and evaluations of it were
therefore not aesthetic. On the other hand, if, as Elliot seems to hold, the
“judgmental element” refers just to the particular kind of critical judgments we can
make only in regard to art, it still does not follow that environmental evaluations are
not aesthetic; it only follows that they are not evaluations based on the kinds of
judgments we can make only with regard to art. But why should they be based on
these kinds of judgments? They are not evaluations of art. As Elliot reminds us:
“Nature is not a work of art.”
Third, in step one, even if the natural world is not an intentional object, not an
artifact, not something that is shaped by the purposes and designs of its author, it
does not follow that environmental evaluation cannot have the “apparently integral
part of aesthetic evaluation” which depends upon such features.
26
This is because
although this “part” may depend upon these features in the case in question—
aesthetic evaluations of art—it need not depend upon them in other cases. If the
object of aesthetic appreciation is an intentional object, an artifact, something that
78 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
is shaped by the purposes and designs of its author, then aesthetically evaluating it
may indeed involve explaining it and judging it in terms of the author’s intentions,
placing it within the author’s corpus of work, locating it in some tradition and in
some special milieu. But if it is not, then aesthetically evaluating it need only involve
something analogous to this. If it is a wildflower or a basking gator, aesthetically
evaluating it may involve explaining it and judging it in terms of what it is, placing
it within its natural category, its species, genus, etc., locating it in its natural history
and in its environmental milieu.
I return to these kinds of considerations in a later section. At present I end this
examination of the argument with another of Ziff’s remarks:
That something is not an artifact does not suggest let alone establish that it is
therefore unfit to be an object of aesthetic attention. And unless one has a
compelling narcissistic obsession with the marks of men’s endeavors one can
view things in the world aesthetically without being concerned with or
inhibited by their lack of status as artifacts.
27
I conclude that attempting to account for positive appreciation of the natural world
by denying that this appreciation is aesthetic does not succeed. The claim that our
appreciation of nature is not aesthetic is implausible and at least one line of
argument for that claim is inadequate.
Positive aesthetics and sublimity
A second defense of positive aesthetics takes the fact that the natural world is not an
artifact—that it does not have an artist—not as grounds for claiming that our
appreciation of it is not aesthetic, but rather as a justification for the view that it is
appropriate to appreciate it aesthetically only in a positive manner. The idea is that
the natural world, by not having an artist, is in an important sense outside the
bounds of human control. This is meant to account for the particular aesthetic
appreciation we have of virgin nature and for the claim that negative aesthetic
criticism of it is out of place.
The defense is conceptually and perhaps historically related to the tradition of
appreciating wild nature in terms of the sublime, especially as developed in the
theories of Burke and Kant.
28
The appreciation of nature as sublime is a function of
the fact that since it is outside the bounds of human control, it is potentially a
threat, a source of fear or terror. However, as an element of aesthetic experience the
threat dissolves into positive aesthetic appreciation: amazement, wonder, or awe in
the face of nature’s threatening otherness. In contemporary thought the idea is
applied not simply to wild nature because of its threatening otherness, but to all the
natural world because of its astonishing qualities.
Of the individuals mentioned in the second section of this chapter, Simonsen most
clearly represents this line of thought. After discussing Burke, he concludes that
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 79
“Burke has confounded the astonishing with the terrifying.”
29
He then describes the
ideal nature appreciator (who happens to be an atheist):
He is confronted with a natural world which has come into existence on its
own, and not in accordance with the design of an intelligent creature. He
cannot enter into this world, as he can the world of human fabrication. There
is, therefore, something astonishing in this world which has been brought into
being by obscure if not blind forces. The wild spectacle he sees before him is
truly full of wonder; it just appears, and stands before him like some terrible
goddess…an Aphrodite emerging mysteriously from formless seas. It is
perhaps this realization which is at the root of our wonder at wild things.
Once this attitude comes to pervade our response to nature…all wild things
become invested with a sense of awe.
30
In this view the positive aesthetic appeal of the natural world is a function of the
astonishing nature of something that is beyond the limits of human control.
Moreover, this is also the basis for the claim that negative criticism has no role. This
aspect of the view can be brought out by noting that virgin nature is beyond human
control in two senses. First, it is beyond human beings’ physical control in that they
do not bring it into being and, insofar as it remains virgin nature, they do not
maintain, shape, design, or develop it. Second, moreover, the natural world is also in
a sense beyond human beings’ mental control. We understand little of why it exists,
how it maintains itself, and what it is really like. Its existence is not only “not in
accordance with the design of an intelligent creature,” it is also “brought into being
by obscure if not blind forces.” It “just appears” like “an Aphrodite emerging
mysteriously from formless seas.” We “cannot enter into this world” as we “can the
world of human fabrication.” It is alien in the sense that we do not bring it into
being, and it is obscure in the sense that we do not really understand it.
These two senses in which virgin nature is beyond human control together
support the view that negative aesthetic criticism of it is inappropriate, in that it is
both pointless and presumptive. It is pointless because it will not, in fact logically
cannot, change virgin nature. There is no artist, no intelligence, who might in light
of such criticism redesign and alter the existing natural world or even change the
design and create a new one, thereby improving our aesthetic situation. Moreover,
such criticism is presumptive in light of our limited understanding. We have no
grounds for negative criticism of something that is as alien and obscure as is virgin
nature, that is not even in accordance with the design of any intelligence. In
Simonsen’s remarks there is even the suggestion that this would be disrespectful.
What right do we have to criticize some mysterious and “terrible goddess”? The only
appropriate response is wonder and awe.
This view partially supports the positive aesthetics position, but on balance it is
not an adequate justification. It does aid in understanding certain positive aesthetic
qualities of nature. However, if virgin nature is not to be appreciated aesthetically in
a negative manner, this is not because doing so is either pointless or presumptive.
80 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
This can be brought out by analogy with the aesthetic appreciation of art. First,
consider works of art that are by a long dead artist and belong to a genre within
which artists have ceased to work; perhaps the techniques for working within it have
been lost in time. Such works, like any other, would be open to and subjected to
negative aesthetic criticism. However, there is no artist who might in light of such
criticism redesign and alter the existing works or even change the design and create
new works in this genre. If some existing artist did alter the works they would no
longer be the same works, and if he or she created new works they would not be
works within this genre. Negative criticism is here as pointless as it is claimed to be
concerning virgin nature, but this does not alter the nature of art appreciation
thereby making it positive aesthetics. It may be objected that the art case is
nonetheless distinct because the original works could have been different, could
have been aesthetically better than they are, and this fact gives a point to criticism.
However, such an objection is not persuasive because, for all we know, the natural
world also could have been different, could have been aesthetically better than it is.
In fact, that it could have been seems very likely. If this gives a point to criticism in
the art case, it does the same for criticism of the natural world.
Second, concerning presumptiveness, imagine that the above-mentioned works
are also hopelessly obscure and belong to a hopelessly obscure genre. Such art would
still be open to and subjected to negative aesthetic criticism. In fact, some of such
criticism would be a result of their obscurity. However, this criticism need not be
viewed as presumptive, but rather the opposite, for some of it would function as a
means of coming to grips with the works—a means of reducing their obscurity.
This may reflect the way in which we develop an appreciation for much rather
obscure modern art. It may be objected here that the art case is yet distinct because
the works of art, since they are art and the products of human intelligence, are not
alien and therefore not essentially obscure as is the natural world. Consequently, it
is possible to gain an understanding and appreciation of them and for this reason
negative aesthetic criticism is not presumptive. I agree that in some sense the natural
world and not art is alien, but do not agree that the natural world is therefore any more
essentially obscure than art is. The crucial error is concluding that because
the natural world is alien in the sense of not being of our making, it is therefore
beyond our understanding. Although the natural world, it may be granted, is not an
artifact, not “in accordance with the design of an intelligent creature,” this does not
mean we cannot understand it. It only means that we cannot come to understand it
as we can an artifact, that is, in virtue of creating it. Rather we come to understand
the natural world in different ways. (I return to this point in the last section of this
chapter.)
I conclude that the appeal to pointlessness and presumptiveness does not establish
that negative aesthetic criticism of the natural world is inappropriate. Thus, I argue,
neither the tradition of the sublime nor its contemporary sequels provide the means
for justifying positive aesthetics.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 81
Positive aesthetics and theism
Each of the two justifications examined above account for positive aesthetics by
reference to the fact that the natural world is not a human artifact. A third
justification also holds that nature is not of human making. It relies on the theist
view that the natural world is designed, created, and maintained by an all-knowing
and all-powerful God. This view is familiar enough that it need not be elaborated
here. I concentrate on it only as a possible justification for positive aesthetics.
The justification can be developed in two ways. The first takes the divine origin of
nature as grounds for positive aesthetics by reference to pointlessness and
presumptiveness, although perhaps presumptiveness plays the greater role. It is not
necessary here to consider this development of the “divine justification” for two
reasons: first, it appears either to have little contemporary support or, when it does,
to have a structure similar to the justification considered in the previous section.
Second, in light of this, the arguments advanced in that section, or analogous
arguments, should be adequate to dismiss it from serious attention.
The second way utilizes the idea that the natural world, since it is of divine design
and origin, is a perfect world, at least insofar as it has not been marred by humans.
Virgin nature is, therefore, only aesthetically good and closed to negative aesthetic
criticism. In discussing the differences between art appreciation and nature
appreciation, Nelson Potter characterizes a part of this view:
The theist sees the world as throughout the product of God’s design and
plan. For example, he may regard a spectacular sunset as having been rigged
by God for the human observer’s pleasure and appreciation, just as the same
observer views paintings in an art gallery as having been composed for his
pleasure and appreciation… The only difference is that in nature, the Artist is
divine, not human.
31
Furthermore, Simonsen points out that if one accepts this kind of view, “one could
certainly see why…we would have adequate cause to delight in its [nature’s]
existence, for it would be an objectification of the divine mind.
32
There is no
doubt that if one accepts the basic theist view, it appears to provide a justification
for the positive aesthetics position. However, aside from the issue of its
acceptability, the theist view as a justification for positive aesthetics presents certain
puzzles.
First, it seems that if the divine origin of the natural world is the justification of
the positive aesthetics position, then only theists would either justifiably believe in
its truth or appreciate the natural world appropriately. This conclusion seems
doubtful, but it could possibly be true. However, the divine justification further
suggests that there is a very significant difference between the aesthetic appreciation
of the natural world of the theist and that of the nontheist. Potter elaborates certain
ramifications of this. He holds that the view that natural beauty is a “product of
82 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
God’s design and plan…seems to require a radically different kind of appreciation
of such beauty for the atheist.”
33
He points out:
And yet the theist who hears that an acquaintance is an atheist, would surely
not thereafter assume that the acquaintance has a radically different kind of
appreciation of the beauties of nature (or at least many theists would not). Or
if the theist hears from a friend that the friend shares the theist’s intense
enjoyment of the beauties of nature, could the theist rightly infer that his
friend must also be a theist… ? Surely not… In general, any kind of inference
from the aesthetic enjoyment of nature to one’s religious views, or any inference
in the other direction must be quite dubious.
34
Potter concludes that because the view that natural beauty is a product of God’s
designentails that many such inferences are not dubious, we have reason for
thinking that that view is incorrect.
35
I am not certain that Potter’s observations are
a reason for thinking the view incorrect, but they do make clear some of the oddity
of the divine justification.
A second puzzling feature of this justification can be seen in relation to a
traditional problem in Western thought: the problem of evil. The problem is how to
reconcile an all-knowing, all-powerful, and all-moral deity with the existence of evil
in the world that he or she has created. The evil is often divided into moral evil,
which is of human making, and natural evil, which is not. The latter is typically
illustrated by natural catastrophes; it is all that need concern us here. Attempts to
solve the problem of evil fall into three categories: first, denials of the existence of
evil, second, denials of one or other of the deity’s three problematic properties and,
third, attempts at theodicy, that is, explanation of why a deity with these three
properties would nonetheless allow there to be evil in the world. Concerning natural
evil, theodicy frequently argues that evil is necessary to human beings for various
purposes, such as the recognition of good, the development of virtue, and so forth.
It is easy to posit an analogous problem of ugliness. Since an all-knowing, all-
powerful, and all-moral deity would presumably have perfect aesthetic judgment,
how is he or she to be reconciled with the existence of ugliness or of more specific
negative aesthetic qualities in the world that he or she has created? The analogous
problem is amenable to conceptually parallel solutions: first, deny the existence of
ugliness, second, deny one or other of the deity’s three (or four) problematic
properties and, third, engage in “aesthetic theodicy.” If, in the problem of ugliness,
as in the problem of evil, we distinguish ugliness of human making and natural
ugliness, it becomes clear that positive aesthetics is a position of the kind embraced
by the first type of solution. Or to put it another way, the justification of the
positive aesthetics position by reference to the divine origin of the natural world
constitutes a pattern of thought equivalent to solving the problem of (natural)
ugliness simply by denying the existence of such ugliness. This begins to reveal a
further oddity of this justification. On the one hand, it seems straightforwardly
circular, and, on the other, counter-intuitive. In the problem of evil, the parallel
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 83
solution, the denial of the existence of evil, and especially of natural evil, is
considered the least acceptable and most implausible line of thought. Theists in the
Western tradition have almost without exception pursued theodicy, although the
occasional philosophical theist has flirted with solutions of the second type.
36
This
suggests that the theist should engage in aesthetic theodicy rather than deny the
existence of natural ugliness. In short, the theist, who accepts the justification’s
premise that the natural world is of divine origin, seems an unlikely candidate for
accepting its conclusion that the natural world is essentially beautiful.
A third set of considerations relevant to the divine justification concerns the
historical relationship between Western theism and the positive aesthetics position.
As a matter of history, theists have not usually accepted this position and theism, at
least as embodied in Christianity, has given little or no support to it. This, of
course, is a complex and subtle historical claim about which I only make a few
relevant observations. First, many authorities believe that Christian theism
traditionally viewed wild nature as something to be confronted, dominated, and
domesticated by human beings for their purposes.
37
Given this, it is understandable
that the theist would view tamed and cultivated nature rather than virgin nature
with aesthetic favor. Within such a climate of thought it is difficult to see how
positive aesthetics would develop, even if it could be justified by the natural world’s
assumed divine origins. Moreover, it has been noted that Christian thought
developed such as to give support to the opposite point of view—the view that
virgin and wild nature is aesthetically repellent. For example, in discussing the
aesthetic appreciation of mountains, Ronald Rees, a geographer, points out that
until the end of the seventeenth century:
Many theologians regarded the world, as they did man himself, as fallen from
a state of pristine innocence. It was commonly believed that the original world
had been a perfectly smooth sphere—the ‘Mundane Egg’—whose surface, as
punishment for man’s sins, had been ruptured by interior fluids piling up, to
quote one seventeenth-century theologian, ‘vast and undigested heaps of
stones and earth’, those ‘great ruins’ we call mountains.
38
Rees is quoting from Bishop Thomas Burnet’s Sacred Theory of the Earth which was
written to give, in Burnet’s words, “some tolerable account of how confusion came
in nature.”
39
It is informative to view Burnet as attempting to deal with the problem
of natural ugliness by means of aesthetic theodicy. Historically it seems that this line
of thought rather than positive aesthetics was cultivated by Christian theism.
Another historical consideration is the contention that in Western culture the
aesthetic appreciation of nature has developed in inverse proportion to religion. For
example, Russian historian Victor Romanenko claims, concerning landscape
appreciation, that:
Strictly speaking, neither Antiquity, nor the Middle Ages, nor the early
Renaissance had any idea of landscape. Landscape appeared at a time when
84 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
criticism of the religious world outlook had ripened in the minds of men, who
more acutely than ever before became aware of their unity with nature.
40
Concerning aesthetic appreciation in general, Romanenko notes a world view that
“inevitably limits” man’s “aesthetic attitude towards nature” and “retards the
development of his feelings for nature.” He adds:
Christianity, as it were, sustains and conserves such a world view, because
religion plays down nature, reduces her to the position of a most christian
subject of the all-mighty creator. But this only so long as science is in its infancy
and still under the guardianship of religion.
41
The claim is that Christianity and the aesthetic appreciation of nature have been
opposing forces to an extent such that the latter could grow only as the former went
into decline. If this is an accurate historical picture, it is not surprising to find that
positive aesthetics does not prosper under Christian theism.
I conclude that the divine justification is not promising. It not only suggests that
the theist has a unique kind of aesthetic appreciation of nature, but is
counterintuitive in light of both the theist position on the problem of evil and the
historical point of view of Christian theism. Perhaps to find a justification for
positive aesthetics we need to look elsewhere, not to religion but rather, as suggested
by Romanenko’s quote, to the infant long under religion’s guardianship: science.
Science and aesthetic appreciation of nature
In the remaining sections of this chapter I explore the role of natural science in our
aesthetic appreciation of nature. Consideration of science suggests a more plausible
justification for positive aesthetics than any of those examined in the last three
sections.
The importance of science in the development of the aesthetic appreciation of
nature is brought out in Marjorie Hope Nicolson’s classic Mountain Gloom and
Mountain Glory. Arguing that appeal to the history of art does not provide the
complete account, Nicolson elaborates the growth of the “aesthetics of the
infinite.”
42
Here science plays the essential role. Seventeenth-century developments
in astronomy and physics, followed by those in geology and geography, explain and
expand the natural world such that the notion of the sublime can find a place in its
appreciation. Wonder and awe, formerly thought appropriate only for a deity, now
become aesthetic responses to the seemingly infinite natural world; and especially to
landscapes such as Nicolson’s prime example, mountainscapes. Moreover, all
landscapes become objects of appreciation as a function of the continued advances of
the natural sciences. Speaking of landscape painting as a reflection of landscape
appreciation, Romanenko claims: “Realistic landscape…reached a flourishing stage
in the nineteenth century and…its development was definitely related to the rapid
advance in all fields of natural science, especially geography, biology, geology.”
43
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 85
In the nineteenth century, in addition to geography and geology, biology
becomes particularly important. Scientists of that century, especially Darwin, turned
the previous practice of collecting and naming into the science of the day, thereby
accomplishing for flora and fauna what sciences such as astronomy and geology had
earlier accomplished for landscapes:
Everything, which before the days of Darwin had borne the stamp of “divine
origin”, the beauty of nature included, was passed down to the earth from
heaven. The idea of man’s unity with nature, since the days of Darwin,
received particularly wide recognition, and his evolutionary theory, his
methodology and the principles of his historical approach began, in the latter
part of the nineteenth century, to exercise a revolutionizing influence on a
subject so remote from exact natural science as aesthetics.
44
With the growth of our aesthetic appreciation of nature in general science shares
credit with art. However, in the more recent development of positive aesthetics,
science is the main if not exclusive factor. The individuals who hold the positive
aesthetics position take science to have a special relevance to their views. This is
particularly true of Marsh; simply a glance at Man and Nature reveals the
importance in his thought of both the theoretical and the applied science of his day.
Moreover, Constable and Ruskin can be seen as no less under the spell of science.
Constable is famous for his claim that “painting is a science, and should be pursued
as an inquiry into the laws of nature. He asks:Why, then, may not landscape
painting be considered as a branch of natural philosophy, of which pictures are but
the experiments?”
45
Equally significant is the following remark: “I must say that the
sister arts have less hold on my mind.. .than the sciences, especially the study of
geology, which, more than any other, seems to satisfy my mind.”
46
And it is well
known that Ruskin’s descriptions of nature compare favorably with those of his
scientific contemporaries in accuracy and detail. Ronald Rees claims that “parts 2, 5
and 7 of ‘Modern Painters’ in effect offer a course in physical geography for
landscape painters.
47
Contemporary advocates of positive aesthetics have a similar regard for science.
The main difference is that now the relevant sciences are not primarily geography
and geology, but rather biology and the all encompassing “science” of ecology. The
issues these writers frequently address, such as the survival of species and the value
and preservation of wild lands, are themselves issues of biological and ecological
importance. Their orientation is even revealed in their titles: “Aesthetic Decision-
Making and Human Ecology,” “The Biology of Beauty,” “Can and Ought We to
Follow Nature?” “Is There an Ecological Ethic?” “The Value of Wildness,”
“Ecological Esthetics.”
48
More significant is the way they bring biological and
ecological insight to the positions they develop. For example, in discussing
“languages” of art and “languages” of nature in aesthetic appreciation, Kinnunen
characterizes the latter as “ecological languages.”
49
Elliot endorses the view that “the
understanding of the complexity, diversity, and integration of the natural world
86 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
which ecology affords us, opens up a new area of valuation.”
50
Rolston in speaking
of “wild value” claims that “this value is often artistic or aesthetic,” but “also has to
do with the intelligibility of each of the natural members; and here natural science,
especially ecology, has greatly helped us.”
51
He also argues that “environmental
science” invites us “to see the ecosystem not merely in awe, but in ‘love, respect, and
admiration.’”
52
As Meeker suggests: “Esthetic theory may be more successful in
defining beauty when it has incorporated some of the conceptions of nature and its
processes which have been formulated by contemporary biologists and ecologists.”
53
It seems no exaggeration to say that this is what these individuals are attempting to
do.
That science has played a role in the development of both the aesthetic
appreciation of nature and the positive aesthetics position is, I think, clear. What is
less clear is exactly why this should be so, although in general the answer is obvious
enough: science provides knowledge about nature. For example, even though Biese’s
The Development of the Feeling for Nature in the Middle Ages and Modern Times is
mainly an account of art’s role in nature appreciation, Biese concludes that the
“present intensity” (1905) of the feeling for nature “is due to the growth of science,
for although feeling has become more realistic and matter-of-fact in these days of
electricity and the microscope, love for Nature has increased with knowledge.”
54
In
a similar vein Val Routley argues that the knowledge that science has gathered
within the last three hundred years and that has only recently been generally
disseminated “makes natural areas intelligible” and “as usual, information is an
important adjunct to appreciation, as much so with the natural area as with the
string quartet.”
55
Following Routley, Elliot takes note of the knowledge provided by
ecology. Of those who value wilderness, he says:
What they do see, and what they value, is very much a function of the degree
to which they understand the ecological mechanisms which maintain the
landscape and which determine that it appears the way it does. Similarly,
knowledge of art history, of painting techniques, and the like will inform
aesthetic evaluations and alter aesthetic perceptions. Knowledge of this kind is
capable of transforming a hitherto uninteresting landscape into one that is
compelling.
56
I think there is no doubt that scientific knowledge, as Elliot suggests, can transform
the landscape, in fact the natural world, but there is yet the question of how and
why this transformation occurs: how and why does scientific knowledge make the
natural world seem beautiful? The beginnings of an answer are suggested by Rolston
when he says:
Ecological description finds unity, harmony, interdependence, stability, etc
earlier data are not denied, only redescribed or set in a larger ecological
context, and somewhere enroute our notions of harmony, stability, etc., have
shifted too and we see beauty now where we could not see it before.
57
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 87
Similarly Routley suggests: “The informed person…sees a pattern and harmony
where the less informed may see a meaningless jumble.”
58
Scientific information and
redescription make us see beauty where we could not see it before, pattern and
harmony instead of meaningless jumble. If these suggestions are correct, they begin
to explain the relationship between scientific knowledge and the aesthetic
appreciation of nature. They begin to account for the way in which the two have
developed hand in hand and why, in light of scientific knowledge, the natural world
seems aesthetically good. However, as they stand they do not do justice to the
complexity of aesthetic appreciation, and by themselves they do not provide a
justification for the positive aesthetics position.
Science and appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature
In this section I reiterate and elaborate those observations about appropriate
aesthetic appreciation and appropriate appreciation of nature that are introduced
and defended in the preceding two chapters.
Appropriate aesthetic appreciation is that appreciation of an object which reveals
what aesthetic qualities and value it has. In the aesthetic appreciation of art, it may
be assumed that relevant knowledge is essential to such appreciation. As Kendall
Walton says:
If we are confronted by a work about whose origins we know absolutely
nothing (for example, one lifted from the dust at an as yet unexcavated
archaeological site on Mars), we would simply not be in a position to judge it
aesthetically. We could not possibly tell by staring at it, no matter how
intently and intelligently, whether it is coherent, or serene, or dynamic, for by
staring we cannot tell whether it is to be seen as a sculpture, a guernica [a
category of Guernica-like works invented by Walton], or some other exotic or
mundane kind of work of art.
59
The suggestion here is that, as elaborated in Chapter 4, in order to appreciate what
aesthetic qualities a work has, it is necessary to know how it is to be seen. And knowing
how it is to be seen is a function of knowing what it is and something about it. For
example, Van Gogh’s The Starry Night (1889) is a dynamic and vibrant post-
impressionist painting. However, were it seen as a German expressionist work, it
would appear more serene, somewhat subdued, even a bit dull. In order to
appropriately appreciate it, to appreciate its dynamic and vibrant qualities, we must
see it as a post-impressionist painting. This requires knowing that it is a post-
impressionist painting and something about post-impressionist painting; it requires
the kinds of knowledge given by art history and criticism.
These observations are developed by different individuals in different ways. As
noted in Chapter 4, Ziff captures the idea of appropriate aesthetic appreciation by
distinguishing different “acts of aspection.” He contends: “Generally speaking, a
different act of aspection is performed in connection with works belonging to
88 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
different schools of art, which is why the classification of style is of the essence.”
60
As spelled out in detail in Chapter 5, the importance of classification is further
developed by Walton who introduces the notion of “categories of art.” “Such
categories include media, genre, styles, forms, and so forth—for example, the
categories of paintings, cubist paintings, Gothic architecture, classical sonatas.”
61
Walton points out that works of art can be “perceived in” different categories and
only by perceiving them in the correct categories are we likely to achieve an
appropriate aesthetic appreciation of them. Correctness of categories, Walton
further argues, is in part determined by certain facts about the origins of works, in
particular, in what category their artists intend them to be perceived and what
categories are well established and recognized by the societies in which they are
produced.
In the aesthetic appreciation of art, I take the kind of view indicated by Ziff and
Walton to be essentially correct. For present purposes I assume a position similar to
Walton’s and utilize some of his terminology. What needs to be shown here is that
an analogous account applies to the aesthetic appreciation of nature. The analogous
account holds that there are different ways to perceive natural objects and
landscapes. This is to claim that they, like works of art, can be perceived in different
categories—not, of course, in different categories of art, but rather in different
“categories of nature.” Analogous to the way The Starry Night might be perceived
either as a post-impressionist or as an expressionist painting, a whale might be
perceived either as a fish or as a mammal, or a gator basking in the sun might be
perceived either as an alligator or as a crocodile. Further, for natural objects or
landscapes some categories are correct and others not. As it is correct to perceive the
Van Gogh as a post-impressionist painting, it is likewise correct to perceive the
whale as a mammal and the gator as an alligator. Lastly, analogous to the way
certain facts about works and their origins in part determine the correct categories
of art for them, certain facts about natural objects or landscapes and their origins in
part determine the correct categories of nature for them. As certain facts about the
Van Gogh and its history in part determine it to be a post-impressionist painting, so
certain facts about the whale and its natural history in part determine it to be a
mammal. Concerning the gator Ziff says the following:
Consider a gator basking in the sun on a mud bank in a swamp. Is he a fit
object for aesthetic attention? He is and that he is is readily confirmable. Go
look and see if you doubt what I say. He is presently to be seen around
Chokoloskee Island in the Everglades. What is in question is the American
alligator (Alligator mississipiensis) not to be confused with a crocodile. Gators
have shorter broader heads and more obtuse snouts. The fourth enlarged
tooth of a gator’s lower jaw fits into a pit formed for it in the upper jaw
whereas a crocodile’s fits into an external notch. It helps in viewing a gator to
see it as a gator and not as a crocodile. But that requires knowing something
about gators.
62
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 89
The account of the appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature suggested here can
be elaborated as follows: first, as in the case of art, the aesthetic qualities natural
objects and landscapes appear to have depend upon how they are perceived. The
rorqual whale is a graceful and majestic mammal. However, were it to be perceived
as a fish, it would appear more lumbering, somewhat oafish, perhaps even a bit clumsy
(maybe somewhat like the basking shark). Similarly the graceful and even elegant
moose would seem an awkward deer; the charming, cute woodchuck, a massive and
awe-inspiring brown rat; the delicate sunflower, a stiff and stodgy daisy. Concerning
landscapes, consider the example from Ronald Hepburn quoted in detail in
Chapter 5 in which he notes that, for example, a “wide expanse of sand and mud”
may appear to have different aesthetic qualities—“a wild, glad emptiness” as
opposed to “a disturbing weirdness”—depending upon whether it is perceived as a
beach or as a tidal basin.
63
Second, as in art appreciation, in these cases, to
appropriately appreciate the objects or landscapes in question aesthetically—to
appreciate their grace, majesty, elegance, charm, cuteness, delicacy, or “disturbing
weirdness”—it is necessary to perceive them in their correct categories. This requires
knowing what they are and knowing something about them—in the cases in
question, something of biology and geology. In general, it requires the knowledge
given by the natural sciences.
I think the above is essentially the correct account of the appropriate aesthetic
appreciation of nature. As noted, it is the account that I defended in more detail in
the preceding two chapters.
64
Moreover, it has plausibility simply in virtue of being
analogous to the assumed position in the aesthetic appreciation of art. If we do not
have an account that is analogous in this sense, we may be forced to accept one of
two alternatives: either that while the appreciation of art is aesthetic, the seemingly
similar appreciation of nature is not; or that even though they are both aesthetic,
they are yet different in their natures and/ or structures. Each of these alternatives is
implausible. I have argued for the implausibility of the first alternative in third
section of this chapter and have brought out some of the problems inherent in the
second alternative in the fourth and fifth sections. In the account sketched here,
however, our appreciation of nature is aesthetic and is analogous to that of art in
both its nature and its structure. The significant difference is that while, in art
appreciation, categories of art and the knowledge given by art criticism and art
history are relevant, in nature appreciation, the categories are natural categories and
the knowledge is that provided by natural history—by science. But this difference is
not unexpected; nature is not art.
In the immediately preceding section, I indicated how the growth of natural
science has promoted the aesthetic appreciation of nature and how scientific
knowledge is especially effective in enhancing it. According to the account outlined
here, scientific knowledge is essential for appropriate aesthetic appreciation of
nature; without it we do not know how to appreciate it appropriately and are likely
to miss its aesthetic qualities and value. Thus, if this account is correct, it explains
the ability of science to both promote and enhance aesthetic appreciation of the
90 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
natural world. Within the context of this chapter, the account also has another virtue:
it suggests a means by which to justify positive aesthetics.
Science and positive aesthetics
Positive aesthetics claims that the natural world is essentially aesthetically good. It
follows that the natural world must appear as such when it is appropriately
aesthetically appreciated. If the view sketched above is to account for this, the
natural world must appear aesthetically good when it is perceived in its correct
categories, those given and informed by natural science. If this is the case and we can
understand how and why it is, we thereby have a justification for the positive
aesthetics position. However, if the natural world seems aesthetically good when
perceived in its correct categories, this cannot be simply because they are correct; it
must be because of the kind of thing nature is and the kinds of categories that are
correct for it. This is because the analogous position in art appreciation does not
justify positive aesthetics concerning art. Works of art do not necessarily seem
aesthetically good when perceived in their correct categories. Yet the only
differences between the two views lie in the kind of thing nature is as opposed to art
and the kinds of categories that are correct for it as opposed to those for art. Thus, if
we are to find a justification for positive aesthetics, these differences must provide
the key.
To pursue this line of inquiry it is useful to see more clearly why works of art are
not necessarily aesthetically good, even when perceived in their correct categories.
Categories of art are established in light of certain facts about works of art and their
origins, such as their times and places of creation, their artists’ intentions, and their
societies’ traditions. The determinations of the correct categories for particular
works are also a function of such facts. Moreover, the determinations of the
aesthetic qualities that particular works or kinds of works have, and thus whether
they are aesthetically good or bad, are in part a function of what categories are
correct for them. For example, since it is a post-impressionist painting, The Starry
Night is aesthetically better than it would be were it an expressionist work. Thus, in
the case of art, determinations of categories and of their correctness are in general
prior to and independent of considerations of aesthetic goodness.
65
This helps to
explain why works of art are not necessarily aesthetically good and why there is no
positive aesthetics position concerning art. Categories of art are established in such a
way that even in their correct categories particular works may be aesthetically bad.
However, what if categories of art were established in a different way? In another
connection, Walton remarks:
Take any work of art we can agree is of fourth- or fifth- or tenth-rate quality.
It is quite possible that if this work were perceived in some far-fetched set of
categories that someone might dream up, it would appear to be first-rate, a
masterpiece. Finding such ad hoc categories obviously would require talent
and ingenuity on the order of that necessary to produce a masterpiece in the
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 91
first place. But we can sketch how one might begin searching for them… If
the mediocre work suffers from some disturbingly prominent feature that
distracts from whatever merits the work has, this feature might be toned down
by choosing categories… [such that]… When the work is perceived in the
new way the offending feature may be no more distracting than the flatness of
a painting is to us…If it needs ingenuity we might devise a set of rules in terms
of which the work finds itself in a dilemma and then ingeniously escapes from
it, and build these rules into a set of categories.
66
This passage describes how we might invent categories that would make works of
art seem aesthetically good. All that is required is that we take the works as given,
and create the categories in virtue of them, and with an eye to making them appear
aesthetically good.
Walton points out that this procedure would not make a work aesthetically good:
Surely, however, if there are categories…which would transform a mediocre
work into a masterpiece, it does not follow that the work really is a hitherto
unrecognized masterpiece. The fact that when perceived in such categories it
would appear exciting, ingenious, and so forth, rather than grating, cliché-
ridden, pedestrian, does not make it so.
67
Inventing categories that would seemingly transform mediocre works into
masterpieces would not make them masterpieces, because in our world no matter
how creatively such categories were produced, they would not be the correct
categories for the works in question. However, we can imagine a world different
from ours. Imagine one in which “works of art” are not created at all, but rather
discovered; and in which “artists” do not have to use their talents and ingenuity to
create works of art but rather use them to create categories in which the discovered
works appear to be masterpieces. Imagine further that the criterion for categories
being correct is that they make the works appear to be masterpieces. In such a world
determinations of categories and of their correctness would be dependent upon
considerations of aesthetic goodness; and (insofar as the artists accomplish their job)
all works of art would in fact be masterpieces. Or to put it another way, all works
would be essentially aesthetically good and appropriately appreciated as such. Our
imagined world would have positive aesthetics concerning art.
In light of the above it is possible to see the beginnings of a justification for
positive aesthetics concerning nature. The idea is that natural objects and landscapes
in our world are analogous to the works of art of our imagined world, and scientists
in our world are analogous to the artists of our imagined world. That the former is
the case is clear enough. Unlike works of art, natural objects and landscapes are not
created or produced by humans, but rather “discovered” by them. Only once they
are discovered can description, categorization, and theorizing proceed. Thus,
natural objects and landscapes are in a sense given, and then the categories of nature
are created in virtue of them.
92 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
The fact that the natural world is discovered suggests one way in which our
scientists are like the artists of our imagined world. Both begin with given objects
and use talent and ingenuity to create categories for them. However, the artists of
our imagined world determine correctness of categories by the criterion of aesthetic
goodness: the correct categories are those that make the given objects appear to be
masterpieces. It is not plausible to say that our scientists do simply that, but perhaps
they do something quite similar. Aesthetic goodness appears to play some
criterialogical role in the scientific enterprise. For example, it is claimed that
aesthetic goodness is one of the criteria by which science adjudicates between
conflicting descriptions, categorizations, and theories. However, even if this is the
case, aesthetic goodness is not the only criterion by which scientists determine
correctness of descriptions, categorizations, and theories. Rather the relationship
between correctness in science and aesthetic goodness must be both more complex
and more contingent.
Perhaps this relationship is somewhat like the following: a more correct
categorization in science is one that over time makes the natural world seem more
intelligible, more comprehensible to those whose science it is. Our science appeals to
certain kinds of qualities to accomplish this. These qualities are ones such as order,
regularity, harmony, balance, tension, resolution, and so forth. If our science did
not discover, uncover, and/or create such qualities in the natural world and explain
the world in terms of them, it would not accomplish its task of making it seem more
intelligible to us; rather, it would leave the world incomprehensible, as any of the
various world views that we regard as superstition seem to us to leave it. Moreover,
these qualities that make the world seem comprehensible to us are also those that we
find aesthetically good. Thus, when we experience them in the natural world or
experience the natural world in terms of them, we find it aesthetically good. This is
not surprising, for qualities such as order, regularity, harmony, balance, tension, and
resolution are the kinds of qualities that we find aesthetically good in art. This, I
take it, is the idea suggested by those who claim that science and art have similar
roots and/or goals; and by those who claim that science is in part an aesthetic
endeavor.
68
Beyond this, why there should be such a connection between aesthetic
goodness and scientific correctness is not clear. It may be a function of our biology
or of our culture; it may be a result of human evolution or an article of humanistic
faith; it may simply be a reflection of our superstition. However, here it is only
necessary to indicate that what we find aesthetically good plays an important role in
what our science takes to be correct.
It is now possible to summarize the suggested justification for the positive
aesthetics position. The key to the justification lies in the kind of thing nature is as
opposed to art and the kinds of categories that are correct for it as opposed to those
for art. Art is created, while nature is discovered. The determinations of categories
of art and of their correctness are in general prior to and independent of aesthetic
considerations, while the determinations of categories of nature and of their
correctness are in an important sense dependent upon aesthetic considerations.
These two differences are closely related. Since nature is discovered, rather than
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 93
created, in science, unlike in art, creativity plays its major role in the determinations
of categories and of their correctness; and considerations of aesthetic goodness come
into play at this creative level. Thus, our science creates categories of nature in part
in light of aesthetic goodness and in so doing makes the natural world appear
aesthetically good to us. Moreover, the categories created in this way are the correct
categories—those that involve appropriate aesthetic appreciation and reveal the
aesthetic qualities and value of the objects of that appreciation. Thus, these
categories not only make the natural world appear aesthetically good, but in virtue of
being correct determine that it is aesthetically good. Or to put the point in a simpler
way: the aesthetic situation concerning virgin nature in our world is essentially
analogous to that concerning art in our previously imagined world. Our natural
objects and landscapes, like its works of art, are discovered and categories are created
for them. Our scientists, like its artists, create these categories in virtue of these given
objects and, over the long run, with an eye toward aesthetic goodness. And in each
world these categories are the correct categories. Thus, our natural objects and
landscapes, like its works of art, are essentially aesthetically good. The result is that
we have positive aesthetics concerning nature as it would have positive aesthetics
concerning its art.
If this line of thought yields a justification for the positive aesthetics position, it
does so with an important qualification. The justification is not of the same kind as
those rejected earlier. For example, the divine justification, if adequate, would
support the claim not simply that virgin nature is aesthetically good, but also that it
always has been and always will be—whether anyone ever notices or not. The
justification developed here, however, regards the aesthetic appreciation of nature as
significantly informed by science and positive aesthetics as intimately related to the
development of science. Consequently, although aesthetic appreciation of nature is
perhaps informed by whatever world view is available, it seems that, outside the
temporal and spatial boundaries of the scientific world view, it is not informed by
science. Thus, positive aesthetics may not be a justifiable position outside these
boundaries. This justification is, as it were, within the scope of the scientific world
view. The nature and extent of positive aesthetics that is justified, therefore,
seemingly depends upon interpretations of science. In light of various views about
science, positive aesthetics might be, for example, absolute, culturally relative, or
paradigm relative.
69
To some this potential limitation of the positive aesthetic position may seem
unfortunate, but it nonetheless adds plausibility to the justification itself. It helps to
explain the close correlation between the development of natural science and the
development of the aesthetic appreciation of nature noted in the two previous
sections of this chapter. Moreover, if we construe the development of science as the
attempt to make the natural world seem more and more comprehensible to us, by
continual self-revision, whenever it appears less then fully comprehensible, then we
also have an explanation of the growth of positive aesthetics. If comprehensibility is
in part a function of qualities such as order, regularity, harmony, and balance, which
we find aesthetically good, then the development of science and its continual self-
94 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
revision constitutes a movement toward the aesthetically good. Or perhaps less
misleadingly, it constitutes a movement that puts the natural world in an
increasingly favorable aesthetic light. Such a movement seems evident in general and
also at more specific levels. The positive aesthetic appreciation of previously
abhorred landscapes, such as mountains and jungles, seems to have followed
developments in geology and geography.
70
Likewise, the positive aesthetic
appreciation of previously abhorred life forms, such as insects and reptiles, seems to
have followed developments in biology.
71
In retrospect, many of the advances in
natural science can be viewed as heralding a corresponding advance in positive
aesthetics. This in itself gives support to the justification suggested in this section.
In a similar way, if this justification is correct, another connection noted in
preceding sections falls into place—the connection between the development of
positive aesthetics as a position concerning the natural world in general and the
birth and growth of ecology. This is understandable in light of the fact that ecology
not only is in certain respects all encompassing, but also puts considerable emphasis
on qualities such as unity, harmony, and balance—ones we find particularly
aesthetically good. I indicated that the positive aesthetics position is most evident in
the writings of contemporary individuals especially concerned with ecology and
ecological issues. Perhaps this position is not simply to be justified as a scientific
aesthetic but is indeed what one individual terms the “ecological esthetic.”
72
The
position has seemingly come into its own with the development of ecology and
seemingly continues to grow in light of it. Some of the individuals noted earlier
suggest this. For example, Rolston writes:
We do not live in Eden, yet the trend is there, as ecological advance
increasingly finds in the natural given stability, beauty, and integrity, and we
are henceforth as willing to open our concepts to reformation by the world as
to prejudge the natural order.
73
Perhaps someday, at least concerning the natural world, we may all agree with
Constable, saying “I never saw an ugly thing in my life.”
74
Notes
1 For an enumeration of uses of “nature” in the appeal to nature for norms of art,
especially with reference to the eighteenth century, see Arthur Lovejoy,” ‘Nature’ as
Aesthetic Norm,” Modern Language Notes, 1927, vol. 42, pp. 444–50. For a brief
discussion of the eighteenth-century point of view, see Harold Osborne, “The Use of
Nature in Art,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1962, vol. 2, pp. 318–27.
2 The comment is quoted and dated in Andrew Forge, “Art/Nature,” Philosophy and the
Arts: Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, London, Macmillan, 1973, vol. 6, pp. 231.
Forge remarks: “The position that he was affirming was to be an ingredient in almost
all the most vital painting of the next sixty years.”
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 95
3John Ruskin, The Elements of Drawing [1857], New York, Dover, 1971, pp. 128–9.
The passage continues:
The rock on which the effect of a mountain scene especially depends is
always precisely that which the roadmaker blasts or the landlord quarries;
and the spot of green which Nature left with a special purpose by her
dark forest sides, and finished with her most delicate grasses, is always
that which the farmer ploughs or builds upon. But the clouds…cannot
be quarried nor built over, and they are always therefore gloriously
arranged;…they all move and burn together in a marvellous harmony;
not a cloud of them is out of its appointed place, or fails of its part.
4 The two characterizations are from respectively Lewis Mumford, The Brown Decades:
A Study of the Arts in America, 1865–1895, New York, Harcourt, Brace and Co., 1931,
p. 78 and Stewart L.Udall, The Quiet Crisis, New York, Holt, Rinehart and Winston,
1963, p. 82. Both are quoted by David Lowenthal in his introduction to George
Perkins Marsh, Man and Nature [1864], Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1965,
pp. ix and xxii.
5 Ibid., pp. 8–9.
6William Morris, An and the Beauty of the Earth: A Lecture Delivered at Burslem Town
Hall on October 13, 1881, London, Longmans and Company, 1898, p. 24. For
Morris’s thoughts on landscape reform, see William Morris, The Beauty of Life: An
Address Delivered at the Town Hall, Birmingham, in 1880, London, Brethan Press,
1974, especially pp. 10–18.
7 John Muir,The Wild Parks and Forest Reservations of the West, in Our National
Parks, Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 1916, pp. 6–7.
8 David Lowenthal, “The American Scene,” Geographical Review, 1968, vol. 58, p. 81.
9 Leonard A.Fels, “Aesthetic Decision-Making and Human Ecology,” in Proceedings of
the VIIth International Congress of Aesthetics, Bucharest, Editura Academiei Republic
Socialist Romania, 1977, p. 369.
10 Lilly-Marlene Russow, “Why Do Species Matter?,” Environmental Ethics, 1981, vol. 3.
p. 109.
11 Kenneth H.Simonsen, “The Value of Wildness,” Environmental Ethics, 1981, vol. 3,
p. 263.
12 Holmes Rolston, III, “Can and Ought We to Follow Nature?,” Environmental Ethics,
1979, vol. 1, pp. 23–4. Later in the article Rolston qualifies this claim somewhat: “My
concept of the good is not coextensive with the natural, but it does greatly overlap it;
and I find my estimate steadily enlarging that overlap” (p. 28). See also Holmes
Rolston, III, “Is There an Ecological Ethic?,” Ethics, 1975, vol. 85, pp. 102–3.
13 Joseph W.Meeker, The Comedy of Survival: Studies in Literary Ecology, New York,
Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1974, p. 129. Meeker, following Konrad Lorenz, holds that in
both animals and man “wild” characteristics are beautiful and “virtually all characters
we perceive as specifically ugly are genuine domestication effects” (see pp. 121–4). The
source is Konrad Lorenz, Studies in Animal and Human Behavior, London, Methuen,
1971. See also Yi-Fu Tuan, “Visual Blight: Exercises in Interpretation,” Visual Blight
in America, Commission on College Geography Resource Paper no. 23, Washington,
96 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
D.C., Association of American Geographers, 1973, p. 27. Tuan attributes the root
idea to Susanne Langer, Feeling and Form, New York, Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1953.
14 Meeker, op. cit., p. 136.
15 Robert Elliot, “Faking Nature,” Inquiry, 1982, vol. 25, p. 84. Elliot does not take
himself to be discussing aesthetic appreciation and evaluation in this article, but rather
what he terms “environmental evaluation,” which he holds is differentiated
from aesthetic evaluation by “the judgmental element” in the latter (see p. 90). As I
indicate in the next section, I believe that the argument for making this differentiation
is not adequate and that he is mistaken in thinking that the relevant judgments and
evaluations are not genuinely aesthetic. Consequently I consider his view a moderate
version of positive aesthetics.
16 Ibid., pp. 86–7.
17 Ibid., p. 87.
18 Elliot’s argument is similar to that of Nelson Goodman in Chapter 3 of Languages of Art,
Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill, 1968.
19 Aarne Kinnunen, “Luonnonestetiikka,” in Aarne Kinnunen and Yrjo Sepanmaa (eds)
Ymparistoestetiikka, Helsinki, Gaudeamus, 1981, p. 49. The quote is translated from
the original Finnish by Anja Sahuri. Kinnunen’s idea of positive aesthetics is also
discussed in Yrjo Sepanmaa, “Ymparistoestetiikka,” in Yrjo Varpio (ed.)
Taiteentutkimaksen Perusteet, Helsinki, Werner Soderstrom Osakeyhtio, 1982, pp. 33–
46. I am grateful to Yrjo Sepanmaa for his contribution to my thinking about the
topic of this chapter. Many of the relevant ideas and sources came to my attention
during a series of fruitful discussions with him throughout 1982. I also thank J.Baird
Callicott and Mark Sagoff for helpful comments.
20 Elliot, op. cit., p. 90. All the short quotes from Elliot in this section are also from p.
90.
21 Osborne, op. cit., p. 325. See also Don Mannison, “A Prolegomenon To a Human
Chauvinistic Aesthetic,” in D.S.Mannison, M.A.McRobbie, R.Routley (eds)
Environmental Philosophy, Canberra, Australia National University, 1980, pp. 212–16.
22 This view is endorsed by theories of aesthetic appreciation as diverse as those held by,
for example, George Dickie and Jerome Stolnitz. Stolnitz says that “the aesthetic
attitude can be adopted toward ‘any object of awareness whatsoever.’” See Jerome
Stolnitz, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art Criticism, New York, Houghton Mifflin,
1960, pp. 402. Dickie holds that limiting an aesthetic theory in virtue of the
“appreciatability” of objects “is vacuous, since it is unlikely that any object would lack
some quality which is appreciatable.” See George Dickie, “A Response to Cohen: The
Actuality of Art,” in George Dickie and R.J.Sclafani (eds) Aesthetics: A Critical
Anthology, New York, St. Martin’s, 1977, p. 200.
23 Paul Ziff, “Anything Viewed,” in Esa Saarinen, Risto Hilpinen, Ilkka Niiniluoto, and
Merrill Provence Hintikka (eds) Essays in Honour of Jaakko Hintikka, Dordrecht,
Reidel, 1979, p. 285.
24 Neil Evernden, “The Ambiguous Landscape,” Geographical Review, 1981, vol. 71, p.
155.
25 Ziff, op. cit., p. 293.
26 Elliot’s claim is actually that the “apparently integral part of aesthetic evaluation
depends on viewing the aesthetic object as an intentional object, as an artifact, as
something that is shaped by the purposes and the design of its author,” not that it
depends on the object having these features. This further weakens the argument.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 97
Given this, all that is required for environmental evaluations to involve the “apparently
integral part of aesthetic evaluation” and thus be aesthetic is for the appreciator to
either mistakenly or intentionally view the natural world as having these features.
Although it is certainly possible for an appreciator to view nature in this way, I do not
develop this weakness, for I agree with the spirit of many of Elliot’s remarks that suggest
that this would be an incorrect, inappropriate, or at least misleading way to view any
natural environment. I discuss some of the problematic aspects of viewing the natural
world in such ways in “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–75 (reproduced in this volume,
Chapter 4).
27 Ziff, op. cit., pp. 286–7.
28 The most important sources are Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry into the
Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful [1757], J.T.Boulton (ed.), London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958, and Immanuel Kant, Observations on the Feeling of
the Beautiful and Sublime [1763], trans. J.T.Goldthwait, Berkeley, California, 1965
and Critique of Judgment [1790], trans. J.H.Bernard, New York, Hafner, 1968.
29 Simonsen, op. cit., p. 261.
30 Ibid., p. 263. All the short quotes from Simonsen in the remainder of this section are
also from p. 263.
31 Nelson Potter, “Aesthetic Value in Nature and in the Arts, in Hugh Curtler (ed.)
What is Art?, New York, Haven Publications, 1983, pp. 142–3.
32 Simonsen, op. cit., p. 263.
33 Potter, op. cit., pp. 142–3.
34 Ibid., p. 143.
35 Ibid., p. 143.
36 For example, John Hick contends that so far as Judaic-Christian theism is concerned
certain solutions to the problem of evil “have to be ruled out.” Within this context, he
holds, solutions which fall within my first category are “impossible” and those which
fall within my second category “have abandoned the basic premise of Hebrew-
Christian Monotheism.” His entire discussion of traditional and contemporary attempts
to solve the problem concerns theodicy. See John Hick, Philosophy of Religion,
Englewood Cliffs, Prentice-Hall, 1963, pp. 44–7.
37 A classic statement of this view is Lynn White, Jr.,The Historical Roots of Our
Ecologic Crisis,” Science, 1967, vol. 155, pp. 1203–7.
38 Ronald Rees, “The Taste for Mountain Scenery,” History Today, 1975, vol. 25, p.
307.
39 Ibid., p. 308; quoted from Thomas Burnet, Sacred Theory of the Earth [1684].
40 Victor Romanenko, “The Beauty of Nature,” trans. Bernard Isaacs, in S.Mozhnyagun
(ed.) Problems of Modern Aesthetics, Moscow, Progress Publishers, 1969, p. 143.
41 Ibid., p. 139.
42 Marjorie Hope Nicolson, Mountain Gloom and Mountain Glory, Ithaca, Cornell
University Press, 1959. It is generally accepted that art, especially landscape painting,
has played an important role in the development of nature appreciation. See, for
example, Alfred Biese, The Development of the Feeling for Nature in the Middle Ages and
Modern Times, New York, Burt Franklin, 1905, E.W.Manwaring, Italian Landscape in
XVIII Century England, New York, Oxford University Press, 1925, or Christopher
Hussey, The Picturesque, London, G.P.Putnam’s, 1927. To understand the complexity
of the subtle interplay between art, science, and nature appreciation, in particular in
98 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
relation to North American environmental attitudes, see Eugene Hargrove, “The
Historical Foundations of American Environmental Attitudes,” Environmental Ethics,
1979, vol. 1, pp. 209–40.
43 Romanenko, op. cit., p. 143.
44 Ibid., p. 141.
45 John Constable, from his last public lecture, delivered at the Royal Institution of
Great Britain in 1836. Quoted in Ronald Rees, “John Constable and the Art of
Geography,” Geographical Review, 1976, vol. 66, p. 59.
46 Ibid., pp. 59–61; quoted from John Constable, in C.R.Leslie (ed.) Memoirs of John
Constable, London, Phaidon, 1951, p. 272. On Constable and science, see also E.H.
Gombrich, Art and Illusion, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1961, especially
part I.
47 Rees, “John Constable and the Art of Geography,” op. cit., p. 59. On the role of
science in Ruskin’s thought, see Denis E.Cosgrove, “John Ruskin and the
Geographical Imagination,Geographical Review, 1979, vol. 69, pp. 43–62.
48 With the exception of the second and the sixth, these are respectively, the titles of the
following articles: Fels, op. cit., Rolston, “Can and Ought We to Follow Nature?,” op.
cit., Rolston, “Is there an Ecological Ethics?,” op. cit., and Simonsen, op. cit. The
second and sixth are chapter and section titles from Meeker, op. cit.
49 Kinnunen, op. cit., pp. 47–8.
50 Elliot, op. cit., p. 91.
51 Rolston, “Can and Ought We to Follow Nature?,” op. cit., p. 23.
52 Rolston, “Is There an Ecological Ethic?,” op. cit., p. 107. Rolston is quoting the last
three words from Aldo Leopold, “The Land Ethic,” A Sand County Almanac, New
York, Oxford University Press, 1949, p. 223. In these articles Rolston is more
concerned with moral than with aesthetic value.
53 Meeker, op. cit., pp. 124–5.
54 Biese, op. cit., p. 357.
55 Val Routley, “Critical Notice of John Passmore, Man’s Responsibility for Nature,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1975, vol. 53, p. 183.
56 Elliot, op. cit., p. 91.
57 Rolston, “Is there an Ecological Ethic?,” op. cit., pp. 100–1.
58 Routley, op. cit., p. 183.
59 Kendall Walton, “Categories of Art,” Philosophical Review, 1970, vol. 79, p. 364.
60 Paul Ziff, “Reasons in Art Criticism,” in W.E.Kennick (ed.) Art and Philosophy:
Readings in Aesthetics, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 1964, p. 620.
61 Walton, op. cit., p. 338–9.
62 Ziff, “Anything Viewed,” op. cit., p. 291.
63 Ronald Hepburn, “Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” in Harold Osborne (ed.)
Aesthetics in the Modern World, London, Thames and Hudson, 1968, p. 55.
64 See my “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” op. cit., (reproduced in this
volume, Chapter 4) and especially “Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Objectivity,”
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1981, vol. 40, pp. 15–27 (reproduced in this
volume, Chapter 5). In the latter chapter, as here, I utilize some of the terminology
introduced by Walton in “Categories of Art,” op. cit. In that article Walton does not
apply his category approach to the aesthetic appreciation of nature and in fact
expresses doubts about the possibility of doing so. However, in subsequent
conversations, he has agreed that it is plausible to understand the aesthetic appreciation
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 99
of nature in terms of natural categories, as I argue in “Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and
Objectivity.”
65 In Walton’s account the two are not necessarily independent, for he holds that the
fact, if it is one, that a work is more interesting or pleasing aesthetically when perceived
in a given category than it is when perceived in alternative ways is a circumstance that
counts “toward its being correct to perceive a work” in that category (op. cit., p. 357).
I think this is mistaken; see “Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Objectivity,” op. cit.
(reproduced in this volume, Chapter 5).
66 Walton, op. cit., pp. 359–60.
67 Ibid., p. 360.
68 These and related claims are illustrated and discussed in Judith Wechsler (ed.)
Aesthetics in Science, Cambridge, Massachusetts, The MIT Press, 1978. The theme of
the collection, ibid., pp. 6, 1, is:
The search in science for models that illuminate nature seems to
parallel certain crucial processes in art… When scientists…reflect on
their work, the development of concepts, and the theories that expound
them, it is evident that intuition and aesthetics guide their sense of “this
is how it has to be,” their sense of rightness.
69 Another possible qualification is that the justification offered here supports positive
aesthetic appreciation of kinds of natural things but not of natural particulars. I doubt
this because, given the role of aesthetic goodness in scientific description,
categorization, and theorizing, I suspect that scientific knowledge as a whole is
aesthetically imbued such that our appreciation of particulars is as enhanced as is that
of kinds.
70 Positive aesthetic appreciation of unfamiliar landscapes such as volcanic mountains
and tropical jungles was probably greatly enhanced by the scientific discoveries and
writings of Alexander von Humboldt. It is noteworthy that his Ansichter der Natur
[1808] went through three editions and was translated into nearly every European
language by the time of his death in 1859. For a brief discussion of Humboldt’s
influence on the aesthetics of nature, see Edmunds Bunkse, “Humboldt and an Aesthetic
Tradition in Geography,” Geographical Review, 1981, vol. 71, pp. 127–46.
71 Concerning positive aesthetic appreciation of life, Darwin is particularly important. It
is sometimes contended that Darwin’s work had an adverse effect on the appreciation
of nature. For example, Rolston notes: “After Darwin (through misunderstanding
him, perhaps), the world of design collapsed, and nature, for all its law, seemed
random, accidental, chaotic, blind, crude.” “Is There an Ecological Ethic?,” op. cit., p.
107). I agree that this may involve misunderstanding and think there is insight in
Romanenko’s remark that “everything, which before the days of Darwin had borne the
stamp of ‘divine origin’, the beauty of nature included, was passed down to the earth
from heaven” (op. cit., p. 141). For example, prior to Darwin’s demonstration of the
transmutability of species these important categories of nature could be viewed as God-
given. Darwin’s work shows how they are the result of the human endeavors of
scientific discovery, generalization, and decision. In addition, the expurgation of divine
design effected by Darwin’s work undercuts the grounds for certain kinds of negative
aesthetic judgments about certain aspects of nature. Darwin’s view that evolution has
100 NATURE AND POSITIVE AESTHETICS
no overall direction and that all life forms must be accounted for in the same natural
terms, gives no basis for viewing some as aesthetically inferior to others. As Stephen
Jay Gould remarks, in light of the view that evolution “does not lead inevitably to
higher things… The ‘degeneracy’ of a parasite is as perfect as the gait of a gazelle.” See
Stephen Jay Gould, Ever Since Darwin, New York, W.W.Norton, 1977, p. 13.
72 Meeker, op. cit., p. 119.
73 Rolston, “Is there an Ecological Ethic?,” op. cit., p. 108.
74 It may be thought that a conclusive objection to this justification is simply that it
tends to justify positive aesthetics, a position that is somewhat implausible. In short,
the objection is that since there is much in the natural world that we do not find
aesthetically good, any justification of the position must be incorrect. I agree that there
is much in the natural world that appears to many of us not to be aesthetically good.
However, this fact itself does not constitute a conclusive objection, for the justification
provides the means of showing how the fact is consistent with the positive aesthetics
position. First, as suggested by Rolston’s remark that “we do not live in Eden, yet the
trend is there,” it is understandable if at the present we do not find all the natural
world essentially beautiful. If our positive aesthetic appreciation of nature follows and
is dependent upon the development of science, then it is to be expected that at this
point in time there is much in the natural world that we do not yet find aesthetically
good. Moreover, this is especially to be expected if the most relevant “science” is
ecology, for it is not only a comparatively recent development but has yet to achieve
the status of a mature science. For useful discussion, see Robert T. McIntosh, “The
Background and Some Current Problems of Theoretical Ecology,” in Esa Saarinen
(ed.) Conceptual Issues in Ecology, Dordrecht, Reidel, 1982, pp. 1–61. Second,
although the correct categories for the aesthetic appreciation of the natural world are
natural categories, there are other categories in terms of which we do, as a matter of
fact, occasionally perceive nature. When nature is perceived in such categories, there
is, according to this justification, no reason why positive aesthetic appreciation should
result. Indeed, when so perceived, much of the natural world may appear aesthetically
second-rate—bland, dull, insipid, incoherent, chaotic, and the like. Whether or not
certain of these other categories should also be accepted as correct categories for the
natural world is another issue. Although this cannot be pursued here, I, as suggested
previously, am inclined to think that they should not be so accepted—at least not for
virgin nature (and not within the scientific world view).
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 101
102
7
APPRECIATING ART AND
APPRECIATING NATURE
The concept of appreciation
The concept of appreciation is common to both art appreciation and nature
appreciation. However, it is usually not examined in the relevant theoretical work.
Writings on appreciating art by art critics and art historians seldom touch on it.
Nature literature may exemplify it but typically does not discuss it. Investigations of
aesthetic appreciation by aestheticians dwell on the nature of the aesthetic and have
little to say about appreciation. That the concept is not discussed is a pity, for it is
central both to philosophical aesthetics and to our day-to-day dealings with such
matters. Not only are the notions of art appreciation and nature appreciation in
common usage, but we move with ease from the appreciation of landscapes to that
of landscape paintings, from appreciating Van Gogh’s The Starry Night (1889) to
appreciating the starry heavens above. Yet the nature of appreciation is far from
clear and what is involved in each of these two central cases—appreciating art and
appreciating nature—remains obscure.
Thus, some clarification of appreciation is useful. To achieve it, since the topic of
this chapter is the appreciation of both art and nature, it is appropriate to consider a
philosophical tradition that in its infancy thought nature at least as significant as art
as an object of aesthetic appreciation. This tradition, which was introduced and
briefly considered in Chapters 1 and 2, ties appreciation to notions such as
disinterestedness. Although this position like most others in philosophical aesthetics
is more concerned with the aesthetic than with appreciation, it yet provides insight
into the nature of appreciation. Equally important, it points the way to a flaw in
much philosophical thinking about appreciation—a flaw that apparently stems from
its myopic focus on the aesthetic. Both the insight and the flaw can be clarified,
adequately for present purposes, by considering the recent version of the position
presented by Jerome Stolnitz and the attack on it by George Dickie.
1
Stolnitz’s
elaboration of “the aesthetic attitude” illustrates the insight; Dickie’s elaboration of
“the myth of the aesthetic attitude” brings out the flaw.
Stolnitz’s version of the disinterestedness position focuses on a special attitude,
the aesthetic attitude, defined as “disinterested and sympathetic attention to and
contemplation of any object of awareness whatever, for its own sake alone.”
2
True to
the tradition, Stolnitz does not directly discuss aesthetic appreciation. However, it is
to be treated, it may be assumed, as related notions such as “aesthetic experience”
which are “defined by reference to” the aesthetic attitude.
3
Thus, aesthetic
appreciation would be defined as the total appreciation engaged in while this attitude
is being taken. Consequently, insights into the nature of appreciation are provided
in Stolnitz’s remarks about taking the aesthetic attitude.
The most fundamental of these insights about aesthetic appreciation concerns what
may be termed its scope. Although at points in its history the disinterestedness
tradition apparently judged certain kinds of objects to be closed to disinterested
attention and therefore essentially nonaesthetic, the tradition by and large
emphasizes a broad scope for appreciation. This is cited by Stolnitz as one of two
major reasons for preferring this line of approach to others. In Stolnitz’s version of
the position the scope is in fact “limitless” in that the “aesthetic attitude can be
adopted toward ‘any object of awareness whatever.’”
4
The recognition of such a
scope for aesthetic appreciation is particularly important for understanding nature
appreciation, for nature, noted for diversity, comes in all shapes and sizes and all types
and kinds, many seemingly not tailor-made for appreciation as are paradigmatic
works of art.
A second significant dimension of appreciation can be clarified by noting how it
differs from some other notions utilized in the tradition and in fact contained in
Stolnitz’s definition—notions such as contemplation and awareness. Here Stolnitz’s
appeal to the concept of an attitude is helpful, although often it is simply
misleading. As Stolnitz emphasizes, attitudes are directive, they organize, orientate,
and guide. This directive nature “prepares us to respond” and the responsiveness of
appreciation separates it from passive states such as contemplation or awareness.
5
Indeed, Stolnitz thinks it “safe” to use the word “contemplation” only after stressing
that taking the aesthetic attitude is an “alert and vigorous” business in which we
focus “discriminating attention” upon the object,” ‘key up’ our capacities of
imagination and emotion to respond to it,” and engage in a range of emotional,
cognitive, and physical “activity.”
6
In this way appreciation is severed from what
Stolnitz describes as the “blank, cow-like stare” often associated with
contemplation, with disinterestedness, and with the aesthetic itself.
7
Rather it is
aligned with the slogan Stolnitz adopts from a psychologist: “Appreciation…is
awareness, alertness, animation.”
8
The active nature of appreciation helps to illuminate the flaw that mars the
tradition’s treatment of it, a flaw central to Dickie’s attack. The problem develops
because, unlike either a blank, cow-like stare that needs no guidance or serene
contemplation that needs only a little, active, responsive appreciation requires
considerable guidance. Stolnitz relies on attitudes here, which since they organize,
orientate, and guide, provide by means of the aesthetic attitude, a general aesthetic
criterion for the guidance of appreciation. Dickie attacks this as the first way the
disinterestedness tradition “misleads aesthetic theory”: the way it sets “the limits of
aesthetic relevance.”
9
This may be called the question of aesthetic relevance, the
question of how to guide appreciation or, more precisely, how to determine what is
104 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
relevant to the appropriate appreciation of particular objects. It is not only the issue
upon which the disinterestedness treatment of appreciation stumbles, it is a key
issue in any such treatment.
The tradition’s problems with aesthetic relevance stem from a tension among its
essential elements. The tension is present throughout the tradition but is especially
evident in Stolnitz’s definition which requires attention to be both disinterested and
sympathetic. Disinterestedness pulls toward the general criterion of aesthetic
relevance, sympathy in the other direction. The tension is illuminated by the
responsive nature of appreciation. By contrast, the blank cow-like stare can be both
disinterested and sympathetic. What does it matter? It does not respond. But since
appreciation is responsive, to sympathetically respond it must, as Stolnitz says,
“accept the object ‘on its own terms,’” “follow the lead of the object and respond in
concert with it”—only in this way can we “relish its individual quality.”
10
On the
other hand, disinterestedness requires an experience that “at its best, seems to isolate
both us and the object from the flow of experience,” one in which the object “is
divorced from its interrelations with other things.”
11
The question is what “other
things” then—in particular, what, as Stolnitz puts it, “thoughts or images or bits of
knowledge which are not present within the object itself’—are relevant to its
appreciation?
12
The tradition’s answer—the general criterion of aesthetic relevance
is that it depends on whether any such thought, image, or bit of knowledge is
“aesthetic,” which in turn “depends on whether it is compatible with the attitude of
‘disinterested attention.’”
13
The upshot is that much that might enhance the
appreciation of an object—help us to “relish its individual quality”—is condemned
as nonaesthetic and therefore as irrelevant to aesthetic appreciation.
Thus, the elaborations of disinterestedness and sympathy place these two
concepts at odds. To make the conflict perfectly clear only requires the right kinds of
objects. In responsive appreciation we must “follow the lead of the object” yet
isolate and divorce it and ourselves from “its interrelations with other things,” unless
such things are compatible with “disinterested attention.” But what if an object does
not lead in that direction, what if it resists being isolated and divorced from its
interrelations? Indeed, although some works of art may be “aesthetic” in the sense
that they readily yield to being—in fact are explicitly created to be—so isolated and
divorced, many other works and most nonart, and nature in particular, are precisely
not “aesthetic” in this limiting sense. Thus, to respond to such objects as if they
were is not to follow their lead, not to be sympathetic to them, not to appreciate
them. Does this mean that these “nonaesthetic” objects that cling to their
interrelations with other things are therefore closed to “disinterested attention”?
This cannot be, for, as noted, at least at this late date in the tradition, the aesthetic
attitude is limitless, it can be taken toward “any object of awareness whatever.” It
becomes clear that something must go.
As is typical in such cases, however, the reaction is an overreaction. It is clear that
something must go and what has gone is most of the disinterestedness tradition
along with its insight concerning appreciation. The isolation of the appreciator and
the object and the divorcing of the latter from its interrelations, all seemingly
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 105
required by disinterestedness, are taken, with some justification, to after all reduce
appreciation to the notorious cow-like stare. With this reductio in mind, critics lose
sight of the rich, expansive, and responsive notion of appreciation contained in the
tradition. Indeed, some reactions are more extreme. Dickie, for example,
overreacting to his own critique, seemingly rejects the very concept of the aesthetic,
stating that “there is no reason to think that there is a special kind of aesthetic
consciousness, attention, or perception.” He adds: “Similarly, I do not think there is
any reason to think that there is a special kind of aesthetic appreciation.”
14
This may
be to throw out the baby with the bath water, but it has a point: the problem with
the disinterestedness tradition, as with philosophical aesthetics in general, is that too
much attention is paid to the concept of the aesthetic and too little to that of
appreciation. The attempt to accommodate the former warps disinterestedness and
therefore appreciation itself into a restrictive and isolating state, caricaturizable as
the cow-like stare. A shift of emphasis to the latter yields a different picture.
Interesting enough, such a shift of emphasis, together with its happy
consequences, is evident within the disinterestedness tradition itself. For example,
once Stolnitz moves from philosophical analysis of the aesthetic attitude to
consideration of art appreciation, the story changes dramatically. Instead of the
strict application of the general criterion of aesthetic relevance, we find that
concerning, for instance, the issue of relevant knowledge: “We need not, however,
condemn all ‘knowledge about’ as aesthetically irrelevant… ‘Knowledge about’ is
relevant under three conditions: when it does not weaken or destroy aesthetic
attention to the object, when it pertains to the meaning and expressiveness of the
object, and when it enhances the quality and significance of one’s immediate
aesthetic response to the object.”
15
Note that only the first condition accommodates
the aesthetic; the latter two aim at enhancing the appreciation of the object. With
the emphasis thus shifted to appreciation, sympathy outweighs disinterestedness,
and we truly “follow the lead of the object.” Moreover, it is now not the blind
leading the blind, for the aestheticizing cow-like stare gives way to appreciation not
only responsive to the object but informed by knowledge about it.
The shift of emphasis to appreciation is followed up by Paul Ziff. Ziff’s treatment
is informative in that it retains the insights of the disinterestedness position without
embracing its flaws.
16
As noted in Chapters 4 and 6, the essence of his account is
the notion of an “act of aspection,” the way of attending to an object that in part
constitutes its appropriate appreciation.
17
Ziff argues that different acts of aspection
are appropriate in the appreciation of, for example, works of art of different kinds,
styles, and schools. Thus, knowledge of a work’s history and nature dictates the
proper acts of aspection: appreciation is a set of activities not only responsive to the
object but incorporating knowledge of it as an essential component. Ziff further
argues not simply that “anything that can be viewed is a fit object for aesthetic
attention,” but that “anything viewed makes demands.”
18
That objects of
appreciation make demands means that following the lead of the object rules out
the possibility of anything like a general criterion of aesthetic relevance. Since
objects of appreciation obviously differ a great deal, so does what is relevant to and
106 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
involved in their appreciation: “As the character of the objects attended to vary, the
character of the actions, the conditions, and the requisite qualities, skills, and
capacities of the person may also have to vary, if attention to the objects is to be
aesthetically worthwhile.”
19
Thus, the appreciation of each of, to use some of Ziff’s
examples, a work of art by Leonardo Da Vinci, a Barry McKenzie comic strip, an
alligator basking in the sun, or a pile of dried dung requires engaging in different
acts of aspection, using different capacities and skills, and knowing different things.
The general criterion of aesthetic relevance is replaced by object-given indications of
appreciative relevance.
Stolnitz’s and Ziff’s remarks on appreciation demonstrate that although
philosophical aesthetics has relatively little to say about the concept, it is yet possible
to derive from its investigation of the aesthetic some useful observations. Ironically
it is precisely in drawing back from the tradition’s obsession with the aesthetic that
the concept of appreciation is brought into focus. The obsession with the aesthetic
inhibits a proper understanding of appreciation by pulling in the direction of a
passive state of limited scope, restricted by a general criterion of aesthetic relevance,
and comparable to a blank, cow-like stare. By contrast, the concept of appreciation
that can be coaxed from philosophical aesthetics, seemingly almost against its will,
reveals appreciation as engaged mental and physical activity applicable to any object
whatever, exceedingly responsive to that object, and guided almost exclusively by its
nature.
We may conclude this discussion of appreciation by asking, in light of the object-
orientated nature of appreciation, what remains of the idea that the tradition
attempts to capture with concepts such as disinterestedness? What becomes of the
isolating attention intended to divorce both the object and the appreciator from all
that is irrelevant to the object’s appreciation? In fact there is in the object-orientated
notion a significant residue of this idea. It is that to follow the lead of the object and
be guided by it is to be “object-ively” guided. This sense of objective is the most
basic: it concerns the object and its properties and is opposed to the subjective in the
sense of concerning the subject and its properties. Appreciating objectively in this
sense is appreciating the object as and for what it is and as and for having the
properties it has. It is in opposition to appreciating subjectively in which the subject
—the appreciator—and its properties are in some way imposed on the object, or,
more generally, something other than the object is imposed on it.
Thus, the insight of the disinterestedness part of the tradition is that, insofar as
appreciation is disinterested, it is objective. And when it fails to be, it is in a
corresponding sense subjective and involves viewing the object as something it is
not or as having properties it does not have. Thus, appreciation is isolating only in
the sense that both object and appreciator must be divorced from that which is not
true of the object. In short, it is the false that is incompatible with disinterested
attention and therefore irrelevant to aesthetic appreciation. The insight contained in
the passive, blank, cow-like stare is that it limits itself to the dull, objective truth.
Moreover, in that disinterestedness constitutes part of the analysis of the aesthetic,
aesthetic appreciation is therefore no more nor less than appreciation in this sense
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 107
objective.
20
To appreciate something aesthetically is to appreciate it as and for, to
use the phrase Butler coined in another context, “what it is, and not another
thing.”
21
No wonder everything is open to aesthetic appreciation.
The notion of object-orientated aesthetic appreciation that thus emerges from
philosophical aesthetics is precisely the kind of concept required for a fruitful
investigation of appreciating art and appreciating nature. Given the “limitless” scope
that it grants appreciation, such a notion is especially useful in understanding the
appreciation of diverse kinds of things, such as works of art and natural objects.
Moreover, the concept of object-orientated appreciation facilitates the constructive
comparison of different kinds of appreciation, of art appreciation and nature
appreciation, without the assimilation of one to the other. Without a concept of
appreciation that allows, indeed requires, appreciative activity to respond directly to
and to vary according to the nature of different kinds of objects, there is a danger of
all appreciation being assimilated to one model—typically that of the appreciation of
the most conventional kind of art. However, although it must not be taken as the
model for all other forms of appreciation, the appreciation of conventional and
therefore paradigmatic works of art is yet the proper starting point for any
investigation of different kinds of appreciation.
Appreciating art: design appreciation
What is involved in the appreciation of paradigmatic works of art or, more
precisely, what is paradigmatic art appreciation? Given the object-orientated nature
of appreciation, there must be diverse kinds of art appreciation, each requiring
engaging in different physical and mental acts of aspection, using different capacities
and skills, and knowing different things. Indeed, they may have little in common,
not even the utilization of any one sense modality. Nonetheless, the question is
what is central to all of these many diverse kinds of appreciation—what in general is
significant in art appreciation? Seemingly the only possible answer is the
appreciation of design: paradigmatic art appreciation must be at least appreciation
of a thing as something designed and therefore as something that is the creation of a
designer. To put it another way, appreciation of art qua art must be appreciation
qua creation of an artist.
That art appreciation is artist or designer centered seems an obvious point, but it
is not always fully appreciated in philosophical aesthetics. To some extent the
prominence of the disinterestedness tradition is responsible. As noted, when
developed in certain ways, the notion of disinterestedness requires that the object of
appreciation be isolated and divorced from its interrelationships with other things,
its appreciation being strictly constrained by the general criterion of aesthetic
relevance. The result is a purified aesthetic object, divorced from its own history,
even from the fact that it is the product of a designer. Moreover, in recent
philosophy of art criticism this perverse offspring of disinterestedness gives comfort
to and joins with anti-intentionalism in an attempt to ban almost any knowledge of
the artist from the appreciation of his or her creations.
22
Thus, the disinterestedness
108 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
tradition, with a little assistance, completely obscures the designer-centered nature
of paradigmatic art appreciation.
This line of thought, however, stems from the same mishandling of
disinterestedness that obscures the object-orientated nature of appreciation.
Consider the fact that even if a work is explicitly designed by its creator to be an
isolated, pure aesthetic object, narrowly “aesthetic” in the sense required by the
general criterion of aesthetic relevance, it is nonetheless still designed by its creator to
be that way. Thus, appreciation that to any extent follows the lead of the object,
although it may appropriately ignore many other facts about such an object, simply
cannot ignore the central fact that the object is designed to be the way it is—that its
being designed is the essence of its being “what it is and not another thing.”
Consequently, in that appreciation is objective in the sense noted in the first section
of this chapter, the fact that paradigmatic art appreciation is designer centered
likewise cannot be ignored. The failure to appreciate this is one of the major ways
philosophical aesthetics is misled by its disregard for the concept of appreciation and
its obsession with the aesthetic.
Whatever the state of affairs in philosophical aesthetics, the point that art
appreciation must focus on the artist is seemingly taken for granted by many art
critics and art historians. A glance at the treatment of the point in some classic
discussions of the history of art is revealing. For example, E.H. Gombrich opens his
The Story of Art with the uncompromising claim that: “There really is no such thing
as Art. There are only artists.”
23
He elaborates by stressing that “what we call ‘works
of art’ are not the results of some mysterious activity, but objects made by human
beings for human beings”—objects designed such that “every one of their features is
the result of a decision by the artist.
24
Indeed, Gombrich characterizes the artist as
the ultimate designer, one who “must always be ‘fussy’ or rather fastidious to the
extreme,” obsessed with, as he puts it, “whether he has got it ‘right’.”
25
Gombrich
discusses what he calls “that modest little word ‘right’” at great lengths so that we
may “begin to understand what artists are really after.”
26
The theme that art appreciation is designer centered is similarly evident in the
introductory chapter of H.W.Janson’s classic textbook, History of Art, aptly titled
“The Artist and His Public.” In discussing originality in artistic creation, Janson
notes that appreciation of the ancient bronze, Thorn Puller (500–400 BC), is
destroyed by the knowledge that the piece is not the creation of a designing
intellect, but rather an ad hoc combination of preexisting parts. He claims that with
this knowledge “we no longer see it as a single, harmonious unit but as a somewhat
incongruous combination.”
27
When we cannot appreciate the bronze as a designed
whole, as the creation of a designer, its appreciation as a work of art is not possible.
Observations of the kind exemplified by Gombrich and Janson support the view
that at the center of appropriate appreciation of conventional works of art is the idea
that the object of appreciation is a designed object, an object created such that all its
significant qualities are, as Gombrich stresses, results of decisions by a designer. This
kind of appreciation, the essence of paradigmatic art appreciation, may be called
design appreciation.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 109
What are the significant features of design appreciation? The object must be
appreciated as a designed object—but what does this entail? Designed objects
involve three key entities: the initial design, the object embodying this design, and
the individual who embodies the design in the object. With the first, the design, the
central issue is what is being done or what the undertaking is or, as it is sometimes
put in artistic discussions, what problem is being solved or, as it is put, rather
unfortunately, in some literature in aesthetics, what the artist’s intentions are. With
the second, the object, what is important are its given properties, its strengths,
weaknesses, limits and potentials, what can and can not be done with it, what is a
use, and what an abuse, of it. With the third, the individual, what is most central
are his or her abilities and skills, his or her talents, as a designer, both at the
individual and the human level, and the ways these talents are used to embody the
design in the object.
Design appreciation involves awareness and understanding of the three entities
and their central properties. Especially important are awareness and understanding
of the interplay among them and of the ways they function, severally and jointly, to
achieve this interplay, for the interplay embodies the design and thereby determines
the nature of the object of appreciation. In this sense design appreciation is object
orientated: knowledge of the nature of the object dictates relevant acts of aspection
and guides the appreciative response. A part of this response involves making
judgments about the interplay, ones that assess the designed object in terms of the
talents of the designer and the undertaking set by the initial design—judgments
such as whether the object is a success or failure, good or bad, or, as it is often put,
whether it “works” or, as Gombrich puts it, whether it is “right.” Such judgments,
together with the mental and physical acts of aspection required for making them,
are at the core of design appreciation—and thus essential to paradigmatic art
appreciation.
Appreciating art: order appreciation
Design appreciation is essential to paradigmatic art appreciation, but, as noted in
the first section of this chapter, the latter must not be unthinkingly taken as the
model for all other forms of appreciation. Consideration of some unconventional
works of art and their nonparadigmatic yet appropriate appreciation is more helpful
in understanding the appreciation of nonart and that of nature in particular. As an
initial case in point, consider what is called action painting; a specific example is
Jackson Pollock’s One (#31) (1950). Its creation is described by art historian
Werner Haftmann as follows:
The canvas is placed on the ground. Casting off all intellectual control, the
painter moves over it with complete spontaneity; the liquid paint dripping
from his brush or from a tin with holes in it weaves the trace of his gestures into
a dense filigree.
28
110 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
Haftmann adds that a “work so produced is a direct record of the psyche” and that
the process of production came to be regarded by Pollock as “pure action, an
intricate trance-like choreography” the trace of which “registers the artist’s inner
life.”
29
What should be said about action painting concerning design, object, and artist?
First, there does not seem to be an initial design that becomes embodied in the
object. Haftmann says that such art is composed of and “by motor energies.”
30
However, even if an embodied design is lacking, the “motor energies” yet form a
pattern, which is a function of the interplay between the other two entities. Thus,
Janson says of Pollock’s works:
The actual shapes visible…are largely determined by the internal dynamics of
his material and his process: the viscosity of the paint, the speed and direction
of its impact upon the canvas, its interaction with other layers of pigment.
31
In this way the object and its properties achieve a greater significance than they have
in more conventional art. They are no longer constrained by an attempt to make
them embody a particular given design; rather they in part strongly determine a
resultant pattern.
The role of the artist is more perplexing. Haftmann characterizes Pollock as
moving with “complete spontaneity” and as “casting off all intellectual control.”
Pollock remarked in 1947: “When I am in my painting, I’m not aware of what I’m
doing.”
32
However, Pollock also noted in 1951, perhaps in response to the criticism
that he, to quote Janson, “is not sufficiently in control of his medium,” that: “When
I am painting I have a general notion as to what I am about. I can control the flow
of paint: there is no accident.”
33
Janson’s cowboy analogy is illuminating:
Pollock does not simply “let go” and leave the rest to chance. He is himself
the ultimate source of energy for these forces, and he “rides” them as a
cowboy might ride a wild horse, in a frenzy of psychophysical action.
34
Such an artist is not happily described as a designer, creating objects such that, as
Gombrich puts it, “every one of their features is the result of a decision.” Rather the
artist has only “a general notion” of what he or she is about and provides “the
ultimate source of energy” for the creation of the object, but not much more. The
role of the artist therefore becomes similar to that of the object and its given
properties: the artist is not the embodier of a design but rather only one force
among others, which working together determine a pattern.
However, although in one sense the artist is assimilated to his or her materials, he
or she also acquires another feature. Even if an individual is an artist, not every set
of drippings, spatterings, and dribblings he or she initiates “weaves the trace of his
gestures into a dense filigree.” Not every pattern is an appreciable pattern. Pollock’s
One, in the Museum of Modern Art, is subtitled #31 and as Janson says, following
up his cowboy metaphor, Pollock “does not always stay in the saddle.
35
What
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 111
happens when he falls out? Where are the paintings One (#’s 1–30)? It seems not
every pattern is selected as an object of appreciation. Perhaps those selected are only
those that seem to reveal “motor energies” or demonstrate “internal dynamics” of
materials and process or actually “weave the trace” of the artist’s gestures and “directly
record” his or her “psyche.” In short, appreciable patterns are those that reveal, or at
least can be seen as revealing, an order, those that are or can be seen as the marks of
the forces that have ordered the drips, spatters, and dribbles into whatever pattern
they form. Thus, although the artist loses his or her role as designer, he or she
acquires the role of selecting ordered and hence appreciable patterns.
Two additional cases, less conventional than action painting and rather more
what is called anti-art, further develop the themes introduced by Pollock’s work.
The first involves Dada experiments with “automatic” writing and drawing and
“chance” poetry and collage, especially as developed by Tristan Tzara and Hans
Arp.Haftmann reports:
Tzara would draw slips of paper with words inscribed on them from a hat,
and present the resulting combination of words as a poem; Arp allowed cut-
outs of free or geometric shapes to arrange themselves in a random order, then
pasted them on a surface, and presented the result as a picture. In the course of
such experiments, Arp also used automatic drawing, i.e., irrational,
spontaneously traced forms rising from the unconscious.
36
The key elements introduced in these experiments are spontaneity, randomness, and
chance. Moreover, unlike Pollock who somewhat unconvincingly claims that “there
is no accident,” these artists embrace random chance as a significant part of the
process. Janson claims: “The only law respected by the Dadaists was that of
chance.”
37
Thus, and this is especially clear concerning “automatic” works, the artist
is completely reduced to a force not unlike his or her materials—a force played upon
by chance. The focus is not on recording the artist’s “psychophysical action” but on
the spontaneous working out of the unconscious, the irrational. The artist’s role is
retained only insofar as there is after-the-fact alteration or, as with Pollock, selection
of certain results rather than others. For example, Janson reports that Arp
sometimes “cautiously adjusted” a “‘natural’ configuration.”
38
Moreover, some
selection played a part in the overall process; after all, not every one of Arp’s
experiments achieved the status of Collage with Squares Arranged According to the
Laws of Chance (1916–17), a work in the Museum of Modern Art.
The element of selection comes completely into its own only in another kind of
anti-art. Although evident in the Dadaist movement, it is most perfectly exemplified
in those works of Marcel Duchamp called found art. When Duchamp selected a
urinal, a bottle rack, or a typewriter cover for display as a found object, selection itself
became the heart of the process. Moreover, it is the fact of selection that is
significant, rather than exactly what is selected, for in many instances one object
does as well as another. In some surrealist experiments with found objects chance is
112 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
in fact the means of selection. For example, in the following work by Salvador Dali
the fact of selection is all that counts, for the object selected is left totally to chance:
Each of the experimenters is given an alarm-watch which will go off at a time
he must not know. Having this watch in his pocket, he carries on as usual and
at the very instant the alarm goes off he must note where he is and what most
strikingly impinges on his senses.
39
Dadaist and surrealist art, more so than Pollock’s, brings out the fact that all these
works have little to do with traditional artistic and aesthetic concerns. For example,
Dali claims the point of surrealist experiments is to realize “to what extent objective
perception depends upon imaginative representation.”
40
Haftmann reports that in
general such techniques are “methods for opening the way to the store of images
preserved in the unconscious. Their purpose is never to produce ‘art’; all of them are
conceived merely as instruments for exploring man’s potentialities.”
41
In a similar
way, Duchamp’s pieces, Dada experiments, and even Pollock’s paintings seem to
have little or no artistic or aesthetic basis. The urinal was not selected, in spite of what
George Dickie suggests, because of “its gleaming white surface.”
42
Duchamp says:
A point that I want very much to establish is that the choice of these Readymades
was never dictated by aesthetic delectation. The choice was based on a reaction of
visual indifference with a total absence of good or bad taste.”
43
Likewise, the Dada
experiments, as with those of surrealism, aim not at artistic or aesthetic qualities but
at “new psychological discoveries”—“a release of the forces of the subconscious.”
44
And Pollock’s paintings, as noted, are a means of producing “a direct record of the
psyche.”
45
The lack of regard for artistic and aesthetic concerns displayed by these works has
ramifications for their appreciation. The works are not designed nor even selected to
either solve conventional artistic problems or exemplify traditionally important
aesthetic qualities such as grace or delicacy. Yet the forces of creation or selection
operate such that these objects have appreciable patterns—patterns ordered by and
revelatory of these forces. But the creation or selection, and hence the ordering, is
typically accomplished by reference to some general ideas or beliefs having little to
do with aesthetics or with art in a traditional sense. Instead the ideas or beliefs
characteristically concern the way these works can reveal the nature and the order of
things such as the subconscious, the unconscious, the human mind, the human
condition. Thus, anything like a general criterion of aesthetic relevance is
completely irrelevant, and even paradigmatic design-focused art appreciation seems
quite out of place. Such appreciation is appropriate for artistically designed aesthetic
objects and gets little purchase on unconventional works of art and anti-art. Some
other form of appreciation is required.
The form of appreciation required may be called, in contrast to design
appreciation, order appreciation, for to the extent that these works have anything
comparable to a design, it is only an ordered pattern. The exact nature of such
appreciation can be elaborated by further pursuing the comparison with design
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 113
appreciation and the entities involved: the initial design, the object embodying the
design, and the individual who embodies the design. As noted, the first is absent;
there is no given design embodied in an object. However, for designed objects the
initial design indicates what is being done, what the undertaking is. Thus, if this
task is to be accomplished for an object with only an ordered pattern, it must be by
some other means. In fact at least something similar is accomplished by the ideas
and beliefs that play a role in the creation or selection of the object. Although they
are typically nonartistic and nonaesthetic, they yet indicate if not what is being
done, then at least what is going on in an ordered object. Thus, they help make the
ordered pattern visible and intelligible somewhat as the initial design does for the
designed object. Consequently, awareness and understanding of them and their
interplay with the other entities is significant in order appreciation, as is the
comparable knowledge of the initial design in design appreciation.
The remaining two entities, although not absent, are greatly altered. The object
embodying the design no longer embodies a design and the individual who
embodies the design is no longer a designer. The object is a thing shaped and
molded by a combination of forces: initially, its own given properties, its strengths,
weaknesses, limits and potentialities, but also the forces of random chance and of
the artist acting upon it—and acting with control only barely more significant than
that exercised by the object or by chance. Thus, as the third entity is only one force
among many, he or she is in large part assimilated to the other forces—a part of the
process and the materials rather than a master of them. But the third entity also has
another role: he or she selects from what these forces, including his or her own,
produce, and in selecting relies on some general ideas and beliefs in light of which
the object’s pattern seems visible and intelligible—can be perceived and understood
as ordered by the forces that produce it. To put it another way, he or she selects by
means of a general account, a story, or a theory that helps to make the object
appreciable.
The additional role for the third entity is a significant factor in order appreciation.
The new role is a traditional spectator role and therefore, as the artist’s original role
is assimilated to processes and materials, the new role is similarly assimilated to the
appreciator. This is not surprising, for works such as the Dada and surrealist pieces
are called experiments in part because any appreciator can conduct them; they are
experiments in appreciation. In summary, then, in order appreciation an individual
qua appreciator selects objects of appreciation from things around him or her. As
noted, he or she does so by reference to a general nonaesthetic and nonartistic
account that, by revealing the order imposed by the various forces—random and
otherwise—which produce the selected objects, makes them appreciable. As in
design appreciation, in order appreciation awareness and understanding of the
entities involved—the order, the forces that produce it, the story that illuminates it
—and the interplay among them is essential, but the focus is switched from a
designed object created by an artist to an ordered object selected by an appreciator.
114 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
Appreciating nature: design appreciation
Frequently the appreciation of nature is assimilated to the appreciation of art. Such
an assimilation is both a theoretical mistake and an appreciative pity. On the
theoretical level, it typically involves misunderstanding not only appreciation but
also one or both of art and nature. On the appreciative level, it can result in either
failing to appreciate nature at all or appreciating it in an inappropriate manner—
relying on the wrong information, engaging in the wrong acts of aspection, and
having the wrong responses. As noted in Chapter 4, Ronald Hepburn puts this point
concisely: If our “aesthetic education” instills in us “the attitudes, the tactics of
approach, the expectations proper to the appreciation of art works only,” we “either
pay very little aesthetic heed to natural objects or else heed them in the wrong
way.”
46
The theoretical mistake of assimilating nature appreciation and art appreciation,
as with some other mistakes noted previously, can be traced in part to the
disinterestedness tradition. However, at times in its history, especially in its
beginnings, the tradition assimilated the appreciation of art to that of nature rather
than the other way around. Nonetheless, whichever way it goes the assimilation is a
mistake. When generated by disinterestedness, the mistake has the same roots as
that of ignoring the designed nature of art, which was noted in the second section of
this chapter. When the notion of disinterestedness is treated such that the object of
appreciation is isolated and divorced from its interrelationships, and its appreciation
is constrained by the general criterion of aesthetic relevance, the stage is set for the
assimilation. According to this construal of disinterestedness, both works of art and
natural objects are in their appreciation more or less severed from their natures and
their histories. Thus, both kinds of objects may be appreciated in the same way: as
pure aesthetic objects. The result is one form of appreciation—aesthetic appreciation
—that appropriately applies to any and all kinds of things. Art appreciation and
nature appreciation collapse into one.
As argued in the first section of this chapter, however, this construal of
disinterestedness is a mishandling of the concept. With it, not only do all forms of
appreciation collapse into one, also, as noted, all seemingly collapse into the blank,
cow-like stare. Thus, the key to avoiding this path to the assimilation of art and
nature appreciation is the same as that to avoiding the cow-like stare: the key is the
object-orientated nature of appreciation. This understanding of appreciation, as it
facilitates the recognition of the designer-centered nature of paradigmatic art
appreciation, also both closes down this route to the assimilation and points toward
the proper understanding of nature appreciation. However, the coast is not yet
clear. Even with object-orientated appreciation and without mishandling
disinterestedness, there are yet means to assimilate art and nature appreciation.
Indeed, the temptation to assimilate them is seemingly so strong that one suspects
that the desire for assimilation is in fact the cause and mistakes such as mishandling
disinterestedness only an effect.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 115
A second path to the assimilation of art appreciation and nature appreciation
involves a tradition even more venerable than that of disinterestedness. This route
recognizes the object-orientated nature of appreciation and thus follows the lead of
the object. It also recognizes paradigmatic art appreciation as design focused. Thus,
it takes design appreciation as basic and assimilates all other appreciation, including
the aesthetic appreciation of nature, to it. All that is required to accomplish this
assimilation is construing nature as the creation of a designer. And if nature is to be
so construed, most cultural traditions have ample resources to support the
construal. In the West many forms of theism seem adequate for the purpose and can
thereby play a role in the assimilation of nature appreciation to art appreciation. As
noted in Chapter 6, Nelson Potter nicely puts the point, remarking that on the
theist view any account of the appreciation of art:
…would be directly applicable to Nature, where God is the artist… [since]…
The theist sees the world as throughout the product of God’s design and
plan… For such a theist it may seem that there is no difference between art-
appreciation and nature appreciation, since both are the products of intentional
design.
47
However, this method of assimilating art appreciation and nature appreciation also
has difficulties. Potter, for example, claims it construes “God in a naive and
excessively anthropomorphic fashion.”
48
And consequently it fails “to realize that
God is so different from man that even as we regard Nature as the product of God’s
handiwork,” we become “aware that the model of a human artist and his intentions
and his artwork is inadequate to understand our appreciation of beauty in nature.”
49
He therefore opts to “bid farewell to those theists who think that conceiving of God
as a divine Philip Johnson is an adequate model for the appreciation of beauty in
nature.”
50
Potter’s conclusion is probably correct. His conclusion seemingly follows
not only from his own concerns, but also from any more general lack of confidence
in the theist world view. In any case it is a conclusion that has wide acceptance.
However, accepting the conclusion that nature is not usefully conceptualized as
the creation of a designer leaves us with a problem concerning its appreciation—a
problem that in the West has become increasingly acute since the end of the
nineteenth century. In an insightful discussion of Ruskin’s agonizing confrontation
with it, Peter Fuller succinctly summarizes the issue: “Once the illusion that the
world was the handiwork of God had been jettisoned, then the whole base of
aesthetics needed to be re-examined.”
51
Thus, the role of theism in the attempt to
assimilate nature appreciation to art appreciation, together with what is perhaps the
ultimate failure of this attempt, brings into sharp focus what may well be the central
theoretical problem concerning the appreciation of nature: the problem of how to
understand such appreciation given that paradigmatic art appreciation is analyzed as
design appreciation, and yet nature is not to be construed as the creation of a
designer.
116 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
This problem about nature appreciation is perplexing enough that it leads to
radical solutions. One such solution is the nonaesthetic view of nature appreciation,
introduced in Chapter 1. A version of this view is what Don Mannison calls the
“Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic.” Mannison contends that “Nature cannot be the
object of aesthetic appreciation” by arguing that “only human artifacts can be
objects of aesthetic judgement,” for “‘artistry’ is an essential component of an
aesthetic judgement”—“The conceptual structure of an aesthetic judgement.. .includes
a reference to a creator; i.e. an artist.”
52
As noted in Chapter 6, a similar conclusion
is drawn by Robert Elliot, who argues that “an apparently integral part of aesthetic
evaluation depends on viewing the aesthetic object as an intentional object, as an
artifact, as something that is shaped by the purposes and designs of its author” and
that this is not possible with nature for “Nature is not a work of art.”
53
As Elliot
brings out, a concern of the Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic is that nature does not
seem open to evaluative aesthetic judgments such as whether it is good or bad, a
success or failure. This concern is legitimate, but drawing from it the conclusion that
nature cannot be an object of aesthetic appreciation is without doubt an
overreaction, not unlike Dickie’s abandoning of the concept of the aesthetic. But
even were it not, the conclusion would still be unacceptable. It offends against the
truism noted in the first section of this chapter as well as in previous chapters: that
aesthetic appreciation is applicable to any object of awareness whatever. Moreover,
as argued in Chapter 6, it is not established by the arguments offered in its
defense.
54
What is important here, however, is seeing how the conclusion that nature
cannot be an object of aesthetic appreciation stems in part from not recognizing the
object-orientated nature of appreciation. As noted in the first section of this chapter,
this concept, by ridding itself of anything like the general criterion of aesthetic
relevance, allows for, indeed requires, different kinds of aesthetic appreciation as a
function of the nature of the object of appreciation. Thus, all appreciation need not
and should not be assimilated to the model of paradigmatic, design-centered art
appreciation. In short, the position that nature appreciation cannot be aesthetic
stems from a failure to recognize that there are legitimate alternatives to design
appreciation. This fact is significant: if that position is a possible solution to the
problem of how to understand nature appreciation when paradigmatic art
appreciation is design focused and nature is not designed, then recognizing that
there are alternatives to design appreciation makes evident a more plausible
solution. Such a solution lies not in denying that the appreciation of nature can be
aesthetic but rather in considering the alternatives to design appreciation. Thus,
although in itself wrongheaded, the attempt to abandon the aesthetic appreciation
of nature points towards a fruitful line of thought.
That nature appreciation is to be understood in light of alternatives to design
appreciation is also suggested, ironically enough, by one aspect of the theist view.
That view assimilates nature appreciation to art appreciation only by construing
nature such that it fits the model of design appreciation. In this way the theist view
brings out the fact that with object-orientated appreciation the way we construe the
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 117
object of appreciation—the general account or the story we accept about it
contributes to determining the nature of its appropriate appreciation. With
paradigmatic works of art this fact is obscured, for there is little dispute and
therefore there are no alternative stories about them: no one doubts that they are
creations of designers and typically there is considerable agreement about the details
of their histories. However, when there is less clarity and agreement, as with nature,
then alternative stories abound and form part of the basis for appreciation. Thus,
with nature, the story accepted about it, the ideas and beliefs we have about it, are
pivotal factors in its appreciation. In this way nature is similar to those works of art
and anti-art for which the appropriate appreciation is, as noted in the third section
of this chapter, order appreciation. Moreover, order appreciation is an alternative to
design appreciation such as is required to solve the problem of how to understand
the appreciation of nature without forcing it into the model of design appreciation.
Appreciating nature: order appreciation
The idea of order appreciation as a model for the appreciation of nature is worth
exploration. It is suggested by more than just that our appreciation of nature, like that
of the works of art and anti-art for which order appreciation is appropriate, is
shaped by the stories we tell about it. It is also suggested by other similarities and
relationships between such works of art and anti-art and the objects of nature. There
is, for instance, the fact that the works called found objects need not be limited to
urinals, bottle racks, or typewriter covers, but can be themselves natural objects, as
Haftmann points out, “a root, a mussel, a stone.
55
Likewise, consider the fact that a
work such as Dalis surrealist experiment is not made less significant if the
“alarmwatch” goes off when the “experimenter” is, for example, in a forest rather
than in his or her bathroom. If order appreciation is the form of appreciation
relevant to such works, it is seemingly as relevant in the forest as it is in the
bathroom.
Especially revealing of the relevance of order appreciation to the appreciation of
nature are the claims of the artists who initiated these works of art and antiart. For
example, it is said such art “urges man to identify himself with nature” and is itself
comparable to the objects of nature.
56
Arp, for instance, claims that: “These
paintings, sculptures, objects should remain anonymous and form a part of nature’s
great workshop as leaves do, and clouds, animals, and men. Yes, man must once
again become a part of nature.
57
Of automatic poetry, in particular, Arp says:
Automatic poetry comes straight out of the poet’s bowels or out of any other
of his organs that has accumulated reserves… He crows, swears, moans,
stammers, yodels, according to his mood… Neither the Postillon of
Longjumiau, nor the Alexandrian, nor grammar, nor aesthetics, nor Buddha,
nor the Sixth Commandment are able to constrict him. [Nor, we might add,
the general criterion of aesthetic relevance.] His poems are like nature; they
118 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
stink, laugh, and rhyme like nature. Foolishness, or at least what men call
foolishness, is as precious to him as a sublime piece of rhetoric. For in nature
a broken twig is equal in beauty and importance to the clouds and the stars.
58
On the assumption that order appreciation provides the correct model for the
appreciation of nature, such appreciation has the following general form: An
individual qua appreciator selects objects of appreciation from the things around
him or her and focuses on the order imposed on these objects by the various forces,
random and otherwise, that produce them. Moreover, the objects are selected in
part by reference to a general nonaesthetic and nonartistic story that helps make
them appreciable by making this order visible and intelligible. Awareness and
understanding of the key entities—the order, the forces that produce it, and the
account that illuminates it—and of the interplay among them dictate relevant acts of
aspection and guide the appreciative response.
However, if this description indicates the general form of nature appreciation as
modeled on order appreciation, it is yet only part of the complete understanding of
such appreciation. As the Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic reminds us in denying that
nature appreciation is aesthetic: “Nature is not a work of art.” Consequently, even
though modeled on order appreciation, nature appreciation differs in certain
substantive ways from the appreciation of those works of art and anti-art for which
order appreciation is also appropriate. Following the lead of the object, as demanded
by the object-orientated nature of appreciation, helps bring out these differences.
As noted at the close of the preceding section of this chapter, the theist view that
nature appreciation, like paradigmatic art appreciation, is design focused ironically
suggests the alternative view that nature appreciation involves order appreciation.
This is because the theist view brings out clearly the role played in nature
appreciation by our story of it. In this way it also makes clear that, with order
appreciation, to follow the lead of an object is to follow the lead of our story about
it. And even if we, like Potter, reject the theist view of nature as designed, we are yet
left with a variety of stories the lead of which we could follow. In one sense any of
these stories can do the job required by order appreciation. Relevant stories derive
from various religious and folk traditions, explaining nature, if not as created and
designed by, as nonetheless involving in some way the actions of, for example, one
all-powerful god, many lesser gods, entities such as spirits, demons, fairies, or
heroes, or whatever. However, in part because such accounts lose much of their
appeal without the element of design and in part because of the powerful appeal of
an alternative story, these stories, with the possible exception of that of an all-
powerful god, do not, I think, play a crucial role in our aesthetic appreciation of
nature. On the contrary, as argued in the preceding three chapters of this volume, what
plays this role, and has increasingly done so in the West since the seventeenth
century, is the alternative account given by natural science.
59
In light of the object-orientated nature of appreciation, the significance of the
story provided by natural science to our aesthetic appreciation of nature can be
further explained and justified. On the one hand, that science, natural or otherwise,
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 119
is appropriate for nature appreciation gathers plausibility in that, as noted in the
first section of this chapter, object-orientated appreciation is objective: it focuses on
an object as what it is and as having the properties it has. And, of course, science is
the paradigm of that which reveals objects for what they are and with the properties
they have. Thus, science not only presents itself as the source of objective truth, it
brands alternative accounts as subjective falsehood and therefore, in accord with
objective appreciation, as irrelevant to aesthetic appreciation. In this way the
significance of science in the aesthetic appreciation of nature is in part a legacy of
the notion of disinterestedness. On the other hand, that the specific kind of science
relevant to nature appreciation is natural science follows rather obviously from
object-orientated appreciation. This marks one important difference between the
order appreciation of nature and that of works of art and anti-art. For the latter the
relevant stories, as noted in the third section of this chapter, are typically
metaphysical, mystical, or psychological. However, it is no surprise that humanistic
stories and the human sciences are relevant to the appreciation of artifacts, while the
natural sciences are relevant to the appreciation of nature. What else should
following the lead of the object indicate?
The content of nature appreciation can now be added to its form. Its form, as
noted, centers on the entities significant to order appreciation: order, the forces that
produce it, and the account that illuminates it. Its content is as follows. First, the
relevant order is that typically called the natural order. Second, since there is no
artist, not even one assimilated to processes and materials, the relevant forces are the
forces of nature: the geological, biological, and meteorological forces that produce
the natural order by shaping not only the planet but everything that inhabits it.
Although these forces differ from many that shape works of art, awareness and
understanding of them is vital in nature appreciation, as is knowledge of, for
example, Pollock’s role in appreciating his action painting or the role of chance in
appreciating a Dada experiment. Third, the relevant account that makes the natural
order visible and intelligible is, as noted, the story given by natural science—
astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology, genetics, meteorology, geology as well as the
particular explanatory theories within these sciences. For example, awareness and
understanding of evolutionary theory is relevant to appreciating the natural order as
revealed in flora and fauna; without such knowledge the biosphere may strike us as
chaotic.
The remaining significant factor in order appreciation is the role of selection by an
individual qua appreciator. And indeed in nature appreciation the appreciator must
select particular objects of appreciation from, as Arp says, “nature’s great workshop.”
However, here again there is a significant difference from the appreciation of works
of art and anti-art. Although selection plays a key role in the order appreciation of
these artistic endeavors, it seemingly has a somewhat less significant role in nature
appreciation. Unlike the situation concerning such works, all of nature necessarily
reveals the natural order. Although it may be easier to perceive and understand in
some cases than in others, it is yet present in every case and can be appreciated once
our awareness and understanding of the forces that produce it and the story that
120 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
illuminates it are adequately developed. In this sense all nature is equally appreciable
and therefore selection among all that the natural world offers is not of much
ultimate importance. As Arp observes, “in nature a broken twig is equal in beauty
and importance to the clouds and the stars.”
If all nature “is equal in beauty and importance,” this is a significant difference
not simply between nature appreciation and the order appreciation of some works
of art and anti-art, but between nature appreciation and art appreciation in general.
However, it is in part explained by design appreciation’s inappropriateness for
nature. An important aspect of design appreciation is judging the object in terms of
the talents of the designer and of the undertaking that is set by the initial design—
assessing, as noted in the second section of this chapter, whether it is good or bad, a
success or failure, or, as Gombrich puts it, whether it is “right.” In short, the fact of
a designer and of an initial design makes both design appreciation appropriate for
conventional works of art and such judgments a key aspect of their appreciation.
Likewise, the absence of these entities makes design appreciation not appropriate for
nature and these kinds of judgments not an aspect of its appreciation. Natural
objects are not such that their appreciation involves judging whether they are
“right” in Gombrich’s sense; in this sense they are all more or less equally right. Thus,
to the extent that they are appreciable at all, all are more or less equally appreciable
—“equal in beauty and importance.” As noted in the preceding section of this
chapter, that judgments of this kind do not apply to nature is part of the argument
of those who support the Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic. It is now clear that what
follows from this is almost the opposite of their conclusion that nature cannot be an
object of aesthetic appreciation.
The appropriateness of order appreciation to nature, just as the inappropriateness
of design appreciation, is also useful in further explaining the issue investigated in
Chapter 6: the seeming fact that natural objects, unlike works of art, are more or
less equally appreciable. In order appreciation, instead of judging a work a success or
failure in light of a design and a designer, there is only appreciating an object as
ordered in light of a story. And although such stories may differ, each (indeed this is
much of the point of constructing them) illuminates nature as ordered—either by
making its order visible and intelligible or by imposing an order on it. Thus,
although such stories are in one sense nonaesthetic, in another sense they are
exceedingly aesthetic. They illuminate nature as ordered and in doing so give it
meaning, significance, and beauty—qualities that those who create the stories find
aesthetically appealing. Thus, unlike design appreciation that focuses on aesthetic
qualities that result from embodying an initial design in an object, order
appreciation focuses on aesthetic qualities that result from applying an after-the-fact
story to a pre-existent object. Moreover, the aesthetic qualities resulting from
ordering nature in one way or another figure in the general attractiveness of one
story as opposed to another. Thus, over the long run, stories develop so as to
provide as much and as universal aesthetic appeal as is possible. In this way the
stories that play a role in the order appreciation of nature work toward making
natural objects all seem equally aesthetically appealing.
60
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 121
Conclusion
In conclusion, some somewhat more vague and general contrasts between
appreciating art and appreciating nature can also be illuminated by reference to
differences between design and order appreciation. What lies behind a designed
object is a designer and therefore in design appreciation part of our appreciative
response is directed toward another intellect not unlike our own. The artist and
design are thus something toward which we can feel the empathy and the closeness
typical of our relationships with other human beings. Yet there is a distance, for it is
an other, a different human being, toward which our feelings are directed. By
contrast, all that lies behind an ordered object is a story, the account that
illuminates the order. Thus, in order appreciation part of our appreciative response
is directed towards whatever is in our story. And whether that be an all-powerful
god, a folklore of demons and fairies, or a world of natural forces, it is something
that is by its nature distinct from and beyond humankind, something essentially
alien to us. Our appreciative response is to a mystery we will seemingly never fully
comprehend. Nonetheless it is our story—our god, our folklore, our science—in
light of which we respond; therefore there is, after all, a closeness. Perhaps not the
same closeness that is typical of our relationships with other human beings, but
maybe something more like that typical of our relationships with our pets—or at
least our pet theories.
Given these differences between design and order appreciation, appreciating art
and appreciating nature should also exemplify different kinds of ambivalences. On
the one hand, in appreciating art we are aware that the work is a human creation, an
artifact, and therefore ultimately open to our appreciation and to our understanding,
our judgment, our mastery. However, we must also be aware that even if we master
the work completely, it will yet not be our own, but someone else’s creation that we
master. On the other hand, in appreciating nature we are aware that the object is
alien, a mystery, and therefore ultimately beyond our appreciation and beyond our
understanding, our judgment, our mastery. However, we may also be aware that
insofar as we manage to achieve some mastery of it, it is by means of our own
beliefs, our own story, our own creation that we do so. Thus, perhaps nature is
easiest to appreciate when our account of it is simplistic anthropomorphic folklore:
a story of almost human gods or godlike human heroes—a story not unlike those of
so-called primitive peoples who are said to feel exceptionally close to nature. In light
of such folklore, nature should seem especially approachable, for it is illuminated
not only by our own story but in terms of beings much like ourselves. Likewise,
perhaps works of art are easiest to appreciate when they are our own creations.
However, for most of us to appreciate art is to confront the quintessentially human
by way of another, while to appreciate nature is to confront either an almighty god
or blind natural forces by ourselves. In neither confrontation is appreciation
necessarily easy, yet in each can be found aesthetic experiences of richness and
power. However, it is no surprise if typically only the confrontations with nature are
marked by overwhelming wonder and awe.
61
122 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
Notes
1 Stolnitz’s version of the position is in Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
Criticism, A Critical Introduction, Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 1960. Dickie’s initial
and best known version of his attack is George Dickie,The Myth of the Aesthetic
Attitude,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 1964, vol. 1, pp. 56–65.
2 Stolnitz, op. cit., p. 35.
3 Ibid., p. 42.
4 Ibid., p. 39.
5 Ibid., p. 33.
6 Ibid., pp. 37–8.
7 Ibid., p. 37.
8 Ibid., p. 37. Stolnitz is quoting Kate Hevner, “The Aesthetic Experience, A
Psychological Description,” Psychological Review, 1937, vol. 44, p. 249.
9 Dickie, op. cit., p. 61. For a fuller discussion of the issue of aesthetic relevance, see
“Between Nature and Art” (in this volume, Chapter 8) and “Landscape and
Literature” (in this volume, Chapter 14).
10 Stolnitz, op. cit., p. 36.
11 Ibid., p. 52.
12 Ibid., p. 53. Stolnitz puts the problem of aesthetic relevance as follows: “Is it ever
‘relevant’ to the aesthetic experience to have thoughts or images or bits of knowledge
which are not present within the object itself? If these are ever relevant, under what
conditions are they so?”
13 Ibid., p. 54.
14 George Dickie, Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis, Ithaca, Cornell
University Press, 1974, p. 40. In a similar fashion in “The Myth of the Aesthetic
Attitude,” op. cit., Dickie states that “an underlying aim of this essay is to suggest the
vacuousness of the term ‘aesthetic’” (p. 64).
15 Stolnitz, op. cit., p. 58. Stolnitz’s brief discussion on pages 57–60 of the relevance of
knowledge to appreciation is excellent.
16 I have elsewhere discussed in detail how Ziff’s account of aesthetic appreciation
seemingly avoids the major difficulties of both the disinterestedness tradition and
alternative “conceptual” approaches. See “Critical Notice of Ziff, Antiaesthetics, An
Appreciation of the Cow with the Subtile Nose,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1987,
vol. 17, pp. 919–34.
17 Paul Ziff, “Reasons in Art Criticism,” Philosophical Turnings: Essays in Conceptual
Appreciation, Ithaca, Cornell University Press, 1966, p. 71.
18 Paul Ziff, “Anything Viewed,” Antiaesthetics, An Appreciation of the Cow with the Subtile
Nose, Dordrecht, Reidel, 1984, p. 136.
19 Ibid., p. 135. I have taken the liberty of adding commas to this quote. It is worth
noting that the object-orientated nature of appreciation suggested by Ziff also becomes
more explicit in Stolnitz in his later writings. In his insightful 1978 Presidential
Address to The American Society for Aesthetics he characterizes disinterestedness as
involving “scrupulous regard for the qualitative individuality of the object” and, just as
Ziff does, speaks of the object itself as making “demands”—“demands that must be
met if the thing is to be savored for what it uniquely is.” (p. 411) See Jerome Stolnitz,
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 123
“The Artistic and the Aesthetic ‘in Interesting Times,’” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 1979, vol. 37, pp. 401–13.
20 The objective residue of the notion of disinterestedness comes out clearly in
Bullough’s well-known discussion in which he notes that his version of
disinterestedness, “psychical distance,” involves in part “looking at it [the object of
appreciation] ‘objectively,’ as it has often been called, by permitting only such reactions
on our part as emphasize the ‘objective’ features of the experience.” See Edward
Bullough, “‘Psychical Distance’ as a Factor in Art and an Aesthetic Principle,” British
Journal of Psychology, 1912, vol. 5, reprinted in W.E.Kennick, (ed.) Art and Philosophy:
Readings in Aesthetics, New York, St Martin’s Press, 1964, p. 535.
21 Joseph Butler, Five Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel [1726], Indianapolis, Hackett
Publishing Company, 1983, p. 20.
22 In the classic anti-intentionalist piece, for example, Wimsatt’s and Beardsley’s
forbidden “external evidence” is more than simply artist’s intentions; it is also
knowledge, “revelations” as they say, about the artist. See W.K.Wimsatt, Jr. and
Monroe C.Beardsley, “The Intentional Fallacy,” Sewanee Review, 1946, vol. 54, pp.
468–88.
23 E.H.Gombrich, The Story of Art, London, Phaidon, 1950, p. 5.
24 Ibid., pp. 12–13.
25 Ibid., p. 14.
26 Ibid., p. 14.
27 H.W.Janson, History of Art: A Survey of the Major Visual Arts from the Dawn of History
to the Present Day, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice-Hall, 1969, p. 13.
28 Werner Haftmann, Painting in the Twentieth Century: An Analysis of the Artists and
their Work, New York, Praeger, 1965, p. 348.
29 Ibid., p. 348.
30 Ibid., p. 349.
31 Janson, op. cit., p. 540.
32 Jackson Pollock, “Three Statements, 1944–1951,” in Herschel B.Chipp (ed.) Theories
of Modern Art: A Sourcebook by Artists and Critics, Berkeley, University of California
Press, 1968, p. 548.
33 Janson, op. cit., p. 540; Pollock, op. cit., p. 548.
34 Janson, op. cit., p. 540.
35 Ibid., p. 540
36 Haftmann, op. cit., p. 183.
37 Janson, op. cit., p. 534.
38 Ibid., p. 534.
39 Salvador Dali, “The Object Revealed in Surrealist Experiment,” in Chipp, op. cit., p.
423.
40 Ibid., p. 423.
41 Haftmann, op. cit., p. 190.
42 George Dickie, “A Response to Cohen, The Actuality of Art,” in George Dickie and
R.J.Sclafani (eds) Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology, New York, St. Martin’s Press, 1977,
p. 199.
43 Marcel Duchamp, quoted in Anne dHarnoncourt and Kynaston McShine (eds)
Marcel Duchamp, New York, Museum of Modern Art, 1973, p. 89. The quote is given
in Timothy Binkley, “Piece, Contra Aesthetics,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
124 APPRECIATING ART AND APPRECIATING NATURE
1977, vol. 35, p. 275. Binkley’s piece is very useful concerning what he calls “Art
Outside Aesthetics.”
44 Haftmann, op. cit., p. 182–3
45 Ibid., p. 348.
46 R.W.Hepburn, “Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” in H.Osborne (ed.) Aesthetics and
the Modern World, London, Thames and Hudson, 1968, p. 53. I discuss the
unfortunate consequences of appreciating nature in terms of some particular artistic
models in “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–75 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4).
47 Nelson Potter, “Aesthetic Value in Nature and In the Arts,” in Hugh Curtler (ed.)
What is Art?, New York, Haven, 1983, pp. 142–3.
48 Ibid., p. 143.
49 Ibid., pp. 143–4.
50 Ibid., p. 144.
51 Peter Fuller, “The Geography of Mother Nature,” in D.Cosgrove and S.Daniels (eds)
The Iconography of Landscape: Essays on the Symbolic Representation, Design and Use of
Past Environments, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 25.
52 Don Mannison, “A Prolegomenon to a Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic,” in Don
Mannison, Michael McRobbie, and Richard Routley (eds) Environmental Philosophy,
Canberra, Australian National University, 1980, pp. 216, 212–13.
53 Robert Elliot, “Faking Nature,” Inquiry, 1982, vol. 25, pp. 81–93. This quote is from
p. 90.
54 I consider these arguments in detail in “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,” Environmental
Ethics, 1984, vol. 6, pp. 5–34 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6).
55 Haftmann, op. cit., p. 191.
56 Hans Arp, “Abstract Art, Concrete Art” in Chipp, op. cit., p. 391.
57 Ibid., p. 390.
58 Ibid., p. 391.
59 I argue for the importance of scientific knowledge to the aesthetic appreciation of nature
in “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” op. cit. (reproduced in this volume,
Chapter 4), “Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Objectivity,” Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism, 1981, vol. 40, pp. 15–27 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 5),
“Nature and Positive Aesthetics,” op. cit., (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6), and
“Saito on the Correct Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” Journal of Aesthetic Education,
1986, vol. 20, pp. 85–93.
60 I develop the line of thought of this paragraph more fully in “Nature and Positive
Aesthetics,” op. cit. (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6) and in “Critical Notice of
Rolston, Philosophy Gone Wild,” Environmental Ethics, 1986, vol. 8, pp. 163–77.
61 A segment of this chapter was presented at a symposium on “Artistic and Natural
Beauty” at the American Philosophical Association Meeting, Portland, Oregon, March,
1988. I thank those present for useful comments.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 125
126
Part II
LANDSCAPES, ART, AND
ARCHITECTURE
128
8
BETWEEN NATURE AND ART
The question of aesthetic relevance
In the second part of this volume, I turn from the aesthetics of nature to a set of
appreciative issues that arise, as it were, between nature and art. I address questions
about the appreciation of landscapes, such as those of agriculture, which exist in the
space between these two realms; I consider aesthetic problems that are generated by
intimate relationships between nature and art, as in the cases of gardens and
environmental works of art; and I reflect on appreciative issues that are posed by art
forms, such as architecture, that fall near the boundary of art.
One general way to frame this diverse set of issues is by reference to the question
introduced in Chapter 7: the question of aesthetic relevance. I thus develop this
question more fully in this chapter, such that it may stand as a backdrop to the
issues taken up in the next five chapters. I return to it explicitly only in the final
chapter of the volume. The question itself constitutes an ideal backdrop for what
follows in that it poses one of the most central and significant issues in aesthetics. It
is significant from both the theoretical and the applied point of view. Its theoretical
significance stems from the fact that answers to the question frequently rest upon
philosophical positions of the most fundamental kind. Its significance for applied
aesthetics derives from the fact that answers to the question dictate the ways and
means of our actual appreciative practice. Thus the question stands as a bridge
between what we think and what we do, between our aesthetics and our
appreciation.
As indicated in the preceding chapter, the question is that of what is relevant to
the appropriate aesthetic appreciation of any particular object of such appreciation.
But since aesthetic appreciation by its nature focuses on what an object presents to
the senses, the question is more precisely that of what, if anything, of that which an
object does not present to the senses is relevant to its appropriate appreciation. Any
appreciator confronts a potential object of appreciation with a head full of thoughts,
images, associations, and bits of information. The question of aesthetic relevance is
the question of what, if any, of all this “outside information” is relevant to the
appreciator’s appropriate appreciation.
1
Traditional aesthetics offers a rather conservative answer to the question of
aesthetic relevance: little outside of what is presented to the senses is taken to be
relevant. As elaborated in Chapter 2, this lean answer rests upon two of the most
fundamental philosophical positions in modern aesthetics: the doctrines of
disinterestedness and formalism. The former doctrine, as noted in Chapter 7,
typically involves a special attitude or state of mind in virtue of which the
appreciator is disinterested in or distanced from the object of appreciation. This
attitude or state thus gives a standard of aesthetic relevance that characteristically
mandates a mode of appreciation in which both the appreciator and the object are
isolated and separated from the world at large. Thereby, appropriate aesthetic
appreciation is severed from anything that is not present in the object itself, and
information external to the object is deemed irrelevant to such appreciation.
2
The second theoretical underpinning of the conservative answer to the question of
aesthetic relevance is formalism. As indicated in Chapters 2 and 3, formalism
provides an essentialist analysis of art in terms of formal relationships of shapes,
lines, and colors, which are typically claimed to evoke a special emotion in the
appreciator. Moreover, formalism sharply distinguishes this essential formal
dimension of art from everything else. Art and its appreciation is confined to a
world of its own, with emotions of its own, and unrelated to the world at large. The
appreciator is to bring to the object of appreciation nothing from this outside
world. Appropriate aesthetic appreciation is again severed from anything that is not
present in the object itself, and information external to the object is again deemed
irrelevant to such appreciation.
3
Thus supported by essentialistic formalism and the doctrine of disinterestedness,
the conservative answer to the question of aesthetic relevance has severe and austere
consequences for aesthetic appreciation. Thoughts, images, associations or
information not presented to the senses by the object itself are condemned as
irrelevant and even harmful, best purged from our minds if we are to appropriately
appreciate an object for what it really is. This approach, however, has not continued
unchallenged into the present, for the history of analytic aesthetics is in part a
history of the assault on formalism and disinterestedness as well as on essentialism; as
these philosophical positions have fallen from favor, the conservative answer to the
question of aesthetic relevance has followed suit. Not only formalism and
disinterestedness, but also closely related dogmas such as aestheticism, anti-
intentionalism, and the autonomy of art have all been thoroughly critiqued and, in
many quarters, rejected.
The upshot of this critique of the foundations of the conservative approach to the
question of aesthetic relevance is that answers have become increasingly liberal.
Thus, for example, in a recent article, Marcia Eaton offers the following test for
aesthetic relevance: “A statement (or gesture) is aesthetically relevant if and only if it
draws attention (perception, reflection) to an aesthetic property.”
4
She elaborates
saying that “whatever directs attention to intrinsic features aesthetically valued is
aesthetically relevant” and, agreeing with Richard Wollheim, claims this may be
“information of any sort whatsoever.”
5
In short, if it works for the appreciator, it’s
130 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
relevant. Moreover, there are even more extreme answers to the question of aesthetic
relevance. Following in the wake of analytic aesthetics’ assault on essentialism,
formalism, and disinterestedness, more recent philosophical movements such as
feminist aesthetics and postmodernism so completely reject these doctrines that they
leave no basis for anything but the most radical answers to the question of aesthetic
relevance. Thus we now have what I call, rather casually and indifferently, a
postmodern approach to aesthetic relevance, which seemingly holds that anything
and everything that any appreciator happens to bring to an object is relevant to its
aesthetic appreciation, for in some sense or other the object is created anew in light
of that which the appreciator contributes to it.
Objects of appreciation and aesthetic necessity
Does calling into question formalism and disinterestedness inevitably lead to a
postmodern approach to aesthetic relevance? Is there no stable middle ground
between the extreme purism required by the former doctrines and the excessive
liberalism offered by the latter approach? Must we say that either next to nothing
or, alternatively, almost anything is relevant to our appropriate aesthetic
appreciation of any object?
Perhaps there is a stable middle ground between these two extremes. However,
establishing such an alternative requires first identifying and abandoning an
assumption common not only to formalism and the doctrine of disinterestedness,
but also to both their analytic and their postmodern detractors. What all these views
have in common is a focus on the subject of appreciation, the appreciator, rather
than on the object of appreciation. This is in part because they all, even the latest
postmodern protestations, stand surprisingly firmly in an aesthetic tradition that
stretches back to Kant and beyond. They retain a commitment rooted in the
subjectification of aesthetic experience that was so successfully accomplished by the
British empiricist aestheticians of the eighteenth century. The commitment is clear
concerning disinterestedness, which is itself a special mental state of the appreciator,
and formalism, which ties form to a special emotion of the appreciator. But even a
refined and late-in-the-day analytic approach such as Eaton’s is focused almost
exclusively on achieving the right attentional state in the appreciator, however that
may be accomplished. And the postmodern approach seemingly simply turns the
whole business over to the appreciator and whatever state he or she happens to be in.
But why should the question of aesthetic relevance be addressed by focusing on
the states of the appreciator? Isn’t it rather odd to think, along with Eaton and
Wollheim, for example, that whatever—“information of any sort whatsoever”—
happens to put an appreciator of any particular object in a state such that he or she
can appreciate that object is thereby relevant to the appreciation of the particular
object in question? It follows from this view that if we could find one single bit of
information, perhaps a Zen insight, or even one simple drug, perhaps a mild
hallucinogenic, that would put appreciators in a state to aesthetically appreciation
anything whatsoever, then that bit of information, or drug, or whatever would be
BETWEEN NATURE AND ART 131
aesthetically relevant to everything whatsoever. But this is surely a vacuous answer to
the question of aesthetic relevance and a reductio of the attempt to answer that
question primarily by reference to states of the appreciator.
A more fruitful approach to the question of aesthetic relevance is to tie its answer
not to the subject of appreciation, but rather, as elaborated in the preceding chapter,
to the object of appreciation. As noted in that chapter, Paul Ziff puts this point by
saying that objects of appreciation “make demands.” And, since objects of
appreciation obviously differ, so does what is demanded for their aesthetic
appreciation.
6
However, what this means is that answers to the question of aesthetic
relevance must be given by reference to the nature of objects of appreciation rather
than states of appreciators. Recognizing the fact that objects of appreciation “make
demands” also has significant implications for how the question of aesthetic
relevance itself is understood. When the question is put in terms of states of the
appreciator, it is typically taken as the question of what “outside information,” if
any, will put the appreciator into the required state. And thus the answers tend to
cluster around two extremes, either that none whatsoever is needed or that any
whatsoever will do—just as long as it does the job. But when the question is put in
terms of the object of appreciation, it must be understood as the question of what
“outside information” is necessary in order to appreciate this particular object or
objects of this particular kind. In short, the question of aesthetic relevance must be
interpreted as a question of aesthetic necessity.
7
When the question is understood in
this manner, both of the extreme answers, none whatsoever and any whatsoever,
seem completely implausible. Given a particular object, why would one imagine
that no information about it is necessary for its appreciation, or, even less plausibly,
that any information whatsoever is?
Thus, the object-focused approach to the question of aesthetic relevance, in
interpreting the question as one of what is necessary for the appropriate appreciation
of the object in question, has direct implications for the traditional answers to the
question. On the one hand, the turn to the object immediately takes the question of
aesthetic relevance beyond the conservative answer supported by doctrines such as
formalism and disinterestedness. Yet, on the other hand, concerning liberal answers
such as Eaton’s or that of postmodernism, the object-focused approach does not
bring us even as far as the former, let alone the latter. This is because the key idea of
objects making demands on appreciators involves not only requirements for
appreciators, but also limitations on them: appropriate aesthetic appreciation of an
object is understood as appreciation in light of what is necessary, but not more than
this. There remains irrelevant as well as relevant “outside information” for
the appreciation of any given object. Thus, an object-focused approach steers
between the two extremes, rejecting the all or nothing dichotomy that has
captivated the philosophical tradition.
132 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
Between nature and art: appreciating other things
The object-focused approach to the question of aesthetic relevance not only moves
beyond the traditional philosophical answers to the question, it also has clear and
important implications concerning applied aesthetics. In recognizing that an object
of appreciation “makes demands” on appreciators, it establishes the necessity of
“outside information” in our actual appreciative practice. This should be obvious
concerning the two paradigm kinds of objects of aesthetic appreciation: art and
nature. Concerning the former, it should be clear, as is assumed in the first part of
this volume, that in appropriate aesthetic appreciation of works of art certain
historical, cultural, and artistic information is necessary. The information concerns
answers to questions such as what the work is, how it was produced, and why it was
produced in the way it was. Such information may be called the “history of
production” of the work. However, although these ramifications of an object-
focused approach concerning art appreciation are significant, they are hardly novel.
Few but the last supporters of strict formalism would deny the aesthetic relevance of
information about the histories of production of works of art, and few but the
advocates of the most radical postmodernism would embrace the relevance of
absolutely any information whatsoever.
Concerning the other paradigm kind of object of aesthetic appreciation, nature,
similar conclusions are plausible. Indeed, this is one of the major contentions of the
first part of this volume, especially Chapters 4, 5, and 6. To briefly reiterate that
contention: it is not unreasonable to believe that, in the aesthetic appreciation of
nature, information about “history of production” is equally as aesthetically relevant
as it is in the case of art. The difference is that with nature the relevant information
—the story of nature’s history of production—is scientific information about the
natural world. Thus, as the information provided by art critics and art historians is
aesthetically relevant for art, that provided by naturalists, ecologists, geologists, and
natural historians is equally so for nature.
8
Moreover, as in the case of art, natural
history’s aesthetic relevance to the appropriate appreciation of the natural world is
becoming increasing accepted.
9
And there is even awareness that some approaches to
the appreciation of nature—for example, those involving excessive emphasis on
ideas that are less naturalistic, such as the picturesque—may involve aesthetically
irrelevant thoughts, images, and associations.
What, however, about the aesthetics of the never-never land between nature and
art? What does the object-focused approach say about appropriate aesthetic
appreciation of, for example, roadsides and cornfields, gardens and graffiti, churches
and office buildings? To address this issue, it is useful to more fully understand the
insight of the object-focused approach concerning nature and art. For each of these,
this approach answers the question of aesthetic relevance by reference to history of
production: the explanation of how the object of appreciation came to be as it is. For
each of nature and art such explanation is the core of what is necessary for
appropriate aesthetic appreciation. This is because each of at least the extremes of
nature and art—pristine nature and pure art—are what they are primarily in virtue
BETWEEN NATURE AND ART 133
of how they came to be as they are. In other words, neither pristine nature nor pure
art have, as such, a purpose or a function. They are not what they are in virtue of
what they are meant or intended to accomplish. This, of course, does not mean that
particular works of art and particular natural objects cannot be put to a purpose, but
only that having such a purpose is not a dimension of their natures as nature and as
art. Thus, for nature and art, the question of aesthetic relevance is successfully
addressed by reference to history of production and perhaps even by reference to
this alone.
However, once an appreciator moves the slightest distance from either pristine
nature or pure art in the direction of the arena of human endeavor that stands
between these two extremes, the situation changes dramatically. Any movement
away from pristine nature takes one into the world of landscapes, countrysides,
farmsteads, and beyond. Any movement away from pure art brings one to
architecture, industrial design, commercial art, and all the varied applied arts. Of
course, the fact that such endeavors constitute neither pristine nature nor pure art,
and, as such, are not purposeless, in no way makes them inappropriate objects for
aesthetic appreciation. They are fully fledged, fully qualified objects of aesthetic
appreciation and the question of aesthetic relevance arises as seriously for them as it
does for both nature and art. What this fact does indicate, however, is that at least
some of such objects are, in a sense that becomes clear in the second part of this
volume, somewhat more difficult and complex objects of aesthetic appreciation.
10
In
part this means that the question of aesthetic relevance cannot be successfully
addressed as simply as it can for nature and art.
What, then, are the ramifications concerning the question of aesthetic relevance?
Things such as roadsides, cornfields, gardens, graffiti, churches, and office buildings
all belong to the rich world between nature and art, to the world of landscapes,
architecture, and the applied arts. All such things have a function, a purpose; and
they are what they are in virtue of what they are meant or intended to accomplish.
Consequently information simply about their histories of production is typically not
sufficient for addressing the question of aesthetic relevance. Rather, given an object-
focused approach together with the fact that these things are functional things, what
is absolutely necessary for and central to their appropriate aesthetic appreciation is
information about their functions. With all such things the main issue is not simply
how they came to be as they are, but why they came to be as they are. The key to
their natures is the purpose or the function they are meant to serve. In
appropriate aesthetic appreciation of these things, the first and most important
request for “outside information” is not, as it is for both pristine nature and pure art,
“What is it and how did it come to be as it is?” Rather the primary question is
“What does it do and why does it do it?”
Of course, even without embracing an object-focused approach, this observation
about the aesthetic relevance of function should be somewhat self-evident. In fact, it
has not been completely overlooked by the tradition concerning at least some things
that are neither pristine nature nor pure art. For example, the idea that there is a
significant relationship between function and design has a long history in the
134 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
aesthetics of architecture, and thus it seems evident that information about the
function of a building is relevant to its appropriate appreciation. The idea is perhaps
most famously captured in the slogan, “form follows function.”
11
In a similar way,
in other areas of human endeavor closely allied with pure art, such as commercial
art and industrial design, there is recognition of the relevance of function to good
design and thus at least implicit recognition of the necessity of information about
function for appropriate aesthetic appreciation. Moreover, there is increasing
acknowledgement of this kind of idea in those areas involving design on a larger
scale, such as landscape architecture, city planning, and environmental design.
12
The aesthetic relevance of information about function, however, is less clearly and
fully appreciated concerning those things not closely allied to pure art, but more
akin to pristine nature. Consider, for example, agricultural landscapes and rural
countrysides. Although they are frequently almost completely formed in virtue of
human functions and purposes, it is not always obvious that they are so formed—at
least not nearly as obvious as in the case of the products of architecture and
industrial design. Thus, the relevance of information about function to aesthetic
appreciation is easily overlooked. Yet, to appropriately appreciate a landscape, we
must know the different uses to which the land has been put and which have thus
shaped its look. Some of these uses, such as the practical uses of agriculture and
mining, determine the look of the land in rather evident ways.
13
But others, such
the symbolic, mythical, and religious uses to which human beings put the land,
contribute to the formation of landscapes in a much more subtle fashion.
14
Nonetheless, information about all such functions, whether obvious or subtle in
their effects, is essential to appropriate aesthetic appreciation.
In summary: my suggestion is that in general an object-focused approach to the
question of aesthetic relevance is required, for we will be guided to appropriate
aesthetic appreciation only by taking into account the real nature of the object of
appreciation. Moreover, concerning those things that are between nature and art,
what is needed for appropriate appreciation is the recognition of the necessity of
information not only about their natures but also about their functions. The
chapters in the second part of this volume pursue this suggestion.
Notes
1 As indicated in Chapter 7, Jerome Stolnitz’s classic formulation of the question is: “Is
it ever ‘relevant’ to aesthetic experience to have thoughts or images or bits of
knowledge which are not present within the object itself? If these are ever relevant,
under what conditions are they so?” See Stolnitz, Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
Criticism: A Critical Introduction, Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 1960, p. 53. For a fuller
discussion of Stolnitz’s position and the question of aesthetic relevance, see my chapter
on “Appreciating Art and Appreciating Nature,” in S.Kemal and I.Gaskell (eds)
Landscape, Natural Beauty, and the Arts, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1993, pp. 199–227 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 7).
BETWEEN NATURE AND ART 135
2 I also discuss disinterestedness and aesthetic appreciation in “Understanding and
Aesthetic Experience” (in this volume, Chapter 2).
3 For a fuller examination of formalism and aesthetic appreciation, see “Understanding
and Aesthetic Experience” (in this volume, Chapter 2), and “Formal Qualities in the
Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1979, vol. 13, pp. 99–114
(reproduced in this volume, Chapter 3). I also discuss these issues in “On the
Possibility of Quantifying Scenic Beauty,” Landscape Planning, 1977, vol. 4, pp. 131–
72.
4 Marcia Muelder Eaton, “Where’s the Spear? The Question of Aesthetic Relevance,”
British Journal of Aesthetics, 1992, vol. 32, pp. 1–12. The quote is from page 4. Eaton’s
analysis of the aesthetic is developed in her Aesthetics and the Good Life, Cranbury,
Associated University Press, 1989.
5 Eaton, “Wheres the Spear?,” op. cit., p. 5. Richard Wollheim’s position is developed
in Painting as an Art, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1987.
6Paul Ziff, Antiaesthetics: An Appreciation of the Cow with the Subtile Nose, Dordrecht,
Reidel, 1984, p. 135. I elaborate Ziff’s account of aesthetic appreciation in “Critical
Notice of Ziff, Antiaesthetics: An Appreciation of the Cow with the Subtile Nose,”
Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1987, vol. 17, pp. 919–33. I more fully discuss his
contribution to an object-focused notion of appreciation in “Appreciating Art and
Appreciating Nature,” in Kemal and Gaskell, op. cit., pp. 199–227 (reproduced in
this volume, Chapter 7) and “Nature, Aesthetic Appreciation, and Knowledge,”
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1995, vol. 53, pp. 393–400.
7 Eaton’s excellent discussion of “aesthetic necessity” is relevant here. See Eaton,
“Where’s the Spear?,” op. cit., pp. 6–8.
8 I develop the view that scientific information is relevant to aesthetic appreciation of
nature in several other papers, reproduced throughout Part I of this volume, especially
in “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–76 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4), “Nature, Aesthetic
Judgment, and Objectivity,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1981, vol. 40, pp.
15–27 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 5) and “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,”
Environmental Ethics, 1984, vol. 6. pp. 5–34 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6).
9 Of particular interest in this regard are H. Rolston, “Does Aesthetic Appreciation of
Nature Need to be Science Based?,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1995, vol. 35, pp.
374–86 and M.Eaton, “Fact and Fiction in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” in
A.Berleant and A.Carlson (eds) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. Special
Issue: Environmental Aesthetics, 1998, vol. 56, pp. 149–56.
10 I discuss this issue in “Is Environmental Art an Aesthetic Affront to Nature?,”
Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1986, vol. 16, pp. 635–50 (reproduced in this
volume, Chapter 10), “Interactions between Art and Nature: Environmental Art,” in
P. McCormick (ed.) The Reasons of Art: L’Art a ses raisons, Ottawa, University of
Ottawa Press, 1985, pp. 222–31 and “On the Aesthetic Appreciation of Japanese
Gardens,” The British Journal of Aesthetics, 1997, vol. 37, pp. 47–56 (reproduced in
this volume, Chapter 11).
11 The slogan is usually attributed to Louis Sullivan. I discuss Sullivan and the
importance of function in architecture in “Existence, Location, and Function: The
Appreciation of Architecture, in M. Mitias (ed.) Philosophy and Architecture,
Amsterdam, Rodopi, 1994, pp. 141–64 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 13).
136 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
12 I discuss related matters in “Reconsidering the Aesthetics of Architecture,” Journal of
Aesthetic Education, 1986, vol. 20, pp. 21–7.
13 I address the role of information about function in the appreciation of such landscapes
in “On Appreciating Agricultural Landscapes,Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
1985, vol. 43, pp. 301–12 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 12).
14 I pursue these ideas in “Landscape and Literature” (in this volume, Chapter 14).
BETWEEN NATURE AND ART 137
138
9
ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS AND
THE DILEMMA OF AESTHETIC
EDUCATION
The eyesore argument
In this chapter I consider the great expanse of our environment that stands between
pristine nature and pure art by addressing a particular environmental movement and
one specific argument that is given in support of this movement. The movement is
the “clean up the environment” movement and the argument is what I call the
“eyesore argument.”
The clean up the environment movement is, of course, that movement urging us
to clean up our environment of the junk, litter, and debris that presently clutter it.
It is clearly an important movement with far-reaching consequences. It expresses
itself in numerous ways in our society; for example, in anti-litter campaigns in the
media, in the call to recycle common litter articles such as cans, bottles, and paper,
and in social pressure and legislation concerning billboards, junk yards, and mining
practices. However, perhaps one of the best publicized developments of the general
movement is the call to “beautify” our roads and highways.
1
For this reason I utilize
the campaign to clean up our roadways as my main example. However, the issues
under discussion are equally relevant to many of the other directions this
environmental movement has taken and can take.
The eyesore argument is one of a number of different arguments frequently
offered in support of the clean up the environment movement. It does not, as some
other arguments do, take note of contentions such as, for example, that junk, litter,
and debris have a negative ecological effect or that littering is wasteful. Rather it
appears to be an argument that makes an explicit appeal to aesthetic considerations.
In its popular form it is the contention that we should clean the environment of
junk, litter, and debris because such materials are “eyesores.” I take it that the
substance of this argument is simply that roadside clutter, for example, is unsightly,
an eyesore; consequently, when scattered about the environment, it distracts from
the aesthetically pleasing nature of that environment. Since an aesthetically pleasing
environment is to be preferred to one that is not, we should clean up the
environment. Understood in this way, the eyesore argument has two basic premises:
first, that roadside clutter, for example, is not aesthetically pleasing and, second, that
an aesthetically pleasing environment is to be preferred to one that is not. These two
premises are my main concern.
The above argument is generally taken to be persuasive. However, I think that
the grounds of its strength have not been made explicit. In the remainder of this
chapter I attempt to bring out the argument’s full strength by discussing a line of
attack on the argument and some alternatives for countering this attack.
The dilemma of aesthetic education
The attack on the eyesore argument can be elaborated by considering what Monroe
Beardsley calls the “dilemma of aesthetic education.”
2
As I understand this
dilemma, it can be developed in at least two different ways: either by reference to
traditional aesthetic attitude theories or by reference to what is called “camp
sensibility.” Beardsley relies on the latter mode of development and I follow him in
this. The idea of camp sensibility is popularized by art critic Susan Sontag. In
“Notes on ‘Camp’” Sontag states that “camp is a certain mode of aestheticism… It
is one way of seeing the world as an aesthetic experience” that “has the power to
transform experience.”
3
Moreover, this transformation of experience is often of our
experiences of objects that, although not commonly experienced as aesthetically
pleasing, can be so experienced with the aid of camp. In other words, objects that
are typically seen as unsightly or as in bad taste or even as simply aesthetically
uninteresting can by means of camp sensibility become objects of aesthetic
enjoyment. Sontag gives a number of examples that she takes to be of this kind.
They include such things as the “concoctions of Tin Pan Alley and Liverpool,”
“turn-of-the-century picture postcards,” “old Flash Gordon comics,” and “kitsch
art” in general.
4
It is the transformation of our experience of such objects that
generates Beardsley’s dilemma. The dilemma is that we are divided between two
conflicting ways of dealing with something that we initially do not aesthetically
enjoy: one is to change the world such that the object of aesthetic displeasure is
eliminated; the other is to educate people to change their aesthetic sensibilities such
that the object, although itself unchanged, can be experienced as aesthetically
pleasing. In short, camp’s transformation of our experience of aesthetically
displeasing objects yields an alternative to ridding the world of such objects.
5
The dilemma of aesthetic education as generated by camp thus meets the eyesore
argument head on. It recognizes the first basic premise—that roadside clutter, for
example, is not aesthetically pleasing—by admitting that we initially find litter, junk
yards, strip mines, and so forth unsightly. But it counters the argument by
presenting an alternative to the conclusion that the environmentalist wishes to draw
—that is, that we should clean up the environment. Instead, it suggests, why not
develop our camp sensibility such that roadside clutter and the like become
aesthetically pleasing? Transforming our experience of the offending objects can
solve the problem as effectively as removing the objects. The line of thought is
suggested by a cartoon that Beardsley describes. It shows “the proprietor of a junk
yard namedSams Salvage standing by a huge pile of junked cars, and saying to
140 ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS AND AESTHETIC EDUCATION
two other men: ‘Whattya mean it’s an ugly eyesore? If I’d paid Picasso to pile it up,
you’d call it a work of art’”
6
Seeing something as a work of art can do the same job
as camp sensibility.
The proposal that we solve the problem of our unsightly environment simply by
changing our sensibilities is likely to be condemned as too ridiculous to consider.
However, some things can be said in its favor. First, in recent years camp has become
a rather well-respected form of sensibility for certain art genres. Sontag, for example,
points out that a full analysis of art nouveau cannot ignore that aspect of it that lends
itself to camp. Moreover, although Sontag does admit that “not everything can be
seen as camp,” camp sensibility seems particularly appropriate to many of those
objects that constitute roadside clutter. This is suggested by the fact that camp has
developed hand in hand with certain art movements, some of which often imitate
such things as billboards and tin cans, and others of which occasionally utilize junk
and trash as a medium. Second, there are some practical points in favor of this
proposal. For example, developing camp sensibility toward our environment might
be easier and would certainly be more economical than attempting to clean up the
environment. Perhaps we as a society cannot afford to select the latter alternative?
And given that there are some segments of our environment that virtually cannot be
salvaged, adopting camp sensibility for them is certainly more reasonable than
forcing ourselves to live with what we experience as an eyesore. In short, the use of
camp for our so-called unsightly environment seems respectable, appropriate,
practical, economical, and in some cases our only hope! With all this in favor of camp
sensibility, the eyesore argument, by contrast, does not appear to give much support
for cleaning up the environment.
Nonetheless, in spite of almost anything that can be said for the camp sensibility
proposal, I think it is clear that most people, and especially environmentalists,
would not find it a satisfactory answer to the environmental problems under
discussion here. They simply would not see it as an acceptable response to the
eyesore argument. We should not conclude from this that environmentalists and
like-minded people are narrow-mindedly wanting to solve our environmental
problems in their own way, without regard for somewhat creative new proposals.
Rather we should attempt to take a more serious look at these issues and especially
at the eyesore argument itself.
The natural
As noted previously, the eyesore argument has two basic premises. The first—that
roadside clutter is not aesthetically pleasing—is the focus for the counter to the
argument posed by the dilemma of aesthetic education. We must ultimately discuss
this premise further, but first it is helpful to consider the second basic premise,
namely, that an aesthetically pleasing environment is to be preferred to one that is
not. I think we can avoid being led astray at this point if we consider this premise by
means of a somewhat digressional investigation into the fact that it is frequently
what is thought of as the natural environment that is at issue.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 141
It is quite clear that the naturalness of the environment plays some role in the
problems under discussion here. This is suggested by how unsatisfactory we, and
certainly environmentalists, must find proposals that certain roadways be
“beautified” with durable, life-size, plastic “trees” and “shrubs.”
7
It is claimed that
such “trees” and “shrubs” are as aesthetically pleasing as the real thing, and in one
sense, this may be correct, for if they are good replicas, they will look just like the
real thing. Yet most people find such roadside decor quite unsatisfactory, and I
suspect that this is at least in part because it is not, in some sense, natural. In light of
this, perhaps a proponent of the eyesore argument may claim that even if we
aesthetically enjoyed roadside clutter, it still must be cleaned up, for it is not
natural. In making this claim such a proponent seems to be shifting the focus of the
argument from the aesthetically displeasing nature of roadside clutter to its
unnaturalness. However, this shift need not be too great, for perhaps the eyesore
argument has a suppressed premise to the effect that roadside clutter is less
aesthetically pleasing than the natural environment just because it is less natural.
Such a premise might help to meet the claim that roadside clutter can become
aesthetically pleasing with camp sensibility. Nonetheless, it seems to commit the
eyesore argument to the assumption that there is a positive correlation between an
object’s being natural and its being aesthetically pleasing. And, although, as noted in
Chapter 6, such an assumption may be plausible concerning pristine nature, it is
very problematic if the objects in question, as in the case of roadside clutter, are not
completely natural to begin with. For example, in both art and craft it is clear that
artists and craftsmen make some objects more aesthetically pleasing simply by
making them less natural. Consider, for instance, the cabinet maker polishing the
natural wood of his or her furniture or the sculptor altering the natural shape of his
or her stone. Moreover, even concerning certain so-called natural environments,
people sometimes seem to find parts of such environments more aesthetically
pleasing when these parts are deliberately made less natural; for instance, there is
some evidence to the effect that people aesthetically enjoy artificially thinned forests
more than ones left in their natural state.
8
All this suggests that the eyesore
argument cannot receive much support from an appeal to naturalness.
Nonetheless, as suggested in the foregoing, naturalness is certainly important to
these environmental issues. However, if we shift the focus further toward
naturalness, we have a new argument rather than the eyesore argument. This would
be an argument to the effect that we must clean up our roadways not because litter
and the like is unsightly, but simply because it is not natural. I make a few remarks
about this argument because I believe it is what some people actually have in mind
when they present what sounds like the eyesore argument. First, we can note that
this new argument is not affected by the dilemma of aesthetic education. Second,
however, it unfortunately has other problems, many of which stem from the
vagueness of the term “natural.” For example, it is not obvious that trees and shrubs
are the natural environment for the sides of roadways and the outskirts of cities; in
some senses of “natural” perhaps junk yards, litter dumps, and billboards are much
more natural. The point is that arguments that appeal to the natural concerning
142 ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS AND AESTHETIC EDUCATION
environmental problems necessarily presume answers to questions such as “What
kinds of things are natural?” and “What is man’s natural environment?” These are
important philosophical questions that must be considered before any argument
from naturalness can be evaluated. However, to discuss them here would take us too
far from our aesthetic-centered concerns.
9
The aesthetically pleasing
The digression of the preceding section shows that the eyesore argument cannot
easily be salvaged through elaborating its second premise by reference to
naturalness. The result is either a new set of problems or a quite different argument
—an argument that is also problematic. Consequently, we must return to the first
premise—that roadside clutter is not aesthetically pleasing—and examine a key
concept of both this and the second premise: the concept of being aesthetically
pleasing.
Up to this point we have relied on a rather pre-analytic, intuitive notion of being
aesthetically pleasing; one that is, I suspect, quite similar to that used in the popular
form of the eyesore argument. However, to shed light on the problems posed by the
dilemma of aesthetic education, we need to refine this notion in certain ways. The
tradition of philosophical aesthetics provides a distinction and some accompanying
concepts that are helpful. The distinction is related to some of the issues discussed in
Chapters 2 and 3; here we may understand it as a distinction between two senses of
being aesthetically pleasing. In this form the distinction is well-illustrated in the
work of D.W.Prall and, following him, John Hospers.
10
Hospers describes it as a
distinction between the “thin sense” and the “thick sense” of “aesthetic,” labels that
serve for our purposes. The thin sense is relevant when we aesthetically enjoy an
object primarily in virtue of the physical appearance of the object, including not
only its surface physical properties, but also its formal properties having to do with
line, shape, and color. The thick sense, on the other hand, involves not merely the
physical appearance of the object, but also certain qualities and values that the
object expresses or conveys to the viewer. Prall calls this the “expressive beauty” of
the object, while Hospers speaks of objects expressing “life values.”
The distinction can be elaborated in terms of examples. Consider an older house.
We often find such houses aesthetically pleasing because of, for example, the design
of the windows or the color of the woodwork, but this is only part of the matter. In
many cases we also enjoy such houses aesthetically because they give the general
impression of a less hectic, more genteel way of life or show more signs of care and
craftsmanship than do many newer houses. In like manner, much music is
aesthetically pleasing not only because of its intricate pattern of sounds, but also
because of the melancholy or the sadness or the joy it expresses; some sports cars are
aesthetically pleasing not only in virtue of their lines and colors, but also in virtue of
expressing speed and workmanship. Hospers gives some similar examples from the
natural environment:
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 143
When we contemplate a starry night or a mountain lake we see it not merely
as an arrangement of pleasing colors, shapes, and volumes, but as expressive of
many things in life, drenched with the fused association of many scenes and
emotions from memory and experience.
11
These comments and examples adequately clarify, for our purposes here, the
distinction between the thin and the thick sense of being aesthetically pleasing.
However, before applying this distinction, some additional remarks about the thick
sense are in order. Concerning this I speak of objects expressing “life values” or
having “expressive qualities.” These terms refer to a fairly wide range of human
values, emotions, and attitudes that are associated with objects in such a way that it
is appropriate to say that an object expresses these values, emotions, and attitudes.
The relevant concept of “expression” is of the kind initially clarified by Santayana.
12
Thus for an object to express a quality or life value, the latter must not simply be
suggested by it. Rather the quality must be associated with the object in such a way
that it is felt or perceived to be a quality of the object itself; that is, what Santayana
meant by saying that the object must seem to “embody” that which it expresses.
Clarified in this way, expression is not typically due to the unique associations
resulting from an individual’s own personal history. Rather what is involved are the
more general and deep-seated associations that are characteristically held in common
by a community of individuals and by and large derived from what is perceived
within that community of individuals to be the nature and function of the
expressive object. Thus, the life values an object expresses are often the ones
reflecting the values, emotions, and attitudes of the individuals who are responsible
for its nature and function.
Life values and the eyesore argument
Given the distinction between the thin and the thick sense and accompanying
concepts such as “expression” and “life values,” we can now sort out the issue
between the eyesore argument and camp sensibility, and perhaps reveal the full
strength of the eyesore argument. If we take this argument in terms of the thin
sense, the argument claims that the physical appearance and form of the
environment is more aesthetically pleasing than the physical appearance and form of
billboards, junk yards, roadside litter, and the like. This claim seems initially plausible,
and consequently the argument is usually not developed further. In short, the
argument appears cogent when developed in terms of the thin sense and is therefore
not developed in terms of the thick sense. However, a dilemma is posed by camp
sensibility just because camp is claimed to make the physical appearance and form
of roadside clutter as aesthetically pleasing as is the environment. And if the thin sense
is all that is considered, this claim seems plausible. Thus we have no cogent
argument for cleaning up the environment.
However, as may be suggested by the consideration of related matters in Chapters
2 and 3, to consider this issue in terms of the thin sense alone is to do justice neither
144 ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS AND AESTHETIC EDUCATION
to the eyesore argument nor to camp sensibility. Whether the proponents of the
eyesore argument realize it or not, roadside clutter is unsightly because of much
more than its physical appearance. I think proponents of the argument tend to
consider it in terms of the thin sense alone because they assume it is largely the
physical appearance of the environment that makes it aesthetically pleasing. The life
values expressed by the environment are less obvious and more difficult to
determine. Yet the life values expressed by roadside clutter are at least as important
as, if not more important than, its physical appearance in making such clutter an
eyesore. In fact, I suggest that it is unsightly primarily because of these expressive
qualities. By and large, its expressive qualities are qualities associated with things
such as waste, disregard, carelessness, and exploitation. It is by taking note of this
fact that the eyesore argument becomes a forceful argument.
In a somewhat similar manner, it is equally incorrect to consider camp sensibility
only in terms of the thin sense. In the way in which it helps us to aesthetically enjoy
the physical appearance and formal qualities of art forms such as art nouveau, camp
can also help us to enjoy aesthetically these same aspects in billboards, beer cans, and
junked cars. This is because, as Sontag says, camp emphasizes “texture, sensuous
surface, and style at the expense of content.”
13
Yet this is still only part of the
matter. Camp sensibility is also relevant to the thick sense of an object’s being
aesthetically pleasing, in that camp, through its detachment and emphasis on style,
often makes it possible for us to become more aware of those expressive qualities of
objects that constitute the thick sense. In doing this, however, camp does not
change these expressive qualities. Sontag rightly points out that “objects, being
objects, don’t change when they are singled out by the Camp vision.”
14
What camp
does is make us aware of the expressive qualities that are present and invites us to
enjoy them, if we can. “Camp taste is, above all, a mode of enjoyment, of
appreciation, not judgment.”
15
I noted above that the life values expressed by roadside clutter such as junk yards,
strip mines, and discarded litter seem to me to be qualities associated with things
such as waste, disregard, carelessness, and exploitation. If this is the case, camp
sensibility cannot alter this fact; it can only make us more aware of it and ask us to
enjoy aesthetically the expression of such qualities. Perhaps with camp we can find
aesthetically pleasing the expression of such qualities and consequently aesthetically
enjoy roadside clutter. In fact, however, I rather doubt if many of us can. A strip
mine that is expressive of exploitation or roadside litter that is expressive of carelessness
and disregard are at least as difficult to find aesthetically pleasing as are a sports car
that is expressive of shoddy workmanship or a cheap novel that is expressive of the
desire for the fast buck. And it is often due to the fact that cheap and shoddy
versions of objects such as cars and houses, novels and musical compositions are
expressive of such life values that we do not and cannot aesthetically enjoy them in
the thick sense. If the case is similar concerning roadside clutter, then camp cannot
succeed in making it aesthetically pleasing in the thick sense of that concept. The
result is that with the thick sense the dilemma of aesthetic education cannot arise.
This point is important, for it not only reinstates the eyesore argument as a strong
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 145
and effective argument, it also indicates the full extent to which roadside and other
environment clutter is truly an “eyesore.”
The preceding brings out the difficulty of aesthetically enjoying in the thick sense
objects that express certain life values. That we often are not able to enjoy
aesthetically in the thick sense such objects is a fairly uncontroversial empirical claim.
However, there is a second and perhaps more controversial empirical claim that, if
accepted, makes the above line of thought even stronger. This is the claim that when
we are actually unable to find an object aesthetically pleasing in the thick sense
because of the (negative) nature of its expressive qualities, this often makes aesthetic
enjoyment of this object in the thin sense psychologically difficult, if not impossible.
If this claim is true, then in some instances any aesthetic enjoyment of an object will
be impossible because of the nature of that object’s expressive qualities. In light of
this, the fact that camp sensibility often makes us more aware of an object’s
expressive qualities becomes quite significant. It means that the utilization of camp
for certain objects will, in virtue of making us more aware of their expressive
qualities, make any aesthetic enjoyment of these objects impossible. Moreover, since
camp, by definition, is a mode of aesthetic enjoyment, the successful and sustained
adoption of camp sensibility toward such objects becomes impossible. In short,
some objects, because of their expressive qualities, cannot be aesthetically enjoyed by
adopting camp sensibility. To attempt to do so is self-refuting. Consequently, if we
grant the truth of the above-mentioned empirical claim concerning certain objects,
the conclusion is not only that camp cannot generate the dilemma of aesthetic
education in either the thin or the thick sense for such objects, but also that these
objects are among those which Sontag admits cannot be “seen as camp.” This
conclusion gives a strong version of the eyesore argument in the thin as well as the
thick sense by means of showing that, in the final analysis, we need not take
seriously the challenge of camp sensibility.
I believe the foregoing line of thought yields a strengthened and yet essentially
aesthetic version of the eyesore argument. However, in doing so, it depends on two
claims that I take to be empirical. Since I do not wish the issue to turn completely
on either of these empirical claims, I conclude this section by mentioning a second,
perhaps in the long run more promising, direction for the eyesore argument to take.
This direction parallels that of the moral argument concerning the aesthetic
appreciation of nature that is suggested at the end of Chapter 5.
This development of the argument turns on what seems to me a conceptual
point: that our aesthetic enjoyment of an object counts toward our wishing to
experience that object and thus against our wishing to eliminate it. Consequently, if
we find roadside clutter aesthetic pleasing, our desire to experience it is somewhat
heightened and our desire to eliminate it somewhat lessened. Now suppose for a
moment that with the help of camp sensibility or whatever, we do find roadside
clutter aesthetically pleasing in the thick sense. This would mean that we
aesthetically enjoy the expression of certain life values. Moreover, given the concept
of expression discussed above, many of these life values are expressed by roadside
clutter in virtue of the human values and attitudes that are in part responsible for
146 ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS AND AESTHETIC EDUCATION
roadside clutter. However, in light of the above-mentioned conceptual point, our
aesthetic enjoyment of the expression of these life values involves at least tacitly
condoning these human values and attitudes in virtue of which roadside clutter
expresses these life values. In general, our not wishing to eliminate and in fact
wishing to experience an effect requires at least condoning, if not actually
approving, the cause. But the problem is that many of these human values and
attitudes are of a kind that we find morally unacceptable, and condoning or
approving the morally unacceptable is itself morally unacceptable. Thus when we
find it possible to enjoy roadside clutter aesthetically, we may not find it morally
acceptable to do so. We may in the last analysis be forced by our moral values to
clean up the environment. I believe that this suggests a fruitful way in which the
eyesore argument may be developed. Construed in this way, it is not simply an
aesthetic argument, but a moral-aesthetic argument that relies on a certain
combination of our moral values and our aesthetic sensibilities. I also think that in
construing it in this manner we may be coming closer to the popular form of the
argument, for the dialogue between environmentalists and their opponents is often
marked by moral indignation and outrage, even when the issues seem to be argued
purely in aesthetic terms.
Conclusion
In the preceding section of this chapter, I have outlined some ways in which the
eyesore argument may be seen to have the force we initially think it has. In doing so
I have relied on the assumption that roadside clutter expresses certain objectionable
life values, those associated with things such as waste, disregard, carelessness, and
exploitation. I conclude this chapter with some further discussion of this assumption
in the hope of supporting its plausibility. Let us begin by reference to some related
examples. Consider the life-size, plastic “trees” previously mentioned. I admit that in
one sense such “trees” may be as aesthetically pleasing as the real thing. This is in
the thin sense. If these “trees” are good replicas, they will have a physical appearance
and form very similar to real trees and consequently in the thin sense be equally
aesthetically pleasing. In this case, as in the roadside clutter case, however, it is
expressive qualities that are important. I think that we would find plastic “trees”
aesthetically unacceptable mainly because of the life values they would express. And
although it is difficult to describe exactly what they would express, I suggest it
would be something like a combination of resignation and ingenuity. Such an
expressive quality is not as objectionable as those of roadside clutter, but it is still
rather disconcerting, disconcerting enough to make such “trees” difficult to enjoy
aesthetically (and yet perhaps not disconcerting enough to prevent them from being
paradigm objects for camp sensibility).
16
A similarly revealing example is that of “junk art.” By this phrase, I mean art that
is constructed from at least some of the possible contents of roadside clutter.
Examples are sculptures such as Picasso’s Bull’s Head (1943), a “bull’s head
constructed of bicycle parts, and John Chamberlain’s Essex (1960), made with
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 147
automobile parts and scrap metal. Whether or not such art is aesthetically pleasing
depends to a great extent on its expressive qualities and on the expressive qualities of
the materials from which it is constructed. On the one hand, when we find such art
distasteful, this is often because the materials have kept their original expressive
qualities. The artist has not reworked the materials so as to prevent the art work
from expressing rather questionable life values. The obvious examples of this kind of
case are, I expect, some of what is called “found art.” Perhaps this is why some
people find distasteful works such as, for example, Duchamp’s Fountain (1917)—
the famous urinal placed in an art show. On the other hand, we often find junk art
aesthetically pleasing (and morally satisfying). Such is the case, I believe, with Bull’s
Head. This is, I suggest, because here the artist has in effect “recycled” the materials
he has utilized and in doing so changed their expressive qualities. Discarded objects
that would otherwise express waste and disregard are reworked such that they now,
as a work of art, express utilization, concern, and sensitivity. With this in mind, I
think we can shed light on the cartoon the description of which I quoted from
Beardsley above. The point is that had the pile of junked cars been piled by Picasso,
it may well have expressed different life values; it may have expressed the qualities of
junk “recycled” as art, rather than the life values typically expressed by objects that
have been used, abused, and discarded by a waste-oriented society.
The last point I mention can be put as an objection to my suggestion that strip
mines, junk yards, discarded beer cans, and the like express qualities associated with
things such as waste, disregard, carelessness, exploitation. An objector might
contend that such objects do not express these life values, but actually others that
are aesthetically acceptable (and morally appealing), such as, for example, hard work,
determination, vision. And that if this is the case, we can aesthetically enjoy these
objects in both the thin and the thick sense of that concept. Therefore, the moral-
aesthetic version of the eyesore argument does not apply. In reply I offer two brief
comments. First, there is no inconsistency in these objects expressing very different,
seemingly opposed life values. Perhaps many express both disregard and
determination. But if this is the case, the objection has no force, for the expression of
acceptable life values does not cancel out the expression of objectionable ones.
Second, I am not sure who can say with certainty what life values these objects
express. Although I suspect that the art critic and the social critic can help, in the last
analysis it is, I expect, up to us as a community of individuals. For example, it seems
to me that while small family farms along the road may express determination,
discarded car bodies do not, and while the skyline of a city may express vision, a
strip mine does not; but these may be eccentric opinions. Thus perhaps the first step
is for each of us to keep the issue in mind when we next take a look at our environment.
Notes
1 There are attempts to approach the goals of this movement in a scientific or at least quasi-
scientific manner. For example, concerning roads and highways in particular, see
148 ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS AND AESTHETIC EDUCATION
H.Burke, C.Lewis, and H.Orr, “A Method for Classifying Scenery from a Roadway,”
Park Practice Guideline, 1968, vol. 3, pp. 125–41. For a critique of this general kind
of approach, see my “On the Possibility of Quantifying Scenic Beauty,” Landscape
Planning, 1977, vol. 4, pp. 131–72.
2 Beardsley introduces this “dilemma” in Monroe Beardsley, “The Aesthetic Point of
View,” Metaphilosophy, 1970, vol. 1, pp. 39–58. He does not suggest a resolution.
3 Susan Sontag, “Notes on ‘Camp’,Against Interpretation, New York, Dell, 1969, p.
279.
4 Ibid., pp. 279–80.
5 I noted that the dilemma can be developed by reference to traditional aesthetic
attitude theories. This is because most attitude theorists hold that, as it is put by, for
example, Jerome Stolnitz, “the aesthetic attitude can be adopted toward ‘any object of
awareness whatsoever.’” See Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art
Criticism, New York, Houghton Mifflin, 1960, pp. 40–2. If so, the aesthetic attitude
will generate the dilemma.
6 Beardsley, op. cit., p. 55. The cartoon is by David Gerard.
7 I understand that Jefferson Boulevard in Los Angeles has (or had or was at one time
planned to have) plastic trees. I do not know if this is true, but it is suggested by
Martin H.Krieger in “What’s Wrong with Plastic Trees?”, Science, 1973, vol. 179, pp.
446–55.
8 See, for example, W.Rutherford and E.L.Shafer, “Selection Cuts Increase Natural
Beauty in Two Adirondack Forest Stands,Journal of Forestry, 1969, vol. 67, pp. 415–
19. However, such evidence may well be tainted by an overly formalistic approach to
the environment. For a discussion of the relevant issues, see my “Formal Qualities in
the Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1979, vol. 13, pp. 99–114
(reproduced in this volume, Chapter 3) and my “On the Possibility of Quantifying
Scenic Beauty,” op. cit.
9 It is important to note that the whole question of a correlation between naturalness
and being aesthetically pleasing is much more complex than suggested in this short
digression. I address some relevant issues in “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,
Environmental Ethics, 1984, vol. 6. pp. 5–34 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6).
10 D.W.Prall, Aesthetic Judgment, New York, Thomas Y.Crowell Company, 1929, pp.
178–227 and John Hospers, Meaning and Truth in the Arts, Chapel Hill, University of
North Carolina Press, 1946, pp. 11–15.
11 Ibid., pp. 12–13.
12 George Santayana, The Sense of Beauty [1896], New York, Collier Books, 1961, pp.
137ff. I utilize an analysis of “expression” similar to that of Santayana for I take it that
such an analysis is, on the one hand, quite accessible, and on the other, adequate for
present purposes.
13 Sontag, op. cit., p. 280.
14 Ibid., p. 284.
15 Ibid., p. 293.
16 I think the life values expressed by such things as plastic trees are significantly different
from those expressed by roadside clutter for a number of reasons. One that may be
particularly important, however, is that while the latter is simply another dimension of
our problem, the former is a response to that problem, albeit a somewhat feeble and
misguided response.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 149
150
10
IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN
AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
Environmental works of art
In this chapter I consider one aesthetic issue that arises between nature and art in
the sense of arising from an intimate relationship between the two. There are, of
course, many such relationships between nature and art in the history of
humankind’s domination of the earth. However, to investigate this aesthetic issue I
here take as my example a quite recent and essentially artistic phenomenon—what
is typically called environmental art. Within this category I focus mainly on works
such as the earthworks and earthmarks of artists such as Robert Smithson, Michael
Heizer, and Dennis Oppenheim and certain structures on the land such as those of
Robert Morris, Michael Singer, and Christo. Some paradigm cases are Smithson’s
Spiral Jetty (1970), Heizer’s Double Negative (1969–70), Singer’s Lily Pond Ritual
Series (1975), and Christo’s Running Fence (1972–76).
Environmental works of art share a common feature that both distinguishes them
from traditional art and makes them examples of the most intimate of relationships
between nature and art. This is that all such works of art are in or on the land in
such a way that a part of nature constitutes a part of the relevant aesthetic object. In
other words, not only is the site of an environmental work an environmental site,
but the site itself is an aspect of the work. Art critic Elizabeth Baker, for example,
speaks of the site as “a part of the content of the work,” adding that these “works are
not only inseparable from their sites—they are not really definable at all apart from
them.”
1
This is clearly not the case with, for example, most sculpture; with such
works, although the site can be aesthetically significant, it is not a part of the work
itself.
Environmental art was initiated in the mid 1960s and has continued into
present. Throughout this time it has been frequently questioned by individuals
concerned about its environmental and ecological consequences. For example, to
clear the ground for the construction of Running Fence, an 18 foot high, white nylon
“fence” running 24 miles across northern California, Christo had to file a 450 page
environmental impact report and was required to work closely with local
environmental authorities.
2
A more recent and ambitious work by the same artist,
Surrounded Islands (1983), caused greater controversy. Since the work involved
surrounding eleven islands with 5.5 million square feet of pink plastic,
environmentalists were concerned about its consequences for the ecology of the
islands and attempted to prevent its construction by legal action.
3
Works such as
these have even prompted one author to question the morality of environmental art
in general. After discussing a wide range of such works, all of which he calls
earthworks, Peter Humphrey concludes: “Are earthworks ethical? It is doubtful.”
4
In this chapter, however, I do not consider the ecological, legal, and moral issues
raised by these works. Rather I concentrate on only one aesthetic issue about art and
nature that arises from the way in which they are related to one another in
environmental works. In part because of the way nature becomes incorporated into,
becomes a part of, art in such works, it has been suggested by a number of observers
that these works constitute something like aesthetic indignities to nature. One
artist, for example, views many earthworks “as simple one-sided aesthetic
impositions upon nature.”
5
Similarly, in a recent discussion of art and nature,
Donald Crawford notes that some of such works “forcibly assert their artifactuality
over against nature.”
6
He adds that although critics usually challenge the
environmental impact of these works, one cannot but think that they believe the
artists are “engaged in an aesthetic affront to nature that goes deeper than the
scientific assessment of environmental implications.”
7
Following Crawford’s way of
putting this point, I frame the issue under discussion here by asking if
environmental art constitutes an aesthetic affront to nature.
Before discussing this question, it is useful to clarify the issue by noting two
points. First, the affront in question is an aesthetic affront. I take this to indicate that
the affront is generated by the aesthetic qualities of an object, rather than by, for
example, its social, moral, ecological, or other such qualities. Crawford, for example,
distinguishes a work’s “aesthetic affront to nature” from its “environmental
implications.” Thus, although an artwork such as Humphrey’s hypothetical Asian
Floodwork, the object of which “is to show Third-World agriculture under water,”
would have unacceptable moral and ecological qualities, it would not constitute an
aesthetic affront to nature (or to the Third World) on these grounds.
8
Whether or
not it would constitute such an affront would depend on its aesthetic qualities,
whatever they might be. Second, it is important to note that the aesthetic affront is
an affront to nature, and not necessarily to normal or appropriate appreciators of the
work. The affront in question is by works that “assert their artifactuality over
against nature” and are “impositions upon nature.” Of course, works that constitute
such aesthetic affronts to nature may also affront normal, appropriate, or
environmentally concerned appreciators, but such possible affronts are distinct from
the issue involved here. Nonetheless, it is true that the recognition of an aesthetic
affront to nature requires an appreciator, for nature itself cannot recognize the
affront. This seems somewhat peculiar, but I take it to be no more so than the fact
that I can insult, affront, or impose upon Jones even though Jones may not, and
may not even be able to, recognize this.
152 IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
Environmental art as an aesthetic affront
Given this clarification of the issue, I turn to the question of why anyone would
hold that environmental art constitutes an aesthetic affront to nature. The most
obvious and intuitive answer is that some of these works are similar in appearance to
things that almost everyone agrees are such affronts.
9
For example, Walter De
Maria’s Las Vegas Piece (1969) consists of four, 8 foot by ½ to 1 mile earthmarks in
the desert 95 miles northeast of Las Vegas. The work resembles a bulldozer scar on a
virgin desert landscape, which is not unexpected, for it was constructed with a
bulldozer. Heizer’s Double Negative is a 50 foot by 30 foot by 1,500 foot double cut
in Virgin River Mesa, Nevada, which displaces 240,000 tons of rhyolite and
sandstone. It is reminiscent of the results of mining operations, in particular the
highwall cuts and skyline notches produced by Appalachian coal mining. Since the
aesthetic affronts offered by the latter are significant enough to partly justify
reclamation legislation, it is not surprising that some see Heizer’s piece as involving
a similar affront. Indeed, one critic characterizes such artists as cutting and gouging
“the land like Army engineers.”
10
Another striking example is Smithson’s Asphalt
Rundown (1969), constructed by dumping a truckload of asphalt down the side of a
quarry. It resembles the aesthetic consequences of certain kinds of industrial
pollution.
The similarity of appearance of such works to the eyesores produced by industry,
mining, and construction is not accidental. Smithson once remarked that the
“processes of heavy construction have a devastating kind of primordial grandeur
and that the “actual disruption of the earth’s crust is at times very compelling.”
11
Heizer characterizes himself by saying: “You might say I’m in the construction
business.”
12
In fact in the early 1970s Smithson contacted industry in an attempt to
actualize a proposal for a set of works called Projects for Tailings. His vision was to
construct earthworks of the millions of tons of waste “tailings” and spoil produced
by modern mining operations.
13
It becomes clear that environmental works of art
can go further than simply being similar in appearance to the aesthetic affronts of
our technological society. They can be virtually identical to them in appearance.
Consequently, the claim that such works constitute aesthetic affronts to nature
acquires some initial justification. In a way somewhat the converse of the cartoon
mentioned in Chapter 9, one can imagine a “leader of industry” responding to a
work such as Smithson’s Asphalt Rundown with the comment: “If my company had
dumped that eyesore out there, the government would make me clean it up!”
I suggest, however, that this obvious and intuitive line of justification does not
establish its conclusion. This is because I suspect that even if a given environmental
work is absolutely identical in appearance to an undisputed aesthetic affront, the
former need not have the same aesthetic qualities as the latter. My view is that the
aesthetic qualities an object has are only those it appears to have when it is
appropriately appreciated and moreover that such appreciation must involve
appreciation of that object as the kind of thing it is. Consequently, if two different
objects are different kinds of things, they can have very different aesthetic qualities
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 153
even if they are identical in appearance. This general position is defended in
Chapter 5 of this volume as well as in the literature.
14
If it is correct, it means that
since it is a work of art, Heizer’s Double Negative, for example, may be, as one critic
describes it, “a deep, majestic double cut,” while the skyline notches produced by coal
Illustration 3 Asphalt Rundown, by Robert Smithson (1969), Rome (Courtesy of John Weber
Gallery).
154 IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
mining, even if identical in appearance, have no majesty whatsoever.
15
Thus, since
being an aesthetic affront to nature is a function of an object’s aesthetic qualities,
the fact that environmental works of art resemble objects that are undisputed
aesthetic affronts does not by itself establish that they are such affronts. The
aforementioned “leader of industry” is simply not appropriately appreciating these
environmental works—he or she is not appreciating them as works of art.
This general position, however, provides a different means by which to support
the claim that environmental art constitutes an aesthetic affront to nature. If an
object’s aesthetic qualities are those given in appropriate appreciation, and if
appropriate appreciation involves appreciation of the kind of object it is, then there
is a simple way to alter the aesthetic qualities of any object. This is by changing the
kind of object it is. Moreover, such changes of the kind of an object and the
resultant alterations of its aesthetic qualities can constitute an aesthetic affront to
that object—indeed perhaps they necessarily constitute such an affront. The point
can be illustrated by examples from the history of art. Consider Leonardo’s Mona Lisa
(1504) and Duchamp’s famous mustached and goateed version entitled
L.H.O.O.Q. (1919). With a few pencil marks and a punning inscription Duchamp
changed the work’s kind from a Renaissance portrait to a twentieth century Dada
statement and in so doing dramatically altered its aesthetic qualities. After
Duchamp, the work epitomizes, as one observer—an observer no less than Dali—
puts it, the “antiheroic, antiglorification and anti-sublime aspects of Dada.”
16
This
is a relatively clear case of an aesthetic affront to the work in question; in fact some
critics have used stronger terms, such as a “denigration” of the work.
17
Moreover, I
think we find the affront to the work acceptable only because Duchamp used a
reproduction of the Mona Lisa to execute it. Had he used the original, the impact of
the affront would have been greater. Similar affronts to works of art are not difficult
to imagine. Consider changing the kind of work the Guernica (1937) is, perhaps
making it somewhat impressionist, by applying gay, pastel colors to its lighter areas,
or, following Monty Python’s Flying Circus, changing Michelangelo’s David (1501–
04) into a kinetic sculpture by giving it a moveable right arm. As a kinetic sculpture,
the David would have radically different aesthetic qualities, even when its moveable
arm is at rest in the position originally ordained by Michelangelo. This last point
underscores my earlier claim that the affront is not simply a function of the
appearance of an object; it is a function of changing an object’s kind and thereby
altering its aesthetic qualities.
It is in this sense that I think environmental works of art can constitute aesthetic
affronts to nature. As noted earlier, a distinctive feature of environmental art is that
a part of nature itself is a part of the aesthetic object—the environmental site is an
aspect of the work. The environmental artist, sometimes with only a few marks on
the land, comparable to Duchamp’s pencil marks, changes the kind of thing that
this part of nature is. The environmental site is thus changed from being a part of
nature to being a part of an artwork and with this change the aesthetic qualities of
nature are altered. Heizer, for example, says: “The work is not put in a place, it is
that place.”
18
And Smithson spoke of his sites as being “redefined in terms of art.”
19
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 155
If such “redefinition” of kind necessarily involves an aesthetic affront, then
environmental art necessarily constitutes an aesthetic affront to nature. However,
even if there is no necessity involved, it is not difficult to see many environmental
works as comparable to Duchamp’s mustached Mona Lisa or Monty Python’s
kinetic David, although such works lack the lightness and humor of Duchamp’s and
the Python’s creations. More typically the tone is seemingly set by Picasso’s famous
remark: “Nature exists to be raped!”
20
In any case, at least some environmental
artists seem to have taken his words to heart. For example, Heizer comments: “I find
an 18 foot square granite boulder. That’s mass. It’s already a piece of sculpture. But
as an artist it’s not enough for me to say that, so I mess with it. I defile…it.”
21
Perhaps “defile” is too strong a word to characterize most environmental art.
Nonetheless, the general way in which environmental artists alter nature’s aesthetic
qualities by turning nature into art does seem to support its being an affront to
nature. This is illustrated by Heizer’s works such as Displaced-Replaced Mass (1969)
in which a 52 ton granite boulder is “messed with” by placing it in an excavated
depression. It is also evident in works such as Christo’s Surrounded Islands described
earlier and Valley Curtain (1971–72), 200,000 square feet of bright orange nylon
polyamide spanning a Colorado valley, or Oppenheim’s Branded Hillside (1969), a
“branding” of the land executed by killing the vegetation with hot tar. In such cases
nature is “redefined in terms of art” at a cost to its aesthetic qualities such that to
speak of an affront, if not a “denigration,” is quite appropriate.
Some replies to the affront charge
Rather than further develop the claim that environmental art is for the reasons
indicated an aesthetic affront to nature, I now turn to four replies to this charge.
22
One common reply is that environmental works do not constitute affronts because
they are more or less temporary. It is true that many works are temporary. Most of
Oppenheim’s pieces and some of Heizer’s earlier ones were constructed such that
nature would gradually reclaim the site, and all of Christo’s major works are
designed to be dismantled after a specific period of time. For example, although
Valley Curtain took over two years to execute, it was in place for only a few days.
However, this is not true of all environmental art. Many pieces by Smithson, Heizer,
and others are seemingly intended to be permanent marks on the land, and others
are surprisingly durable. For example, although De Maria’s Las Vegas Piece is only a
few inches deep, in 1976 one critic enthusiastically reported: “Six years old and only
slightly eroded, the cut appears freshly ‘drawn.’”
23
Nonetheless, even if all environmental works had the relatively short life spans of
Christo’s pieces, this reply would not be adequate. It might be relevant to the
environmental issues that have been raised about works such as Christo’s, for the
temporary nature of an environmental work can lessen the possibility and the extent
of its having a serious environmental impact. However, the issue of an aesthetic
affront is of an altogether different nature. An affront is like an insult rather than
like an impact, and even if an insult is only temporary, it can yet be as much of and
156 IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
as great an insult as it would be were it permanent. If environmental works of art are
aesthetic affronts to nature, they constitute such affronts by the fact of their
existence and not by the duration of that existence. Had Duchamp pencilled the
mustache and goatee on the Mona Lisa and erased it after a few days, he would yet
have accomplished his affront to the work. And the consequences of the affront,
whatever they are, would have continued to exist after the erasure. Some
environmental artists, even though their works are temporary, are well aware of this
kind of point. When asked whether the site of Valley Curtain remains unaffected by
having hosted the work, Christo replied: “Perhaps not. Was Mont-Saint-Victoire
ever the same after Cezanne?”
24
If Valley Curtain was an aesthetic affront to nature,
then the fact of its existence still constitutes the affront.
A second rather common reply to the affront charge is that environmental works
are not affronts since by altering nature’s aesthetic qualities they improve nature. The
original site is seen as having few positive or mainly negative aesthetic qualities and
the resultant work of art as an improvement on it. In speaking of Heizer, Smithson,
and De Maria, for example, one critic notes that “none of these three artists has
opted for sites that are conventionally scenic; their spaces tend to be rather
neutral.”
25
Smithson in particular is known for his use ofsites that have been
disrupted by industry, reckless urbanization, or nature’s own devastation,” ones he
thought could be “cultivated or recycled as art.”
26
He remarks: “I’m interested in
bringing a landscape with low profile up, rather than bringing one with high profile
down.”
27
The reply, in short, is that given the barren sites of works such as
Smithson’s Spiral Jetty and Amarillo Ramp (1973), Heizer’s Displaced-Replaced Mass
and Double Negative, or De Maria’s Las Vegas Piece, these works do not constitute
affronts. They are comparable not to Duchamp’s treatment of the Mona Lisa, but to
improvements made on the work of a third rate hack.
This reply can be met by considering the extent to which the sites in question are
in fact natural sites. When they are natural, as the desert sites of Heizer and De
Maria, I see no grounds for the claim that they have few positive or mainly negative
aesthetic qualities. It is true that such sites are not “conventionally scenic,” but, as
argued in Chapter 4, “the scenic” is a narrow and parochial construal of nature’s
aesthetic interest and merit.
28
The desert, for example, has a subtle, quiet beauty of
its own, and altering that beauty can be as great an aesthetic affront to nature as
altering the aesthetic qualities of conventionally scenic landscapes. In fact I suggest
that none of virgin nature is comparable to the work of a third-rate hack—that
virgin nature by and large has positive aesthetic qualities. I have developed this
suggestion in Chapter 6.
29
If it is correct, the charge that environmental works on
natural sites constitute affronts to nature cannot be countered by claiming that the
original sites offered little or nothing of aesthetic interest and merit.
On the other hand, some sites such as many of Smithson’s are to various degrees
less than natural. They are sites such as quarries or spoil dumps which have been, in
Smithson’s words, “in some way disrupted or pulverized” and “denaturalized.”
30
In
such cases, to the extent that the site is not a natural site, the environmental work
does not constitute an aesthetic affront to nature. This is because the aesthetic
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 157
qualities that are altered by the work are not the aesthetic qualities of nature but
rather those that have been produced by earlier human incursions. If environmental
works on such sites are designed to regain some of nature’s original aesthetic
qualities, then they may be comparable to an art restorer’s treatment of the Mona
Lisa rather than to Duchamps. However, more typically, as in Robert Morris
Johnson Pit #30 (1979), a former strip mine “decorated” with terracing and tarred
tree stumps, they are designed to “improve” the site by producing new “artistic”
aesthetic qualities. As such, they are comparable to environmental art on any man-
made site, such as in the city. Consider, for example, Otto Piene’s city sky “ballets.”
If such works are not aesthetic affronts to nature, it is not because they are not
aesthetic affronts, but because they do not have natural sites.
A third, more sophisticated reply to the affront charge draws upon the attempt to
identify the works of environmental artists with the works of nature. The idea is
that if environmental art and nature are the same kind of thing, then environmental
art cannot constitute an aesthetic affront to nature, or at least it cannot do so by
changing the kind of thing nature is. The bases for this reply were most clearly
articulated by Smithson, who claimed that an “artist’s treatment of the land
depends on how aware he is of himself as nature.”
31
He also urged artists to
“become conscious of themselves as natural agents.”
32
He characterized his own
artistic interest as that of taking “on the persona of a geologic agent where man
actually becomes part of that process rather than overcoming it.”
33
In this view the
changes to nature and its aesthetic qualities produced by environmental works are of
the same kind as those brought about by natural processes such as earthquakes or
volcanic eruptions. In fact Smithson explicitly compared some of his works—in
particular, one with the self- explanatory title Partially Buried Woodshed (1970) and
the earlier described Asphalt Rundownto the results of natural occurrences such as
the Alaska earthquake and the Icelandic volcanic eruptions.
34
The point is that
although such natural occurrences change nature and alter its aesthetic qualities,
they do not change the kind of thing nature is, and thus, whatever else they yield,
they do not result in aesthetic affronts to nature. If environmental works of art are
also natural occurrences in this sense, they too can avoid being aesthetic affronts.
Concerning this reply, we may initially note that claiming that an environmental
work cannot constitute an affront to nature because it, like nature, is also natural is
comparable to claiming that Duchamp’s mustached Mona Lisa cannot constitute an
affront to Leonardo’s Mona Lisa because it, like Leonardo’s work, is also art. In each
case, even if we accept the claim of a basic similarity of kind, there seems to be
enough difference to make an aesthetic affront possible. Be that as it may, there is
perhaps a deeper problem with this reply: it seems, as is said, to throw out the baby
with the bath water. If we take the comparison between environmental works and
natural occurrences such as earthquakes completely seriously, it becomes difficult to
see any point or purpose in environmental art. As we have seen, some
environmental artists, including Smithson himself, have elaborated the point and
purpose of their art in terms of improvements on nature, of “recycling” “devastated
places,” or of “bringing up” “low profile” landscapes. But viewing environmental
158 IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
works as natural occurrences undercuts this kind of justification. One cannot
consistently hold that these works have the point of improving upon nature and
that they yet have the natural purposelessness of earthquakes and volcanic eruptions.
Of course, one might concede that such works have neither point nor purpose, that
they, like natural occurrences, involve neither improvement nor its lack but only
existence and change. It is reported, for example, that Heizer considers the meaning
and raison d’être of his desert works to be only their “own existence—nothing more
and nothing less”—they have “no significance” other than their “presence.”
35
This
line of thought, however, has its own drawbacks, for it puts environmental art in an
uncomfortable limbo between nature and humanity’s traditional incursions upon
nature. The former, as embodied in natural processes, is characterized by
inevitability; the latter, as embodied in activities such as farming and mining, are
characterized by purposefulness.
36
However, if environmental artists can claim for
themselves neither the inevitability of nature nor the purposefulness of traditional
human incursions, then their art may be more similar to simple vandalism than to
anything else. If so the charge of being an aesthetic affront is not avoided, for the
vandal’s marks and alterations, since they are excusable neither by inevitability nor
by purposefulness, constitute greater aesthetic affronts than any other. Compare
Duchamp’s treatment of the Mona Lisa with that of a vandal who attacks it with a
can of spray paint. Even Smithson once said that he could not accept pointless
graffiti on boulders (although it was all right on subway trains).
37
The last reply I consider attempts to avoid the affront charge by reasserting a
purpose for environmental art. However, this purpose is not to improve upon
nature by recycling it as art. In fact it is not to alter nature’s aesthetic qualities in any
way, but rather only to bring out or to make more evident these qualities. In this
view an environmental work does not change the kind of thing nature is, turning a
natural site into part of an artwork; rather it only “spotlights” the site itself. Thus
the environmental piece is construed as a means of displaying and enhancing
nature’s beauty, and not as an aesthetic affront to nature. Perhaps the genesis of this
conception of environmental art is to be found in the traditional idea of art as a
mirror of nature or in the idea behind some of Smithson’s earlier works which he
called “nonsites.” These works display in a gallery materials such as rocks and gravel
from a natural site and thus call attention to that site without making it a part of the
work. Such gallery-bound nonsites do not change nature, but at most only our
perception of nature, and thus it is difficult to see how they could be aesthetic
affronts to nature. On balance, they are more like providing the Mona Lisa with
proper lighting than like providing it with a mustache.
Some concluding examples
However, once art moves out of the gallery and directly engages natural sites, the
extent to which this reply is relevant is less clear. In fact it seems that whether or not
it holds for any particular environmental work depends on the exact nature of the
work in question. Thus its strength as a reply must be considered on a case-by-case
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 159
basis. Consequently, I conclude by examining some examples for which the reply
might be thought to hold. Perhaps the best known of works sometimes
characterized in this way are some of Christo’s such as Oceanfront Project for Covering
the Cove at Kings Beach (1974) and Wrapped Coast—Little Bay—One Million
Square Feet (1969), each of which involved covering a large area of ocean coastline
with fabric. For example, one critic says that the former was “intimately related to
the landscape in that the natural forms are accentuated by the fabric—in a sense
made more visible, rather than altered or disguised.” She concludes: “Concealment
by a fabric so malleable, supple, and relatively sheer as polypropylene is thus
ultimately revealing.”
38
Similarly, another observer notes that “the texture and color
of the sand was strangely intensified” by Christo’s Wrapped Coast.
39
The claim is
that these environmental works, rather than alter nature’s aesthetic qualities,
“accentuate,” make “more visible,” “reveal,” and “intensify” these qualities.
However, since the sites are nonetheless covered with fabric, it is not clear that this
claim is ultimately convincing.
Somewhat more convincing are similar claims made for the environmental
structures of Michael Singer, such as Lily Pond Ritual Series, First Gate Ritual Series
(1976), and Sangam Ritual Series 4/76 (1976). These works are constructions of
materials such as wooden strips, reeds, jute, and bamboo which Singer describes as
“clues” to the environment by which nature is made visible.
40
They have also been
characterized as “gateways,” “reflectors,” “accents,” and “magnifiers” of the site, and
even as “instrument[s] by which each detail of the area might be signaled, might
register tellingly on its observer.”
41
Such metaphors are somewhat appropriate, for
instead of altering or covering their sites, Singer’s pieces seem only in a sense to frame
them, although the frames are internal, skeleton-like frames rather than traditional
external frames. Nonetheless, framing of any kind is a recognized artistic method for
displaying and enhancing, rather than altering an object’s aesthetic qualities. In a
similar way it might be said that Christo’s Running Fence internally frames the
landscape through which it passes, although in this case perhaps the frame
overwhelms that which is framed.
Another environmental artist comparable to Singer is Alan Sonfist, who art critic
Grace Glueck describes as “Nature’s boy.”
42
Like Singer, Sonfist claims he is “not
trying to alter” nature, but “trying to present it”; he wants to create art which makes
nature “visible” and “directs” people “to look at nature.”
43
To this end Sonfist has
developed the idea of “natural phenomena as public monuments.”
44
The idea is
illustrated by works such as Rock Monument of Buffalo (1976–78). In this piece
rocks from the local region are positioned such that the work “makes clear in one
experience the geology of the entire area.”
45
Concerning the issue of presenting
rather than altering nature, it is useful to compare Sonfist’s piece with works such as
Heizer’s Elevated, Surface, Depressed (1981), a monument in which rocks are
mounted on aluminum slabs and positioned according to geometrical rather than
geological considerations. By contrast with works such as Heizer’s, in Sonfist’s, as
one critic puts it: “Nature asserts itself as itself.”
46
160 IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
As this remark suggests, Sonfist takes the concept of environmental art that does
not alter, but only displays, nature’s aesthetic qualities one step further—to the point
of nature itself as art. He claims: “I think nature is art and people have to realize
this” and compares himself to Duchamp, saying: “He claimed man-made objects as
works of art—I claim natural phenomena.”
47
The idea of displaying nature as art is
not unique to Sonfist. Consider environmental pieces such as Morris’ Steam Piece
(1967–73), in which vents in a 25 foot site filled the area with steam, or Hans
Haack’s work with the self-explanatory title, Spray of Ithaca Falls Freezing and
Melting on Rope (1969). Each of these works does little more than present “natural
phenomena” in a natural site; the aesthetic qualities displayed are those of nature
itself. The basic idea is given more extensive treatment by Sonfist in works such as
Time Landscape (1965–78). This work consists of a network of sites throughout
New York City, where areas of land have been restored to the way they might have
appeared before urbanization. Depending upon the particular site, the land has been
replanted with different varieties of trees, shrubs, and grasses in an attempt to
recreate pre-colonial landscapes. As one critic says: “Time Landscape presents nature
in an unadulterated, unmodified state as the fundamental content of the work.”
48
Environmental works such as Sonfist’s Time Landscape and Morris’ and Haack’s
pieces do little if anything to alter nature’s aesthetic qualities, and consequently they
avoid constituting aesthetic affronts on these grounds. Such works, therefore, are the
only clear cases of environmental pieces that are not aesthetic affronts to nature as
that notion is discussed in this chapter. However, they yet present two interrelated
problems. First, they suggest the possibility of another kind of aesthetic affront—the
affront implicit in the idea that for the aesthetic interest and merit of nature to be
recognized it must first be considered a work of art. Second, they pose a general
question—the question of why such natural environmental pieces should be
considered works of art in the first place. In response to these problems, I suggest,
concerning the second, that there are adequate grounds for considering these
natural pieces not to be works of art. And, concerning the first, if they are not so
considered, they do not constitute cases of intimate relationships between art and
nature and, therefore, do not raise the possibility of offering significant aesthetic
affronts to nature. If this is the case, we are, by these examples of environmental art,
re-directed to the issues addressed in the first part of this volume: the important
questions of how to recognize and appropriately appreciate nature’s own aesthetic
interest and merit.
49
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 161
Illustration 4 Time Landscape, by Alan Sonfist (1965–78), New York City (Courtesy of Alan
Sonfist).
Notes
1 Elizabeth C.Baker, “Artworks on the Land,” Art in America, 1976, vol. 64, pp. 92–6;
reprinted in Alan Sonfist (ed.) Art in the Land: A Critical Anthology of Environmental Art,
New York, Dutton, 1983, p. 75.
2 See Alfred Frankenstein, “Christo’s ‘Fence’: Beauty or Betrayal?Art in America, 1976,
vol. 64, pp. 58–61.
3 See “Compromise Proposed in Christo Island-Wrap,” New York Times, March 20,
1983, p. 54.
4 Peter Humphrey, “The Ethics of Earthworks,” Environmental Ethics, 1985, vol. 7, p.
21. I am grateful to Humphrey’s essay for a number of insightful suggestions.
5 Newton Harrison, paraphrased in Michael Aupling, “Earth Art: A Study in Ecological
Politics,” in Sonfist, op cit., p. 103.
6 Donald Crawford, “Nature and Art: Some Dialectical Relationships,” Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1983, vol. 42, p. 57.
7 Ibid., p. 56.
8 Humphrey, op. cit., p. 8.
162 IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
9 Humphrey, ibid., p. 8., for example, motivates his ethical inquiry into earthworks by
means of a somewhat similar point:
…an earthwork is ethical if and only if what it does to the environment
is ethical. This requires us to look at the earthwork as a mark and not
only as art. In seeing earthworks in this way, the implication is that
earthworks should be ethically judged by the same standard…that all
other such marks are judged by-marks like strip mines, dams, and
golden arches.
10 Alan Gussow, A Sense of Place: Artists and the American Land, San Francisco, Friends
of the Earth, 1972, quoted in Robert Smithson, “Frederick Law Olmstead and the
Dialectical Landscape,” Artforum, 1973, vol. 11, pp. 62–8; reprinted in Nancy Holt
(ed.) The Writings of Robert Smithson: Essays with Illustrations, New York, New York
University Press, 1979, p. 122.
11 Robert Smithson, “A Sedimentation of the Mind: Earth Projects,” Artforum, 1968,
vol. 7, pp. 44–50; reprinted in Holt, op. cit. p. 83.
12 Michael Heizer, quoted in John Gruen, “Michael Heizer: ‘You might say I’m in the
construction business,’” ARTnews, 1977, vol, 76, p. 98.
13 For a description of one such proposal and an illustration, see Robert Smithson,
“Untitled, 1972” and “Proposal, 1972,” in Holt, op. cit., pp. 220–1. For a useful
discussion, see Aupling, op. cit., pp. 92–104.
14 Concerning different kinds of artworks, see Kendall Walton, “Categories of Art,”
Philosophical Review, 1970, vol. 79, pp. 334–67; concerning artworks and non-art
artifacts, see Mark Sagoff, “The Aesthetic Status of Forgeries,” Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism, 1976, vol. 35, pp. 169–80; concerning artifacts and non-artifacts, see
my “Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Objectivity,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 1981, vol. 40, pp. 15–27 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 5).
15 Baker, op. cit. p. 74.
16 Salvador Dali,Why They Attack the Mona Lisa, ARTnews, 1963, vol. 62, pp. 36,
63–4; reprinted in Barbaralee Diamonstein (ed.) The Art World: A Seventy-Five-Year
Treasury of ARTnews, New York, ARTnews Books, 1977, p. 326.
17 Ibid., p. 326.
18 Heizer, quoted in Michael Heizer, Dennis Oppenheim and Robert Smithson,
“Discussions with Heizer, Oppenheim, Smithson,” Avalanche, 1970 vol. 1, pp. 48–
70; reprinted in Holt, op. cit, p. 171.
19 Robert Smithson, quoted in Lawrence Alloway,Robert Smithsons Development,
Artforum, 1972, vol. 11, pp. 52–61; reprinted in Sonfist, op. cit., p. 131.
20 Pablo Picasso, quoted in Andre Malraux, Picasso’s Mask, trans. June Guicharnaud and
Jacques Guicharnaud, New York, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1976, pp. 55; the
remark is related to environmental art in Mark Rosenthal, “Some Attitudes of Earth
Art: From Competition to Adoration,” in Sonfist, op. cit., pp. 60–72.
21 Heizer, “Discussions with Heizer, Oppenheim, Smithson,” op. cit., p. 178.
22 Some of these replies are suggested by Humphrey, op. cit., pp. 11–18, and Crawford,
op. cit., pp. 50–1 and pp. 55–6.
23 Baker, op. cit. p. 80.
24 Christo, quoted in Crawford, op. cit., p. 56.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 163
25 Baker, op cit., p. 75.
26 Smithson, “Frederick Law Olmstead and the Dialectical Landscape,” op. cit., p. 124.
27 Robert Smithson, “Conversation in Salt Lake City: Interview with Gianni Pettena,”
Domus, 1972, no. 516, pp. 53–6; reprinted in Holt, op. cit., p. 186.
28 See my “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–75 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4).
29 See my “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,Environmental Ethics, 1984, vol. 6, pp. 5–34
(reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6).
30 Smithson, quoted in Heizer, Oppenheim and Smithson, “Discussions with Heizer,
Oppenheim, Smithson,” op. cit., p. 172.
31 Smithson, “Frederick Law Olmstead and the Dialectical Landscape,” op. cit., p. 123.
32 Smithson, “Untitled, 1972,” op. cit., p. 220.
33 Smithson, “Conversation in Salt Lake City,” op. cit., p. 187.
34 Robert Smithson, “Entropy Made Visible: Interview with Alison Sky,” On Site, 1973,
vol. 4, pp. 26–31; reprinted in Holt, op. cit., pp. 192–4
35 Gruen, op. cit. p. 97.
36 See my “On Appreciating Agricultural Landscapes,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 1985, vol. 43, pp. 301–12 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 12).
37 Smithson, “Frederick Law Olmstead and the Dialectical Landscape,” op. cit., p.127.
38 Sally Yard, Christo Oceanfront, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1975, p. 19.
39 Alan McCullogh, “Letter from Australia,” Art International, 1970, vol. 14, p. 71;
quoted in Carol Hall, “Environmental Artists: Sources and Directions,” in Sonfist, op.
cit., p. 16.
40 Michael Singer, quoted in Kate Linker, “Michael Singer: A Position In, and On,
Nature,” Arts, 1977 vol. 52, pp. 102–4; reprinted in Sonfist, op, cit., p. 188.
41 Linker, op. cit., pp. 183–4.
42 Grace Glueck, “Art Notes: Auction Where the Action Is,” New York Times, November
15, 1970, p. D26.
43 Alan Sonfist, quoted in ibid., p. D26.
44 Alan Sonfist, Natural Phenomena as Public Monuments, Purchase, New York,
Neuberger Museum, 1978.
45 Alan Sonfist, Rock Monument of Buffalo, Buffalo, New York, Albright-Knox Art
Gallery, 1979; quoted in Jonathan Carpenter,Alan Sonfists Public Sculptures, in
Sonfist, op. cit., p. 146.
46 Carpenter, op. cit., p. 151.
47 Sonfist, quoted in Glueck, op. cit., p. D26.
48 Rosenthal, op. cit., p. 68. Rosenthal’s article provides a useful comparison of Sonfist’s
Time Landscape and Smithson’s Spiral Jetty.
49 A shorter version of this chapter was presented as part of a symposium on interactions
between art and nature at the Xth International Congress for Aesthetics in August,
1984, and appears in the proceedings of that congress. I thank my co-symposiests,
Donald Crawford and Dabney Townsend, for helpful comments.
164 IS ENVIRONMENTAL ART AN AESTHETIC AFFRONT TO NATURE?
11
THE AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF
JAPANESE GARDENS
The dialectical nature of Japanese gardens
In this chapter I focus on another case of an intimate relationship between nature
and art, that which takes place in gardens. As my example, I consider oriental
gardens, in particular Japanese gardens. There are, however, different kinds of
Japanese gardens with different features, styles, and designs that, accordingly, present
different issues concerning aesthetic appreciation. Here I focus only on certain types
of Japanese gardens and only on one specific aesthetic issue. The particular types of
gardens are often called tea and stroll gardens. Such gardens characteristically
possess the kinds of features, styles, and designs that most clearly pose the aesthetic
issue in question.
1
The specific aesthetic issue concerning Japanese gardens can be seen as somewhat
of a paradox. I introduce it by reference to my own experience: I find Japanese
gardens of the relevant kind very easy to aesthetically appreciate. In them I find
myself effortlessly slipping into a state of calm and serene contemplation, marked by
feelings of quiet joy and well-being. This in itself is not paradoxical nor even worthy
of remark. Japanese gardens are well known, widely acclaimed, and by most
accounts explicitly designed for precisely this feature; they typically induce this kind
of aesthetic experience. What is remarkable and yields a touch of paradox is that
Japanese gardens are in many ways exactly the kind of thing that I, and I think
many others, frequently find somewhat difficult to aesthetically appreciate. Let me
explain.
In general I, and I assume others, find both pristine nature and pure art relatively
easy to aesthetically appreciate. Neither typically causes me appreciative difficulty
nor confusion. The relevance of this to Japanese gardens is that such gardens,
although also very easy to appreciate, are, of course, neither pristine nature nor pure
art. Rather they are classic examples of things “between” art and nature, paradigm
cases of the meeting and the mixing of the artificial and the natural. However, such
cases of interaction between artifact and nature are frequently found to be
somewhat difficult to aesthetically appreciate. This is generally true of what might
be called nonartistic cases. For example, many individuals have some aesthetic
difficulty appreciating farming, mining, urban sprawl, and other kinds of human
intrusions into natural landscapes.
2
Sometimes such intrusions are simply regarded
as eyesores, but in many cases, and particularly if the resultant landscapes are not
especially unpleasant, the difficulty in appreciation is more a matter of something
like aesthetic confusion or aesthetic uneasiness. Moreover, many people have similar
aesthetic difficulty appreciating other smaller scale intermixing of the artificial and
natural, such as, for example, graffiti on rocks, initials carved in trees, artificially
designed plants and animals, and even tattoos. And, again, if the particular instances
are not especially unpleasant to the eye, the aesthetic difficulty is more a matter of
confusion than condemnation.
More to the point, however, are instances of the meeting and mixing of art and
nature that are more clearly artistic, for a Japanese garden is anything but a simple
human intrusion into a natural landscape. We might think that artistic cases pose
fewer problems for aesthetic appreciation, but this is not necessarily so. In an essay
titled “Nature and Art: Some Dialectical Relationships,” Donald Crawford
distinguishes between traditional harmonious relationships between art and nature
and what he calls dialectical relationships.
3
In harmonious relationships art and
nature serve as models for one another and in a sense reinforce one another, but do
not interact with one another. By contrast, in dialectical relationships art and nature
are two distinct and frequently conflicting elements whose “interaction is a
determining factor in the constitution of the object of appreciation.”
4
Crawford
suggests that certain kinds of environmental artworks exemplify such dialectical
relationships between art and nature, in particular some of the kinds of works
discussed in the previous chapter, such as the earthworks of Robert Smithson and
the placement pieces of Christo. As noted, many of such environmental artworks are
controversial. Crawford notes that they have been attacked on environmental and
ethical grounds, and that they pose appreciative problems as well. And, as with the
nonartistic cases, the appreciative difficulty seems to involve uneasiness and
confusion rather than simply a negative reaction. Thus, environmental artworks
that involve Crawford’s dialectical relationship between art and nature clearly
exemplify what may be called the problem of difficult aesthetic appreciation.
5
Gardens and especially Japanese gardens are not, of course, earthworks or
placement pieces. Do gardens exemplify dialectical relationships between art and
nature or rather just the more traditional harmonious relationships? As noted,
Crawford characterizes harmonious relationships as ones in which art and nature
serve as models for one another. Within the Western gardening tradition there are
clear examples of such harmonious relationships. On the one hand, in “French-
style” formal gardens, such as some of those at Versailles, harmonious relationships
are achieved by art serving as a model for nature. On the other hand, in “English-
style” natural gardens, exemplified by what are sometimes called picturesque or
landscape gardens, harmonious relationships are achieved by the opposite means, by
nature serving as a model for art.
6
However, in the Western tradition there is also
another kind of garden, the topiary garden. In such cases, as in environmental
artworks, clear dialectical relationships exist between art and nature. In topiary
gardens, nature and art are distinct and in a sense conflicting forces and the
166 THE AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF JAPANESE GARDENS
interaction between the natural and the artificial is constitutive of the object of
aesthetic appreciation. And, again as with environmental artworks, topiary gardens
are difficult and confusing objects of aesthetic appreciation.
What about Japanese gardens? Do they, like earthworks, placement pieces, and
topiary gardens and unlike French formal gardens and English natural gardens,
involve dialectical relationships between art and nature? A number of considerations
suggest this. For instance, Japanese gardens sometimes include topiary. However, as
Josiah Conder notes in his classic study of the subject, “the clipping and carving of
trees and bushes into shapes such as mountains, water-falls, boats, and buildings” is
“kept within the bounds of moderation.
7
In fact, topiary is increasingly
unparadigmatic of Japanese gardens. Nonetheless, dialectical interaction between
the natural and the artificial is yet manifest in what Conder calls “a sort of surgical
treatment.”
8
This treatment, described by another author as the necessity for
“pruning, clipping, shearing, pinching or plucking,” is an essential part of any
Japanese garden.
9
One Japanese authority even notes that if one asks “a Japanese
gardener the secret of gardening,…he will hold up his pruning shears.”
10
Thus,
although they do not serve the representational ends of topiary gardens, the shrubs
and trees of Japanese gardens are yet highly artifactualized. And it is not a matter of
just a little casual pruning. The vegetation of the Japanese garden is carefully formed
and shaped to realize distinctive styles such as in the “ball treatment” and the
“fraying treatment.”
11
Moreover, the Japanese gardener frequently utilizes complex
systems of bending, binding, bracing, and weighting to achieve certain desired
effects. Occasionally he or she will even use chemical retardants or thin entire trees
by hand—one needle at a time!
12
Moreover, dialectical interaction between the natural and the artificial in Japanese
gardens is evident not only in the vegetation, but in the entire landscapes of such
gardens. The landscapes themselves are highly artifactualized. For example, Conder
notes that in designing the kind of garden known as a hill garden “the hillocks
should first be arranged, and then the water channels; the principal rocks and stones
are next distributed, and lastly the trees and shrubs are planted.”
13
And, as with the
vegetation, there are distinctive styles and means of forming, shaping, and
positioning hills, rocks and stones, and water. The control of water is especially
striking. A popular account of Japanese gardens from the turn of the century notes
that Westerners “cannot understand how water, which, like the wind, goes where it
wills, has had its bed of white stones built for it, and has been trained, as pet dogs
are, to run and tumble and lie down at the will of the master.”
14
The most obvious way in which Japanese gardens manifest dialectical interaction
between the natural and the artificial, however, is by, as with many environmental
artworks, the careful placement of the artificial within the context of the natural. An
essential aspect of the landscape of the Japanese garden is a scattering of artifacts
throughout them. These include the paradigmatic lanterns, bridges, and teahouses,
as well as pagodas, shrines, wells, arbors, and occasional statuary. One Western
introduction to the appreciation of Japanese gardens notes that a superficial contact
might unfortunately leave the impression of “a quaint, tinkling medley of little
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 167
arched bridges, carp ponds, paper lanterns, oddly pruned trees, bamboo blinds,
grotesquely jutting rocks, and perhaps a dainty geisha.”
15
The appreciative paradox of Japanese gardens
It is now possible to succinctly state what might be called the appreciative paradox of
Japanese gardens. It is this: on the one hand, such gardens lend themselves to easy
aesthetic appreciation not unlike each of pure art and pristine nature. But, on the
other hand, they are neither pure art nor pristine nature, and moreover they are not
even examples of harmonious relationships between art and nature, such as the
French formal garden and the English natural garden. Rather, they, like earthworks,
placement pieces, and topiary gardens, involve dialectical relationships between the
natural and the artificial, and thus they should be similarly difficult and confusing
objects of aesthetic appreciation. Consequently, the question posed by Japanese
gardens is: why are they not difficult to aesthetically appreciate? Or, to put it another
way: how do they manage to so successfully and completely solve the appreciative
problem of difficult aesthetic appreciation?
16
Addressing these questions requires pursuing beyond the intuitive level the
theoretical question of why objects that involve dialectical relationships between art
and nature pose the problem of difficult appreciation. First, it should be clear that
this is not simply because dialectical relationships involve conflicting forces. When
conflicting forces are present either in pure art or in pristine nature, they typically
give the aesthetic object a dynamic and dramatic quality that makes it an easy and
natural focus of appreciation. Rather, I suspect the answer lies not in the conflict
between the natural and the artificial, but simply in the differences in their
respective natures. I suggest that because of their different natures, each of the
natural and the artificial lends itself to somewhat different kinds of appreciation.
Moreover, given that in dialectical relationships, as Crawford puts it, “both forces
retain their identity as separately identifiable components of the completed work,”
the resultant object of appreciation is difficult to appreciate.
17
Aesthetic appreciation
is difficult because both of the natural and the artificial are independently present,
each requires different kinds of appreciation, and thus together they force the
appreciator to perform various kinds of appreciative gymnastics. For example, the
appreciator may attempt to force either the natural or the artificial component into
the appreciative mode of the other or may attempt to achieve some blend of the two
kinds of appreciation. However, such appreciative gymnastics are difficult and
marked by aesthetic uneasiness and confusion.
What then is the difference between the kinds of appreciation to which the
natural and the artificial each lends itself? Much of what is said in Part I of this
volume, especially in Chapters 6 and 7, is directly relevant to answering this
question. Here I suggest a point similar to that noted there by following up some
remarks by Francis Coleman. In delineating what he calls the critical point of view,
Coleman opines:
168 THE AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF JAPANESE GARDENS
Suppose we are in the country. We might ask someone who is with us to look
at the hills and valleys aesthetically, but never critically… Only if man’s
efforts are mingled with the products of nature do we speak of criticism or
judging or judges…the critic supposes that the object could have been
otherwise and that it is as it is because someone designed it to be so. The
design rests upon the artist’s judgment, and his judgment can be good or bad,
faulty or sure.
18
If Coleman is correct about these differences between appreciating nature and
appreciating art, then a significant part of the mode of appreciation appropriate for
the artificial is some dimension of critical judgment. Critical judgment is
appropriate because the object of appreciation, since it is seen as designed, is seen as
something that could have been otherwise. On the other hand, the natural is not
seen as designed by an artist whose judgment might have been less than perfect, and
thus it is not seen as something that, in the relevant sense, could have been
otherwise. Consequently, the mode of aesthetic appreciation appropriate for the
natural takes the aesthetic object as given and thus to be, as it were, beyond
judgment. If this is correct, then one aspect of the appreciative difficulty involved in
appreciating objects constituted by dialectical relationships between the artificial and
the natural is the question of the proper role, if any, of critical judgment in such
appreciation. It is the appreciative problem of exactly how and to what extent to
judge.
19
If the problem of the proper role of critical judgment is, therefore, part of the
difficulty in appreciating objects such as earthwork, placement pieces, and topiary
gardens, then the question about Japanese gardens can be put as the question of how
they manage to so successfully solve or evade this appreciative problem. Of course,
objects of appreciation constituted by dialectical relationships between art and
nature may solve the problem in many different ways. However, two general lines of
approach suggest themselves. They are by following either the lead of art or the lead
of nature. Consider cases such as those discussed in Chapter 10: to the extent that
they successfully deal with the problem, most well-known environmental artworks,
such as those by Smithson and Christo, do so by following the lead of art in the
sense of making the artificial component of the work so dramatic that there is little
doubt about the appropriateness of critical judgment. On the other hand, many
lesser-known environmental works, such as some by Michael Singer and Alan
Sonfist, may follow the lead of nature in the sense of making the artificial
component so unobtrusive that, as in the case of pristine nature, the tendency to
judge does not arise.
20
I suggest that Japanese gardens successfully solve the problem
also by following the lead of nature rather than that of art. However, they do so not
by means of making the artificial unobtrusive, but rather by making the natural
appear in such a way that the tendency to judge is again averted. In short, Japanese
gardens solve the problem of the role of critical judgment by rising above judgment
in a way similar to the way nature itself does. Let me explain.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 169
First, consider the aesthetic appreciation of nature. The idea suggested by
Coleman’s remarks is that in such appreciation we are not confronted by the
problem of the proper role of critical judgment because nature rises above such
judgment in virtue of appearing as something that could not have been otherwise.
This, however, is not to say that any particular bit of nature appears as if it could
not have turned out different from how it in fact has. Rather, it is to say that nature
in general has a certain kind of look, a look of inevitability—indeed, what we often
call a “natural” look. I suggest that Japanese gardens solve the problem of judgment
because they, in a way similar to nature, are by and large seen as having this kind of
look of natural inevitability. This is a common theme in the literature. For example,
even after becoming completely acquainted with the design and construction of
Japanese gardens, one commentator describes her reaction as involving the following
sentiments:
What luck, what wonderful luck, these people have! They do not need to
make their gardens: Nature has done it for them. It is not that they are so
artistic in composing, but only so wise in not changing a single stone or tree
from the place in which it was found. And so one feels that the garden had to
be arranged as it was,…that the lake and the trickling stream and the cascade
must have been set there by the Divine Landscape Gardener Himself, and
that the beautiful old trees had grown to that precision of shape and loveliness
by the help of Nature alone.
21
As she notes, the general impression is that the garden had to be as it is, that is, that
it could not have been otherwise. It is thus beyond critical judgment. Moreover,
who, after all, would attempt to judge the “Divine Landscape Gardener Himself”?
The fact that Japanese gardens look as if they could not have been otherwise does
not mean, however, that they look just like nature. This is because, first, in many
ways they do not in fact look just like nature. And, second, because if they did, they
would not exemplify dialectical relationships between art and nature, but rather
simply a kind of harmonious relationship such as, for example, the English natural
garden. The English natural garden is more or less a copy of nature and often looks
if not just like then at least quite a lot like nature. Rather the point is that a certain
kind of looka look of natural inevitabilityis achieved in Japanese gardens and
that in the realization of this kind of look such gardens solve the problem of
judgment. Relevant to understanding this solution is not only seeing that Japanese
gardens have this look but also knowing how it is achieved. I suggest that the key to
achieving the relevant kind of look is a kind of idealization aimed at isolating and
revealing the essential. In short, the solution to the problem of judgment lies in the
fact that Japanese gardens achieve a look of inevitability not by the creation of a
simple copy of nature, but rather by the creation of an idealization of nature that
attempts to uncover what are taken to be its essential qualities. The guidebook for
the well-known Japanese garden in Portland, USA, puts this point simply by saying
that the garden is “intended to demonstrate the essence of nature.”
22
Similarly, one
170 THE AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF JAPANESE GARDENS
Japanese authority characterizes the Japanese garden as “the continuous endeavor to
extract the essence of a stone, a tree, a view” that results in “a celebration of the
elementals” and “a glimpse of nature bare.”
23
Following Millay, we might say that in
the Japanese garden, we, like Euclid, “look on Beauty bare,” although the beauty
exhibits a natural rather than a geometric facet.
24
If, in light of the idea of focusing on the essence of nature, we reconsider the ways
in which Japanese gardens are artifactualized, the artificial side of the dialectical
Illustration 5 Willow in the Japanese garden, Portland.
relationship between art and nature can be seen in a new light. The
artifactualization, although a separate identifiable aspect of the garden, is yet
completely subservient to the aim of revealing the essence of nature. Therefore, the
artifactualization in Japanese gardens, instead of prompting critical judgment as it
seemingly does in many environmental artworks, rather contributes to seeing the
garden as something that could not have been otherwise and is thus beyond critical
judgment. Consider again the pruning and shaping of vegetation. This should be
seen as aimed at what Conder calls “natural prototypes,” that is, ideal forms of, for
example, the pine, the maple, and the willow, which forms display the essential
qualities of the species.
25
As one authority says: the “Japanese gardener can
emphasize these qualities, eliminate distracting elements, simplify [a plant’s] lines,
and thus reveal its true nature to the world.
26
Another commentator puts the point
this way: “There is pruning and placing but this results in the re vealing of a line
which nature itself created and then obscured in its own plenitude.”
27
He adds:
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 171
…this pruning…allows a more natural and, at the same time, more ideal
beauty to emerge… [that] is there from the first. It is not created, it is merely
allowed to express itself in a louder voice and in plainer terms.
28
In a similar fashion, the presence of artifacts within the landscape also aims at the
accentuation of nature. First, the artifacts are themselves designed and placed, as one
source says, “so as to look as accidental and natural as the landscape itself.”
29
Second,
they by subtle contrast, as another authority stresses, “create within the viewer that
feeling of nature heightened which is the salient quality of the Japanese garden.”
30
Conclusion
Thus, in conclusion, I propose the following account of how the Japanese garden,
although indeed exemplifying a dialectical relationship between the artificial and the
natural, yet deals so successfully with the problem of difficult and confusing
aesthetic appreciation that frequently accompanies such relationships: it does so by
following the lead of nature in the sense of making the artificial subservient to the
natural. It employs the artificial in the creation of an idealized version of nature that
emphasizes the essential. It thereby achieves an appearance of inevitability—the look
of something that could not have been otherwise—and in achieving this look, it, as
pristine nature itself, rises above critical judgment. Therefore, to the extent that the
problem of difficult aesthetic appreciation is correctly analyzed as the problem of the
proper role of critical judgment in such appreciation, the Japanese garden does not
result in difficult and confusing aesthetic appreciation because concerning it the
question of critical judgment does not arise. And thus, since it is reasonably pleasant
in other ways, the Japanese garden lends itself easily to aesthetic appreciation in
spite of involving dialectical interaction between art and nature.
In addition, I note that this account also explains the nature of the aesthetic
experience typical of the Japanese garden. As described at the outset, when I
experience such a garden I find myself slipping without difficulty into a calm, serene
contemplative state, marked by feelings of well-being. Such an aesthetic experience
is exactly what one would expect to envelop an appreciator who is in a reasonably
pleasant environment that seems as if it could not have been other than it is;
moreover, it is the mode of aesthetic experience that quite naturally follows the
suspension of critical judgment. However, in spite of the initial plausibility of this
account, it may yet be objected that we simply do not suspend judgment, that as a
matter of fact we frequently make critical aesthetic judgments of Japanese gardens. I
can only respond to this objection by again appealing to my own experience, noting
that my aesthetic appreciation of Japanese gardens does not characteristically involve
critical judgments. However, perhaps I am aesthetically perverted by my own theory.
Thus, I suggest you find a Japanese garden and see for yourself.
31
172 THE AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF JAPANESE GARDENS
Notes
1 A classic Western introduction to the different kinds of Japanese gardens and their
different features, styles, and designs is Josiah Conder, Landscape Gardening in Japan
[1912], New York, Dover, 1964. The oldest source on these matters appears to be an
eleventh-century manuscript, Memoranda on Garden Making. It is attributed to a
Fujiwara nobleman, Tachibana-no-Toshitsuna, and now published as Sakuteiki: The
Book of Garden, trans. Shigemaru Shimoyama, Tokyo, Town and City Planners, Inc.,
1985.
2 I discuss some of the difficulties involved in appreciating farmland in “On Appreciating
Agricultural Landscapes,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1985, vol. 43, pp.
301–12 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 12).
3 Donald Crawford, “Nature and Art: Some Dialectical Relationships,” Journal of
Aesthetic and Art Criticism, 1983, vol. 42, pp. 49–58.
4 Ibid., p. 49.
5 I discuss closely related issues in “Is Environmental Art an Aesthetic Affront to
Nature?,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1986, vol. 16, pp. 635–50 (reproduced in
this volume, Chapter 10).
6 For philosophically-informed discussion of these distinctions, as well as some of the
different aspects of Japanese gardens, see Mara Miller, The Garden as an Art, Albany,
SUNY Press, 1993, especially Chapter 1, “Definitions, Examples, and Paradigms.”
Similarly pertinent to these issues as well as to those concerning environmental art are
Stephanie Ross, “Gardens, Earthworks, and Environmental Art,” in Salim Kemal and
Ivan Gaskell (eds) Landscape, Natural Beauty, and the Arts, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1993, pp. 158–82; and Thomas Leddy, “Gardens in an Expanded
Field,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1988, vol. 28, pp. 327–40.
7 Conder, op. cit., p. 7.
8 Ibid., p. 108.
9David H.Engel, Japanese Gardens for Today, Tokyo, Charles Tuttle, 1959, p. 46.
10 Teiji Ito, The Japanese Garden: An Approach to Nature, trans. Donald Richie, New
Haven, Yale, 1972, p. 140.
11 Conder, op. cit., p. 109.
12 Mitchell Bring and Josse Wayembergh, Japanese Gardens: Design and Meaning, New
York, McGraw-Hill, 1981, p. 203.
13 Conder, op. cit., p. 132.
14 Mrs. Basil Taylor [Harriet Osgood], Japanese Gardens, New York, Dodd, Mead &
Co., 1912, p. 7.
15 Engel, op. cit., p. 5.
16 It could be argued that what I call the appreciative paradox of Japanese gardens would
not arise (and thus would not require solution) within the framework of Japanese
aesthetic appreciation, for such appreciation presupposes a unity of man and nature, of
the artificial and the natural, and not the separation of the two that characterizes
Western aesthetic appreciation. If so, the paradox is perhaps an interesting example of
a quandary generated at least in part by attempting “cross-cultural” aesthetic
appreciation. For an excellent short account of how Japanese aesthetics presupposes a
“unity and co-identity between man and nature,” see Yuriko Saito, “The Japanese
Appreciation of Nature,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 1985, vol. 25, pp. 239–51. Yet,
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 173
in other essays Saito herself expresses some doubt about the extent to which Japanese
gardens exemplify an harmonious unity of man and nature; see Yuriko Saito, “The
Japanese Love of Nature: A Paradox,” Landscape, 1992, vol. 31, pp. 1–8 and especially
“Japanese Gardens: The Art of Improving Nature,” Chanoyu Quarterly: Tea and the Arts
of Japan, 1996, no. 83, pp. 41–61.
17 Crawford, op. cit., p. 57.
18 Francis J.Coleman, “What Is the Aesthetic Point of View?,” in Francis J.Coleman
(ed.) Contemporary Studies in Aesthetics, New York, McGraw-Hill, 1968, p. 7.
19 I discuss these issues in more detail in “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,” Environmental
Ethics, 1984, vol. 6, pp. 5–34 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 6) and in
“Appreciating Art and Appreciating Nature,” in Kemal and Gaskell, op. cit., pp. 199–
227 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 7).
20 For a good introduction to environmental art, and especially to somewhat lesserknown
artists, such as Sonfist and Singer, see Alan Sonfist (ed.) Art in the Land: A Critical
Anthology of Environmental Art, New York, Dutton, 1983. Ross, op. cit., provides a
useful taxonomy of environmental art, sorting works into seven different categories.
21 Taylor, op. cit., pp. 6–7.
22 [no author given], The Japanese Garden, Portland, Oregon, USA, Portland, The
Japanese Garden Society [no date given], p. 1. The Portland Japanese garden is widely
considered to be one of the most authentic gardens outside of Japan. Moreover, it is
described in the McFadden guidebook, Oriental Gardens in America, as “surely…one
of the most beautiful.” See Dorothy Loa McFadden, Oriental Gardens in America: A
Visitor’s Guide, Los Angeles, Douglas-West, 1976, p. 198.
23 Ito, op. cit., pp. 197, 139.
24 The idea of the Japanese garden revealing the essence of nature has interesting roots. A
noted authority on Japanese art, Donald Keene, relates it to one of the four themes in
terms of which he analyzes Japanese aesthetics. He labels the theme “simplicity” and
traces it to the Zen preoccupation with the “use of the most economical means to obtain
the desired effect.” See Donald Keene, “Japanese Aesthetics,” Philosophy East and West,
1969, vol. 19, pp. 293–306 (the quote in the last sentence is from p. 301). Saito,
“Japanese Gardens”, op. cit., p. 59, likewise relates the idea to Zen Buddhism,
suggesting that by presenting “an idealization of nature” the Japanese garden gives us
“a glimpse of this world as it appears to a Zen-enlightened sensibility.” She also finds a
source in the notion of kowan ni shitagau. Literally meaning “following the request,”
this is the central design principle of the eleventh-century Sakuteiki manuscript, op.
cit. Originally it was a principle of stone placement, recommending that a gardener
follow the request of the mind (essence, true nature) of an initial stone in the
placement of others. However, it was subsequently employed in the placing,
designing, shaping, and pruning of other elements of the garden, in each case
“following the request” indicated by the true nature of the object in question.
25 Conder, op. cit., p. 108.
26 Engel, op. cit., p. 46.
27 Ito, op. cit, p. 197.
28 Ibid., p.140
29 Conder, op. cit., p. 11.
30 Ito, op. cit., p. 187.
31 A version of this chapter was presented at a symposium on Japanese gardens at the
American Philosophical Association Meeting, Portland, Oregon, 1992. I thank my co-
174 THE AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF JAPANESE GARDENS
symposiast, Donald Crawford and Yuriko Saito, as well as others who have
commented on subsequent versions, especially Arnold Berleant, Arlene Kwasniak,
Soili Petajaniemi, and Joni Petruskevich.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 175
176
12
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL
LANDSCAPES
Traditional agricultural landscapes
Writing in the 1800s, William James gave the following description of a newly
established North Carolina farm:
The settler had in every case cut down the more manageable trees, and left
their charred stumps standing. The larger trees he had girdled and killed, in
order that their foliage should not cast a shade. He had then built a log cabin,
plastering its chinks with clay, and had set up a tall zigzag rail fence around the
scene of his havoc, to keep the pigs and cattle out. Finally he had irregularly
planted the intervals between the stumps and trees with Indian corn, which
grew among the chips; and there he dwelt with his wife and babes.
1
James noted that his impression of the farmstead was “one of unmitigated squalor
and characterized the scene as “hideous, a sort of ulcer, without a single element of
artificial grace to make up for the loss of Nature’s beauty.”
2
James’s aesthetic judgments may seem harsh; yet had we stood in his place our
own judgments may have been similar. The farm James had encountered was both
new to the landscape that contained it and unfamiliar to the eye that viewed it. Each
of these factors typically contributes to the nature and the intensity of an aesthetic
reaction. Consequently, when landscapes molded by agriculture are newly created
and unfamiliar, our initial aesthetic reactions to them are frequently as negative as
those recorded by James. Fortunately, however, in the time after James’s encounter
both the landscapes of agriculture and the eyes and minds that appreciated them
developed in ways that made possible a more positive aesthetic experience.
3
By the mid-twentieth century, for instance, the agricultural landscapes of North
America were in general quite different from what they were like in James’s time.
Of course, the exact nature of these more recent agricultural landscapes, and of the
fields, farms, and towns that constituted them, varied greatly depending upon places
and products. However, whether the landscapes were those of the corn, grain, and
dairy farms of the Midwest, the ranches and orchards of the West, or the tobacco,
cotton, and truck farms of the South, Southwest, and East, they had all changed
dramatically from James’s scene of “unmitigated squalor.”
For example, at that time the Midwestern agricultural landscape was one of
orderly and well-tended fields, bordered by fencerows and windbreaks and
punctuated with a wood lot, a rural church, or a country school. Situated at regular
intervals across this landscape were relatively tidy farmsteads, with white two-story
frame houses and red gambrel-roofed barns. There may have been masonry silos,
slat-sided corn cribs, or gable-roofed granaries, and perhaps a chicken house, a
milking parlor, or a hog house. If the scene was somewhat cluttered, it was richly
diverse—a scattering of chickens, a hay-or bail-stack, various livestock, brightly
colored machinery, possibly a windmill, an apple tree, a white picket fence, a dog, a
couple of children.
In addition to fields and farmsteads, such agricultural landscapes also contained
small rural communities. The point where the roadway intersected the railway had
become a main street, dominated by a row of gray and white grain elevators and
lined with the shops that served the surrounding countryside. There would have
been a grocery, a dry goods store, a hardware store, an implement dealer, a
lumberyard, perhaps a creamery, a feed mill, or a remnant blacksmith shop.
These more recent agricultural landscapes were complemented by developments
in the sensitivity of many who viewed them. In our aesthetic appreciation of such
landscapes we could not but be struck by the orderly pattern, the neat geometry of
fields, fencerows, and roadways. However, the most significant focus of appreciation
was the farmstead itself. We had learned to perceive it as a pastoral scene. Typically
it, just as the fields, was orderly and neat, but even if slightly squalid, it yet was
aesthetically rich in appearance and laden with expressive and associative quality.
The sights, smells, and sounds of the farmyard, the colors and contrasts of
buildings, machinery, and plants and animals, the subtle and intriguing details that
permeated the entire scene, all contributed to an appearance of aesthetic diversity
and interest. Moreover, it represented the “storybook” farm of many of our
childhoods, experienced (often vicariously) as the home of happy hospitable “folks”
and “home cooking” and reconstituted in our imagination as the source of both
value in our way of life and wholesome food on our tables.
The perceptual and expressive mix that enhanced our aesthetic appreciation of
the fields and farmsteads also characterized the rural community. The main street,
the storefronts, the row of grain elevators were the charming and picturesque centre
of the agricultural landscape, pleasing to the eye in appearance and to the mind’s eye
in expression. Indeed, at mid-century, one astute observer of the American
landscape discussed such communities under the description “The Almost Perfect
Town.”
4
In short, by the middle of the twentieth century the fields and farms and farm
communities of North America had much of aesthetic interest and merit for anyone
who had the imagination and the inclination to appreciate them. However, if this
time represented an aesthetic “golden age” for the appreciation of agricultural
landscapes, it, like all golden ages, was destined to pass. Agriculture is presently
178 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
undergoing a revolution and the resulting landscapes are again, like James’s North
Carolina farm, both newly created and unfamiliar. In confronting the fields, farms,
and towns that are being produced by these current agricultural developments, we
may find that our aesthetic reactions are more similar to those experienced by James
than to those of our own recent past.
The new agricultural landscapes
The last quarter-century has seen technological, economic, and social changes that
are revolutionizing agriculture and in doing so bringing about dramatic alterations
in the look of the land. The changes are taking place at every level: in breeding and
tending, in growing and harvesting, in storing and transporting, in processing and
handling, in marketing and merchandising. They involve new machinery,
equipment, and buildings on the farm, new crops, chemicals, and fertilizers in the
field, and new packages, products, and tastes on the table. In general they are
accompanied, on the one hand, by the demise of general farming, the decline of the
family farm, and the depopulation of the rural countryside and community; and, on
the other, by the growth of specialized “monoculture,” the development of
mechanized corporate farming, and the birth of “agribusiness.” As a result of such
changes new agricultural landscapes are emerging that not only are radically different
from, but also are rapidly replacing, those we had learned to appreciate.
The exact nature of these new agricultural landscapes is not yet completely clear,
but the outline of the new look is not difficult to perceive. In general it involves
larger scale and greater uniformity. The primary element of agriculture, the field, is
the clearest indicator of these developments. In North America there are now fewer
and larger farms than ever before, and the number and size of farms directly effects
the size and nature of fields. As agricultural geographer J.F.Hart notes, “few farms,
no matter how large they are, have more than eight or ten fields” and “the great
majority…are probably subdivided into four or five.”
5
Larger farms have resulted in
the larger and more uniform fields that are basic to the appearance of the new
agricultural landscapes.
Such fields are not simply a function of farm numbers and size, but of
technology, especially as manifested in modern farm equipment. The diverse and
large-scale machinery of present-day farming makes larger and more uniform fields
both possible and necessary. On the one hand, the utilization by agriculture of
graders, bulldozers, land levellers, and other earth-moving equipment has made
possible “land remodelling” by which the farmer can transform smaller fields broken
up by vegetative and topographical features into vast flat tracts of land. On the
other hand, such tracts are necessary for mechanized farming. Modern planting,
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 179
Illustration 6 A traditional farmstead, Minnesota.
Illustration 7 The new agricultural landscape, Saskatchewan.
cultivating, and harvesting equipment, because of both its size and the subtlety of
the operations it performs, requires large uniform surfaces. Such surfaces necessitate
less frequent turning, maneuvering, and adjusting of complex machinery and
180 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
produce regular, even crops that can be handled mechanically at every stage of
production. Without large uniform fields, there would be limited use for high-speed
tractors, 50-foot cultivators, self-propelled irrigation and spraying systems, and
mechanized harvesters and pickers for every crop.
Modern farms and fields complement not only mechanized farming, but also
monoculture, the production of a single crop to the exclusion of other uses of the
land. Larger farms and more uniform fields are more easily devoted to one crop,
whether wheat or corn, beef or turkeys, and doing so is increasingly looked upon as
an economic necessity. For the farmer it represents a way to streamline his or her
operation and to localize his or her investment of time, energy, and capital. It means
capital investment in a smaller range of expensive equipment and personal
investment in a smaller range of increasingly complex and technical activities.
Moreover, monoculture, when practiced on uniform fields or under the similarly
standardized conditions of large farms and in conjunction with the controlled
utilization of irrigation, fertilizers, food supplements, and pesticides, produces a
uniform crop. Such crops lend themselves not only to mechanized farm equipment,
but also to modern methods of produce handling, processing, merchandising, and
even consuming.
6
The movement to a larger scale and a greater uniformity of farms and fields has
produced in the new agricultural landscapes what landscape critic J.B. Jackson has
described as a “coarseness of detail,” a coarse-grainedness characterized by a lack of
small and subtle aspects.
7
This is initially most evident in the field itself. Not only
have fields become vast flat tracts of land exclusively devoted to a single crop, they
have become devoid of many traditional features of rural landscapes. In the quest
for large uniform farming surfaces, topographical irregularities such as gullies,
washes, sloughs, rises, slopes, and knolls have succumbed to land remodeling. At the
same time features once essential to rural life such as wood lots, windbreaks, ponds,
fences, country schools, rural churches, and outlying farm buildings are
systematically being removed or destroyed. In general such features are themselves
deemed unnecessary and occupy land too valuable to remain idle.
The disappearance of traditional features is well illustrated by the case of fences.
At one time fencing was so essential to farming that prior to the invention of barbed
wire it was thought that the treeless prairies of North America must remain
unoccupied for lack of fencing materials.
8
Today however fences and fencerows are
all but gone from the new agricultural landscapes. Of the Midwest, for example, the
Minnesota Historical Society notes:
Fences are rapidly disappearing from the American farm… Fence uses change
with farm functions. Animals confined to feedlots don’t need field fences, and
fence removal allows larger fields suitable to modern, large-scale machinery.
So the once-common barbed wire along highways is now rare.
9
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 181
The changing nature of the agricultural landscapes is apparent not only in a
countryside devoid of detail, but also in the farmstead itself. In fact frequently it is
apparent in the absence of the farmstead. Geographer Peirce Lewis writes:
It’s no news that the traditional American farm is disappearing. Indeed, in
some parts of the country—much of the West, for example—it is already
gone… Drive across the country and look around. Farmhouses are empty and
falling down, and in the rich cornland of the Midwest a good many have been
bulldozed so they wouldn’t get in the way of the huge expensive machines of
corporate agriculture.
10
Moreover, even when the farmstead has not completely disappeared, it is frequently
totally or partially abandoned. “One harvest of America’s increasing productivity,”
claims the Minnesota Historical Society, “is the abandoned farmstead.”
11
While the totally abandoned farmstead is typically destined for the bulldozer,
those only partially abandoned undergo other changes. In many cases only the
farmhouse is maintained; the traditional outbuildings—the barn, the corn crib, the
chicken house—and the rich detail of the traditional farm—the chickens, the mix
of livestock, the windmill—have all disappeared. If the farmstead has become the
home of a non-farming family, their passing has probably been gradual; however, if
it has become the headquarters for a modern farm, it has probably been more rapid
and dramatic. For example, Hart says of the traditional farmyard barn:
On a modern farm the barn is a relict feature; the hayloft is obsolescent, the
threshing floor is obsolete, and who needs stalls for horses? Of course some
use can be found for the old building, if it is still structurally sound, but as
soon as it starts to deteriorate the best thing to do is to pour kerosene on it
and light a match.
12
Remarking on the modern farm headquarters, another observer notes: “Swept clean
of all the usual farmyard clutter of broken and obsolete equipment, chickens,
haystacks and manure, the area looks much like an industrial plant.”
13
On today’s farmstead the most common feature other than the farmhouse (if
there is a farmhouse) is most likely the long, low-profile steel or aluminum shed. These
prefabricated, warehouse-like buildings are used in a variety of ways depending upon
the nature of the farm: to house and tend stock or poultry, to store various crops, to
shelter and maintain machinery. In the new agricultural landscape such featureless
metal sheds are to the farmstead what the uniform fields and crops are to the
surrounding countryside.
The new developments in agriculture that are evident in fields and farmsteads are
also reflected in the agricultural community. Larger, more mechanized farms mean
fewer people, and the resultant depopulation of the countryside, together with
improved transportation, is having a devastating effect on what was once “the
almost perfect town.” Many small rural communities, like many farmsteads, are
182 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
simply disappearing, becoming the new ghost towns of North America. The
functions they once served are now carried out by what are called “regional centers.”
For example, although Iowa had in 1964 a higher concentration of “real farms” than
any other state, its small towns are now dying.”
14
United States Department of
Agriculture economist Warren Bailey says of them:
These towns represent the unfulfilled dreams of the people who went there.
They are going the same way as the neighborhood grocery. People want to
shop where they have a choice. With air-conditioned cars and good roads,
they choose to do their shopping in the cities. Iowa really doesn’t have room
for more than twelve regional centers.
15
In the cases where certain towns or “regional centers” are surviving, such
communities, due to new farming methods and declining rural population, are
undergoing significant changes. Much of the “main street,” the center of character
and charm in many older communities, is being deserted. The blacksmith shop and
the local creamery are long gone, and now the grocery, the dry goods store, and the
hardware store are following suit. Those services which are still vital, or newly vital,
such as the implement dealer, the chain store, and the fertilizer and pesticide depots,
have moved out to the edge of town. Here rows of massive farm equipment, an
assortment of storage tanks, and again the ubiquitous metal sheds line the highway
strip. Near the vacated main street often only the frame grain elevators remain, and,
if the area is prosperous, they are frequently overshadowed by giant round storage
towers.
The rows of equipment, the storage tanks and towers, the activity on the highway
strip all indicate a rich agricultural region. However, the new agricultural landscapes
are landscapes of a mechanized prosperity, a prosperity almost without people.
Jackson, who coined the phrase “the almost perfect town,” emphasizes some of the
ramifications of this:
It is true we are no longer disturbed by the abandoned one room school or
the crossroads General Merchandise; but how will we take the abandoned,
more or less modern, high school with monster gymnasium? The abandoned
drive-in movie with rows of empty stanchions emerging from the weeds, the
abandoned shopping center? We will see them, not only in North Dakota but
in Texas and Florida and Kansas and elsewhere.”
16
In spite of the fact that the farm land of North Dakota, Texas, Florida, and
Kansas is rich, in fact in part because it is so rich, the traditional rural community,
as the traditional farmstead, is rapidly passing from our agricultural landscapes. As
one observer notes, like the small farm, “small towns in America—at least of the
Norman Rockwell ilk—are…obsolete relics of a different age. There are no more
being built today, and, unless things in America change radically, there never will
be.”
17
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 183
Difficult aesthetic appreciation and novelty
When perceived in light of the rural landscapes of the recent past, the new
agricultural landscapes may initially appear to be aesthetic wastelands. As Lewis
points out: “We can study and admire the landscapes our rural ancestors created, but
the idea of studying, much less admiring, the landscape of modern agribusiness
somehow is repellent.”
18
If it is repellent, this is not surprising. In the new
agricultural landscapes the fields and farmsteads have lost whatever pastoral quality
they once had; the rural community is no longer charming and picturesque. The
whole is indeed characterized by a “coarseness of detail.” In fact the large flat
uniform fields devoid of gullies and knolls, fences and wood lots, and, due to
modern pesticides, even insects and weeds, may, in spite of their great productivity,
strike us as dull or even sterile in appearance. And the impression of barrenness is
reinforced by decaying farmsteads and vacated main streets. Moreover, the signs of
prosperity both on the farm and in the community, such as the low-profile
featureless metal sheds, seemingly add little of aesthetic interest. On the whole, in
comparison with traditional agricultural landscapes, the appearance seems that of a
“blandscape” rather than a landscape, a “flatscape” of dreary and monotonous
sameness.
19
Were James to look upon the new agricultural landscapes, although he
could not describe them as scenes of “unmitigated squalor,” he might think
appropriate the claim that they are “without a single element of artificial grace.”
Moreover, if the appearance of the new agricultural landscapes is a factor in
rendering repellent the idea of admiring them, their associative and expressive
qualities seem doubly so. As noted, the new landscapes are related both to the
decline of general farming and the family farm and to the growth of monoculture
and specialized farming, together with their increasing dependence on
mechanization, irrigation, chemical fertilizers, pesticides, supplements, and the
other necessities of the agricultural revolution. The environmental and social price
that has been and in the future will be paid for this revolution is by no means clear.
Indeed the controversy surrounding this issue is difficult and complex. In spite of
lack of clarity, however, it is not hard to find claims such as: “Nowhere is the misuse
of resources so evident as in the agricultural landscape.”
20
And “more than food
rolls off the agribusiness assembly line—rural refugees, boarded-up businesses,
deserted churches, abandoned towns, broiling urban ghettoes, and dozens of other
tragic social and cultural costs also are products of agribusiness.”
21
These and other
similar charges may be exaggerated, but there can be no doubt that the
environmental and social spinoffs of modern agricultural developments and
practices are frequently undesirable.
The aesthetic ramifications of such spinoffs are found in the expressive qualities
of the new agricultural landscapes. If the family farm and its rural support
community constituted a source of social stability and cultural value in our way of
life, and if large-scale mechanized farming has led to their demise, then the
mechanized equipment and the vast fields, as well as the abandoned farmsteads and
the vacated main streets, express the loss of such stability and value. Similarly, if
184 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
mixed general farming constituted agricultural practice that was relatively sound
from an ecological and environmental point of view, then to the extent that such
practice has been replaced by a resource-consumptive dependence on mechanization
and irrigation and an environmentally hazardous dependence on chemical agents,
we suffer another kind of loss. This is the loss of the vitality, stability, and integrity
of our environment, and it is expressed not only by the uniformity of fields and rural
countryside, but also by the massive machinery, the fuel and chemical storage tanks,
and all the other signs of agricultural prosperity that line the highway strips of
regional centers.
If we do indeed find the idea of admiring the new agricultural landscapes repellent,
this seems a function of both their blandscape appearances and the expressive
qualities we take them to have. Moreover, in light of these factors it may seem that
our hesitancy to admire these landscapes is justified, that they are, as James judged
the newly established North Carolina farm, completely without grace. However, it
must be emphasized that these agricultural landscapes, as the farmstead that James
found so distasteful, are a new creation. Thus, as James’s farm once did, the new
fields, farms, and towns lay somewhat awkwardly on the land, with the unfinished
and ambiguous appearance frequently characteristic of the newly created. Moreover,
we find ourselves in a position similar to that of James: unfamiliar with the new
landscapes and thus with neither eyes nor minds either fully able or willing to
appreciate that upon which we gaze. Consequently, we are inclined to judge the
aesthetic interest and merit of the new landscapes in relation to that which they have
replaced. As James judged his farmstead to have nothing “to make up for the loss of
Nature’s beauty,” so too we may judge the new agricultural landscapes to contain
little of aesthetic value to compensate for the loss of the beauty and character of the
agricultural landscapes of the recent past.
In order to better understand aesthetic judgments such as James’s and our own
judgments about the new agricultural landscapes, it is useful to turn momentarily to
a more familiar area—the aesthetic appreciation of art. Such judgments seemingly
have analogues in the history of art appreciation. Consider the aesthetic reaction of
both the public and many art critics to the famous New York Armory show of
1913. The show first brought to the United States the works of various “modern”
movements such as futurism and cubism. The products of these movements were
judged to be “the most unexplainable and inartistic works,” “the weird output of the
‘Eccentrics,’” and “the disquieting perpetrations of the art criminals.”
22
Duchamp’s
Nude Descending a Staircase (1912) was found to be especially offensive and
baffling, being described as a “so-called picture” that “looks like a collection of
saddle bags.”
23
Concerning this case, as with many similar cases in the history of art
appreciation, it is now clear that these works were condemned at least in part
because of the novelty of these movements and the unfamiliarity of the spectators
with their works. The spectators were thus inclined to judge these works in terms of
older appreciative models. The cubist works in particular, being early representatives
of that movement, were explicitly compared with “a number of beautiful examples
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 185
by sane and serious men, whose art only shines the more by its close proximity to
this vaudevillian collection.”
24
Concerning cases such as the futurist and cubist works at the Armory show, it
may be said that the public and the critics failed to appreciate these works on their
own terms. However, this was undoubtedly difficult to do. For example, in part
because cubism was a relatively new movement, some of the works in question, such
as Duchamp’s Nude, have a somewhat ambiguous, perhaps not-quite-cubist
appearance. In many cases a movement in art must mature in order to fully achieve
its distinctive style, yield its most finished and characteristic works, and thereby
make manifest how to appreciate any of its works on their own terms. Until a
movement reaches such a level of development, it is not clear exactly what some of
its works are, and thus it is difficult to appreciate them for what they are rather than
as something else. In such cases the appropriate appreciative models for the products
of a movement may not be evident, and inappropriate, often obsolete, models
supplied by movements that have been superseded will stand in their stead.
Moreover, these features of new movements in art are also present in other cases of
aesthetic appreciation, such as that of the new agricultural landscapes. Given the
recentness of the agricultural revolution, it is not surprising if such landscapes are
similar in certain respects to the futurist and cubist works at the Armory show. Like
those movements in 1913, the exact nature of the new agricultural landscapes is not
yet clear and they have as yet to fully achieve their distinctive and characteristic look.
Thus appreciating such landscapes on their own terms rather than in relation to
their own past is understandably difficult.
In order for the works of a new movement in art to be appreciated on their own
terms, however, not only must the movement mature, but so too must the eyes and
minds of those who view its products. Moreover, for appropriate aesthetic
appreciation, this latter development is perhaps the more essential. This is because
as spectators mature they are both freed from inappropriate appreciative models and
freed to appreciate the newly created works for what they are. They thereby achieve
a fuller and truer appreciation of such works. On the one hand, in being freed from
inappropriate models, and in casting about for appropriate ones, spectators find how
to best appreciate the appearance of new works. For example, the sharp, angular
lines and the subdued shades of brown of Duchamp’s Nude seemingly made it
appear harsh, coarse, and dull by comparison with the impressionist works also
represented in the Armory show, for “the works of such masters as Manet, Monet,
Renoir, Degas” were described as “a relief to eyes and minds tortured by” the works
of the cubists, who in turn were judged to be “carpenters” who “in a few weeks…
will have to seek places in their real trade.”
25
Yet in light of the appreciative models
driven home by works such as Picasso’s Guernica (1937), Duchamp’s Nude can be
appropriately appreciated as a stunning study of form and movement. On the other
hand but in a similar fashion, in being freed to appreciate newly created works for what
they are, spectators discover the representational and expressive qualities of such
works. When appreciated as a cubist study, Nude looks very little “like a collection of
saddle bags” and much more like a nude descending a staircase. And whatever Nude
186 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
expresses, it is clearly not the case that, as one Armory show critic suggested, “the
said expression is one of disordered stomachs or deranged minds.”
26
Appreciating the new agricultural landscapes
In the light of these considerations concerning the appreciation of the works of new
art movements, it is fruitful to consider more carefully the aesthetic interest and
merit of the new agricultural landscapes. In general, in order to appreciate aesthetically
a new landscape, we must, as with the products of new movements in art, view it on
its own terms. In part this means that we are not likely to learn to admire a new
landscape by extensive comparison with the landscapes that it has destroyed and
replaced. The new agricultural landscapes are large in scale and vast in scope.
Consequently, we look in vain for the snug little farmstead and the intimate tree-or
fence-enclosed field and with frustration and dismay upon that which we find
instead. But in so looking we are guided by an inappropriate and perhaps obsolete
model. When divorced from this model and appreciated simply in terms of their own
appearances, both the new farmsteads and the new fields offer much of aesthetic
value.
The farmstead, for example, is now not only neater and cleaner in appearance, but
also has an orderly sharpness about it. A sequence of evenly spaced, precisely
squared, and perfectly plumbed aluminum structures can have an intensely metallic
and boldly geometric elegance all their own. And although the charm of the
gambrel-roofed barn and the two-story farmhouse is lost, the low horizontal lines of
the new structures, like those of the ranchstyle houses that often accompany them,
can echo the lay of flat open farm land in a manner reminiscent of Frank Lloyd
Wright’s “prairie style.”
27
However, it is in the fields where the aesthetic impact of
the new agricultural landscape is most evident. Here intensity of color and boldness
of line combine with scale and scope to produce landscapes of breathtaking formal
beauty: great checkerboard squares of green and gold, vast rectangles of
infinitesimally different shades of gray, or “immense stripes of sepia and ocher
stretching mile upon mile to the margins of the sky.”
28
When viewed from high
land or a low-flying plane such landscapes match the best of abstract geometrical
painting in power and drama.
29
And when standing in their midst one is engulfed
by their beauty.
The intensity of color and boldness of line which mark farmsteads and fields are
also apparent in the equipment that shapes the new landscape. Consider the
following:
It was still early,… Gigantic silver monsters, half a section long, were crawling
across the dark red earth, casting great arcs of water that shattered the white
Texas sunlight into a cascade of diamonds. Everything was geometry and
primal color—circles and planes and cylinders and parabolas and swirling
prisms of transparent light.
30
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 187
These remarks are about a modern self-propelled irrigation system at work, but the
described effect seemingly surpasses anything a kinetic sculpture-fountain might
achieve.
31
Indeed the appearance of much modern agricultural equipment defies
comparison with anything other than sculpture of the grandest and most innovative
kind: consider the rich primary colors and the clean, clear lines of any piece of farm
machinery, the steady, effortless movement of self-propelled harvesters, pickers, and
combines, the massive grandeur of towering silos of shining steel. Such sights can
surely dazzle the eye and excite the mind, but to do so modern fields and farms
must be viewed without being prejudiced by their own past.
The sights that enliven the farmstead and the field are similarly evident in the
rural community. If the highway strip has replaced the main street, it has yet
replaced it with what can only be described as a stunning display of color and form.
In order to appreciate this display, however, we may have to learn by drawing
comparisons with Las Vegas rather than with previous agricultural communities.
32
Nonetheless, if this is so, it again illustrates that, once freed from the appreciative
models given by its past, the new agricultural landscapes can be of aesthetic interest
and merit. Concerning their appearances, the fields, farms, and towns of modern
agriculture are much more than the blandscapes they may initially seem to be.
However, we hesitate to admire the new agricultural landscapes not simply
because of what we initially perceive as their blandscape appearance, but also
because of what expressive qualities we take them to have. The appearance is
enlivened by viewing a landscape on its own terms. In part this means appreciating
it without recourse to inappropriate models. But to view a landscape on its own
terms also means something more significant than this, and more relevant to its
expressive qualities. This, again as with works of art, is to appreciate it for what it is.
In the case of any agricultural landscape this means appreciating it as a functional
landscape.
In general, functional landscapes are those created or molded by humans in order
to achieve human goals. Such landscapes are typically deliberately designed to
perform the functions necessary for fulfilling relatively important goals.
Consequently, functional landscapes are to various degrees both designed and
necessary landscapes. In the case of any particular functional landscape, the degree
to which it is designed depends in large measure upon the kind of functions it
performs and how it performs them; the degree to which it is necessary, upon the
necessity of the functions for fulfilling the goal and the importance of the goal itself.
In the aesthetic appreciation of any functional landscape it is essential to take into
account the degree to which it is designed and is necessary, for these factors are
relevant to the determination of what qualities such landscapes have and express.
These considerations are especially pertinent to agricultural landscapes, for such
landscapes in general and the new agricultural landscapes in particular are both
highly designed and extremely necessary. The kind of functions they perform and
how they perform them—using the land itself to produce food and fiber—leads to
the creation of highly designed landscapes; and the importance of the goal those
functions fulfill—the production of food and fiber—together with the difficulty of
188 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
fulfilling this goal by alternative means, constitute such landscapes as extremely
necessary. Thus, in the appreciation of agricultural landscapes, it is important to
consider their designed and necessary nature in order to achieve a balanced aesthetic
view.
The aesthetic significance of a landscape being designed is that its aesthetic value
depends in part upon how and in particular how well it is designed. In the case of many
familiar designed landscapes, such as formal gardens, urban parks, and city squares,
this point is frequently overlooked or taken for granted, for such landscapes are in large
measure designed specifically for aesthetic purposes. Consequently, our aesthetic
appreciation of their appearances and expressive qualities itself constitutes an
appreciation of how and how well such landscapes are designed. In order to
appreciate our everyday functional landscapes in a comparable manner, however, we
must explicitly consider their functions and how and how well they are designed to
perform these functions. This is in part the point of the much-repeated phrase “form
follows function.” The forms of all functional objects—buildings, airplanes, and
appliances as well as landscapes—must be aesthetically appreciated in terms of how
and how well such forms fit their functions. However, the cliché is frequently
interpreted too narrowly. With anything functionally designed, not only its form,
but much of its aesthetic interest and merit, “follows function.”
33
When considered in this light, the aesthetic appreciation of the functional
landscapes of modern agriculture is greatly enhanced for, given the functions they
perform, they are in general very well designed. In agriculture, years of trial and error
together with the pressures for production have resulted in landscapes that can be
appreciated as paradigms of good design—crisp, clean, and uncluttered in
appearance and expressive of ingenuity, efficiency, and economy. Moreover, not
only the vast open fields and the orderly farmsteads, but also both the machines and
the buildings that occupy them, are aesthetically richer when appreciated in terms
of how and of how well they perform their functions. Consider again the self-
propelled pickers and combines, the mechanized stock buildings, and the new silos
and grain elevators of present-day agriculture. These are examples of machines
designed to collect, sort, and clean in one continuous flow of activity, of structures
designed to provide all the necessities of life, growth, and production, and of storage
units designed to follow the natural “angle of repose” of that which they contain. Such
machines and buildings not only express the virtues of good design, but possess a
style, grace, and elegance seldom exceeded anywhere else. Some observers even claim
that in terms of architectural design the landscapes of modern agriculture have
achieved a level of sophistication almost unknown in the city and its structures. For
example: “What seems to be evolving in our new rural landscape is a form and
concept of utilitarian architecture which the city as yet knows little about.”
34
Moreover, it is claimed that the machines themselves “are more than mere
machines: they are architecture, where form follows function more truly than in
most buildings, and with no trace of archness or apology.”
35
Even if functional landscapes, such as the new agricultural landscapes, are very well
designed, it is yet important to their aesthetic interest and merit that they be relatively
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 189
necessary landscapes. A landscape designed to perform functions unnecessary for
fulfilling our goals or only necessary for fulfilling trivial or whimsical goals,
regardless of how well designed, may express at best playfulness, more typically
capriciousness, superficiality, or crassness. Here again we can learn from Las Vegas,
but now by contrast rather than comparison. When we regard a landscape as
unnecessary, we often cannot take it seriously nor appreciate it as right or
appropriate, and thus the possibility of our admiring it suffers accordingly. The
importance of perceived seriousness in landscape appreciation and its relationship to
necessity is emphasized by geographer Yi-Fu Tuan:
Landscapes command our respect if we perceive them to be serious… Nature
is deemed serious because mountains and plains, forests and grasslands are
molded by necessity operating through geological time… As to human
environments, those which cater to the biological processes of life are deemed
serious. Thus modest homes, country roads, and well-cared fields have
traditionally appealed to our sentiments.
36
We have already noted that in general agricultural landscapes are extremely
necessary. They are in Tuan’s sense serious landscapes; they “cater to the biological
processes of life.” In fact many of such landscapes are necessary for our survival.
This has always been a dimension of their aesthetic appeal, and unless we judge the
new agricultural landscapes to be in this sense unnecessary, they too should
command our respect. Thus insofar as “modest homes, country roads, and well-
cared fields have traditionally appealed to our sentiments,” so now should the
elaborate equipment and the vast uniform fields of modern agriculture. They too
express the seriousness, rightness, and appropriateness of necessity. Of course, we
may doubt the necessity of the new agricultural landscape, and concerning some of
its details our doubts may be justified. However, its main trends, its massiveness,
mechanization, and monoculture, are probably necessary, and perhaps inevitable, in
our modern world. About the latter, for example, agronomist J.R.Harlan writes:
There are too many people in the world for us to go back to the more
complex and more stable agroecosystems… Monoculture is a feature of
modern agriculture, and we shall have to learn to live with it; indeed, we
might die without it.
37
Conclusion
There is no doubt that when confronted by the new agricultural landscapes we find
their aesthetic appreciation troublesome. The very idea of admiring them may strike
us as repellent. Initially we may perceive only a blandscape, dreary and monotonous
in appearance and expressive of the loss of both social stability and environmental
vitality. However, these landscapes are new and unfamiliar and thus difficult to
appreciate on their own terms, that is, without undue comparison to that which
190 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
they have replaced and as the well-designed and necessary functional landscapes they
are.
When appreciated without inappropriate comparison and in light of their
functional nature, however, the new agricultural landscapes are infused with new
aesthetic interest and merit. With such a landscape, not only is its appearance
enlivened, revealing a vibrant richness of color and form, but its expressive character
is enhanced by a mixture of good design and serious necessity. Such aesthetic
dimensions do not completely obliterate the new agricultural landscapes’ sometimes
monotonous look and unsavory expressive qualities. Yet these new aesthetic
dimensions serve to remind us that these landscapes, like most functional
landscapes, are complex, many-faceted, and equivocal objects of aesthetic
appreciation. And they demonstrate that our attempts to achieve fuller appreciation
of such landscapes are always rewarding and perhaps yield a truer assessment of their
actual aesthetic value.
William James saw this clearly and certainly more quickly than many of us. After
turning from the new and unfamiliar farmstead that he had just judged in the
harshest of terms, he had only to talk with a farmer to revise his opinion.
I instantly felt that I had been losing the whole inward significance of the
situation. Because to me the clearings spoke of naught but denudation, I
thought that to those whose sturdy arms and obedient axes had made them they
could tell no other story. But, when they looked on the hideous stumps, what
they thought of was personal victory. The chips, the girdled trees, and the vile
split rails spoke of honest sweat, persistent toil and final reward… In short,
the clearing, which to me was a mere ugly picture on the retina, was to them a
symbol redolent with moral memories and sang a very paean of duty,
struggle, and success.
38
His conclusion is relevant to more than that one North Carolina farm: “…wherever
there is conflict of opinion and difference of vision, we are bound to believe that the
truer side is the side that feels the more, and not the side that feels the less.”
39
Notes
1 William James, “On a Certain Blindness in Human Beings” [1899], Essays on Faith
and Morals, New York, Longmans, Green and Co., 1949, p. 261.
2 Ibid., p. 261.
3 Throughout this article I follow current usage and refer to agricultural landscapes
rather than agricultural environments. In doing so, however, I use “landscape” in its
geographical sense, which indicates our surroundings or our environment rather than
simply a viewed block of scenery or a prospect. On this distinction, see my
“Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–75 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4).
4 J.B.Jackson, “The Almost Perfect Town,” Landscape, 1952, vol. 2, pp. 2–8.
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 191
5John Fraser Hart, The Look of the Land, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice Hall, 1975, p. 74.
I introduce and illustrate the issues examined in this chapter by reference to the North
American agricultural landscapes and North American agricultural authorities, such as
Hart. However, this should not be taken as indicating that these issues are exclusively
North American concerns. They are concerns wherever the agricultural revolution is
occurring. For example, England’s Countryside Commission opens its discussion
paper on the new agricultural landscapes of Britain with the following: “There is
growing public concern about changes which are taking place in the appearance of the
lowland farmed countryside due to modern farming practices.” See New Agricultural
Landscapes: A Discussion Paper, Cheltenham, The Countryside Commission, 1974, p.
1.
6 For discussion of this point, see Jack R.Harlan, “Crop Monoculture and the Future of
American Agriculture,” in S.S.Batie and R.G.Healy (eds) The Future of American
Agriculture as a Strategic Resource, Washington, DC, The Conservation Foundation,
1980, pp. 225–50.
7 J.B.Jackson, “The New American Countryside: An Engineered Environment,”
Landscape, 1966, vol. 16, p. 18. This article is an exceptionally insightful and, given its
publication date, prophetic discussion of the role of the agricultural revolution in
shaping the new agricultural landscapes. It, together with a number of other perceptive
and relevant pieces originally published in Landscape, is republished in E.H.Zube and
M.J.Zube, (eds) Changing Rural Landscapes, Amherst, University of Massachusetts
Press, 1977, pp. 27–38.
8 See May Theilgaard Watts, Reading the Landscape of America [1957], New York,
Macmillan, 1975, p. 104. Wattss essays constitute the near perfect guidebook for the
appreciation of the rural landscape; concerning agricultural landscapes, see especially
“Prairie Plowing Match.”
9 [no author given], Minnesota Farmscape: Looking at Change, St. Paul, Minnesota
Historical Society, 1980, p. 16.
10 Peirce Lewis, “Facing Up to Ambiguity,” Landscape, 1982, vol. 26, p 20.
11 Minnesota Farmscape, op. cit., p 15.
12 Hart, op. cit., p. 136.
13 Jackson, “The New American Countryside,” op. cit., p. 19.
14 See John Fraser Hart, “A Map of the Agricultural Implosion,” Association of American
Geographers Proceedings, 1970, vol. 2, pp. 68–9.
15 Warren Bailey, quoted in Nick Kotz, “Agribusiness,” in Richard Merrill (ed.) Radical
Agriculture, New York, New York University Press, 1976, p. 51.
16 Jackson, “The New American Countryside,” op. cit., p. 17.
17 Peirce Lewis, “Axioms for Reading the Landscape: Some Guides to the American
Scene,” in D.W.Meinig (ed.) The Interpretation of Ordinary Landscapes, New York,
Oxford University Press, 1979, p. 23.
18 Lewis, “Facing Up to Ambiguity,” op. cit., p. 20.
19 For a discussion of the nature of “flatscapes,” see Ted Relph, “The Landscape of the
Conserver Society,” in Barry Sadler and Allen Carlson (eds) Environmental Aesthetics:
Essays in Interpretation, Victoria, University of Victoria, 1982, pp. 47–54.
20 Howard F.Gregor, Geography of Agriculture: Themes in Research, Englewood Cliffs,
Prentice Hall, 1970, p. 139.
21 Jim Hightower, “Hard Tomatoes, Hard Times: The Failure of the Land Grant
College Complex,” in Merrill (ed.) Radical Agriculture, op. cit., p. 106. For further
192 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
discussion of the environmental and social spin-offs of modern agriculture, in addition
to the other essays in Radical Agriculture, see, for example, David Allee, “American
Agriculture: Its Resource Issues for the Coming Years,” in R.Revelle and H.H.
Landsberg (eds) America’s Changing Environment, Boston, Houghton Miffin, 1970,
pp. 56–66; Wendell Berry, The Unsettling of America, San Francisco, Sierra Club
Books, 1977; Frederick H.Buttel, “Agriculture, Environment, and Social Change:
Some Emergent Issues,” in F.H.Buttel and H.Newby (eds) The Rural Sociology of the
Advanced Societies: Critical Perspectives, Montclair, Allanheld Osmun, 1980, pp. 453–
88; Committee on Agriculture and the Environment, National Research Council,
Productive Agriculture and A Quality Environment, Washington, DC, National
Academy of Sciences, 1974; P.Crosson and S.Brubaker, Resource and Environmental
Effects of US Agriculture, Washington DC, Resources for the Future, 1982; Walter
Goldschmidt, As You Sow: Three Studies in the Social Consequences of Agribusiness,
Montclair, Allanheld Osmun, 1978; Wes Jackson, New Roots for Agriculture, San
Francisco, Friends of Earth, 1980. For a brief overview, see William Aiken, “Value
Conflicts in Agriculture,” Agriculture and Human Values, 1984, vol. 1, pp. 24–7.
22 Respectively, James B.Townsend, “A Bomb from the Blue,” ARTnews, February 22,
1913; anonymous, “The Armory Exhibition,” ARTnews, March 1, 1913; and L.
Merrick, “Chamber of Horrors,” ARTnews, March 1, 1913; reprinted in Barbaralee
Diamonstein (ed.) The Art World: A Seventy-Five Year Treasury of ARTnews, New
York, ARTnews Books, 1977, pp. 23–5.
23 Townsend, op. cit., p. 23.
24 Merrick, op. cit., p. 25. In addition to the Armory show case, Monroe Beardsley
describes a number of other similar cases from the history of art appreciation, in which,
as he puts it, the spectators “failed to see what he [the artist] had done, because they
approached it [the work] with mistaken assumptions and expectations.” He reports
that Duchamp’s Nude was also called “a hurricane in a shingle factory.” See Monroe
C.Beardsley, Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism, New York, Harcourt,
Brace & World, 1958, p. 268.
25 Merrick, op. cit., p. 25.
26 Townsend, op. cit., p. 24.
27 In his early writings Wright observes:
A building should appear to grow easily from its site and be shaped to
harmonize with its surroundings if nature is manifest there… The
prairie has a beauty of its own and we should recognize and accentuate
this natural beauty, its quiet level. Hence, gently sloping roofs, low
proportions, quiet sky lines.
See “In the Cause of Architecture, I,” Architectural Record [1908], reprinted in
Frederick Gutheim (ed.) Frank Lloyd Wright on Architecture: Selected Writings,
1894– 1940, New York, Duell, Sloan and Pearce, 1941, p. 34.
28 Lewis, “Facing Up to Ambiguity,” op. cit., p. 21.
29 It is difficult not to draw direct comparisons with some of the works of painters such
as Kenneth Noland, Barnett Newman, Josef Albers, and Burgoyne Diller—even
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 193
though such comparisons may import appreciative models as inappropriate as those
given by our more traditional agricultural landscapes.
30 Lewis, “Facing Up to Ambiguity,” op. cit., p. 21.
31 However, given Lewis’s description, some of the works of Naum Gabo and of certain
other constructivism sculptors achieve a somewhat similar effect, although typically on
a smaller scale. For example, some aspects of the description are reminiscent of Gabo’s
Spiral Theme (1941) even though the sculpture is not a fountain, not kinetic, made of
plastic, and only inches in height. Again, however, such comparisons, as those with
abstract painting, must be considered with caution.
32 See Robert Venturi, Denise Scott Brown, and Steven Izenour, Learning from Las
Vegas: The Forgotten Symbolism of Architectural Form, Cambridge, MIT Press, 1977.
33 Architect Louis H.Sullivan, to whom the cliché is typically attributed, did not give it a
narrow interpretation. That “form ever follows function,” he describes as “the
pervading law of all things…of all true manifestations of the head, of the heart, of the
soul,” adding that “shape, form, outward expression, design or whatever we may
choose…should in the very nature of things follow function.” He continues, “when
the known law, the respected law, shall be that form ever follows function;…then it
may be proclaimed that we are on the high-road to a natural and satisfying art,…an
art that will live because it will be of the people, for the people, and by the people.”
See “The Tall Office Building Artistically Considered,” Kindergarten Chats and Other
Writings [1918], New York, Wittenborn, 1979, pp. 208–13.
34 Jackson, “The New American Countryside,” op. cit., p. 19.
35 Lewis, “Facing Up to Ambiguity,” op. cit., p. 21. If we were to follow Sullivan, we
might put part of the point of this paragraph by saying that well-designed functional
landscapes, buildings, and machines, such as those of modern agriculture, may be
appreciated as the products of “a natural and satisfying art,…an art…of the people, for
the people, and by the people.”
36 Yi-Fu Tuan, “Visual Blight: Exercises in Interpretation,” Visual Blight in America,
Washington, DC, Association of American Geographers, 1973, p. 26.
37 Harlan, op. cit., p. 232. Of course, not all authorities agree with the position
represented by Harlan. For an overview of some alternatives to large scale
monoculture, see Richard Conviser, “Toward Agricultures of Context,” Environmental
Ethics, 1984, vol. 6, pp. 71–85. Moreover, the actual aesthetic ramifications of the line
of thought of the last part of this section depends upon what we take our human goals
to be and how we evaluate their importance. The accepted goal for the functional
landscapes of agriculture may be simply to ensure the survival of as many human
beings as possible for as long as possible. However, we may recognize more
comprehensive systems together with different goals and evaluate these goals as equally
or as more important. For example, one such goal might be, following Aldo Leopold’s
“Land Ethic,” “to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic
community” (including, I assume, at least some human beings). See “The Land Ethic”
[1953], A Sand County Almanac with Essays on Conservation from Round River, New
York, Random House, 1974, p. 262. When perceived in light of such considerations,
many agricultural landscapes may again reveal rather unsavory expressive qualities
similar to those discussed in the third section of this chapter. Although I am
sympathetic to these considerations, they cannot be pursued here. Within the context
of this chapter my point is simply that given the goals that many of us in fact accept for
194 AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT
the functional landscapes of agriculture and given the importance we grant to these
goals, we should find such landscapes more expressively appealing than we typically do.
38 James, op. cit., p. 262.
39 Ibid., pp. 260–1.
APPRECIATING AGRICULTURAL LANDSCAPES 195
196
13
EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND
FUNCTION: THE APPRECIATION OF
ARCHITECTURE
Architecture and art
What of general aesthetic interest and significance can be said about the
appreciation of architecture, an art marked by works, movements, traditions, and
theories possibly more diverse than those of any other major art form? Perhaps
preliminary progress is best made only by noting some obvious ways in which
architecture as an art differs from many other forms. These differences mean that
the aesthetic appreciation of architecture poses certain challenges not typically
present in the appreciation of other arts. Such challenges not only shape the nature
of appropriate appreciation of works of architecture, but also help to make such
appreciation especially rewarding.
Initially it is important to again stress what has been suggested in a number of
previous chapters: that aesthetic appreciation involves more than simply either
passive contemplation of pleasing form or spontaneous delight in sensuous surface.
Essential to aesthetic appreciation is active engagement, involving cognitive and
emotional interaction between the appreciator and the object of appreciation. An
important aspect of this engagement is a kind of dialogue between appreciator and
object in which the latter explicitly or implicitly poses certain questions or problems
and the former finds the answers or solutions. Such finding of answers or solutions
typically takes the form of coming to realizations about the nature of the object of
appreciation. This process of realizing is at the heart of aesthetic appreciation; it
employs the imagination so as to produce that unique combination of admiration
and awe that is central to aesthetic experience.
1
The questions that are posed by a work of art vary according to its kind, for
different art forms present different problems to be solved. Consider a
representational painting, for example, a small sketch by Group of Seven artist Tom
Thomson such as Autumn Foliage (1916).
2
Such a work constitutes a
straightforward case, for with representational works the initial and obvious problems
to be solved typically concern what is represented. In Autumn Foliage we confront a
small but vibrant mass of fiery color, but even without reference to the title we easily
experience the work as a landscape. We see it as the red and yellow autumn foliage of
eastern hardwoods against a background of blackish blue water, distant stands of
dark conifers, and an almost turquoise fall sky. Such realizations come almost
without effort to any appreciator familiar with early twentieth-century painting.
However, even relatively simple representational works pose further problems that
offer the imagination somewhat more exercise, typically questions concerning how
and why the work is executed as it is and what the appreciative consequences are of
the particular execution. For example, if we consider the question of the significance
Illustration 8 Autumn Foliage, by Tom Thomson (1916) (Courtesy of the National Gallery of
Canada, Ottawa).
198 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
of Thomson’s dimensions, imaginative contemplation rewards us with the
realization of the extent to which its small size contributes to its power. Its borders
confine the fiery mass of color such that it struggles to escape from the surface, and
we experience a work that glows and flares like embers enclosed in a pressurized
chamber.
To be or not to be: Hamlet and Tolstoy
In contrast to art forms such as representational painting, works of architecture
typically pose some larger if not deeper questions. Perhaps the most basic of these is
captured by the opening line of Hamlet’s most famous soliloquy: “To be, or not to
be: that is the question.”
3
Hamlet’s question is whether it might not be better
—“nobler in the mind”—not to exist, and this is a question that seldom arises when
we view conventional works of art. It is difficult to imagine a work such as Autumn
Foliage posing such a question concerning its existence. Of course, this is in part
because Autumn Foliage is a small masterpiece and as such seems to fully justify its
own existence. However, even were this not the case, the question does not easily
arise for such works. Perhaps this is for reasons similar to those that apparently
move Hamlet toward the conclusion that it is better to be. The alternative, to die, is
to be no more, or worse, and “there’s the rub,” to suffer other ills “that we know not
of”—the fact that the alternative is unknown “does make cowards of us all.”
4
Similarly, as we contemplate Autumn Foliage, even were it not a masterpiece, it
would yet be the case that were it not there, we would contemplate only the blank
wall of the gallery or worse some other work that we know not of. Apparently, with
such art forms, the question of existence arises only if the work is so bad that almost
anything else, even a blank wall, would yield a better aesthetic experience.
Concerning architecture, however, Hamlet’s question is very much alive.
Consider Philip Johnson’s American Telephone and Telegraph (AT&T) Building,
monumental, granite clad, standing boldly on the street edge, and capped with what
has been called a “Chippendale highboy top.”
5
As we contemplate it, even if we
believe it a masterpiece, we cannot help but consider the question of its existence; it
is forced upon us. We ask ourselves: Might it not have beeen better for this not to
have existed? Might it not have been better for the place, for the skyline, for the
city, for the world? Such questions are forcefully posed by the building itself, but
not simply because of the work’s monumental size or its controversial postmodern
style. With architecture such questions are posed in part because, unlike with either
Autumn Foliage or Hamlet, the alternatives to a work’s existence are typically not
either nothing or the unknown. Had the Johnson AT&T Building not been
constructed, there would not have been nothing, there would not have been a blank
space analogous to a blank wall. Rather there would have been another work, either
the previous building or a different work of architecture, or if not that, then at least
the lot or the city block with its own aesthetic features. Moreover, such alternatives
are not unknown; in contemplating them we are not in a position analogous to
contemplating what death might hold or what might go on the blank gallery wall.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 199
We can know exactly what the previous building was like, know roughly what the
city block would be like, and have a good idea of what kind of alternative
architectural work might have existed had the one we confront not existed.
Ilustration 9 The AT&T Building, by Philip Johnson/John Burgee (1980–83), New York
City (Courtesy of American Telephone and Telegraph).
200 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
Whether or not the question of its own existence is posed by a work of art has
significant ramifications concerning its appreciation. Once the question is broached,
attempting to answer it brings realizations that are central to our aesthetic
experience of the work. However, if a work does not pose the question, then this is
not the case. In appreciating Autumn Foliage it is appropriate to consider whether or
not the work might have been improved by a somewhat less turquoise sky. Such
consideration can bring us to the realization that the turquoise is just what is
wanted. A stronger blue would have not only been less true to a northern autumn
sky, but also contrasted too much with the fiery reds and yellows, and thus would
have resulted in a less subtle work. Such realizations enhance our appreciation of the
work and are a central part of it. In contrast, considering whether it might not be better
for Autumn Foliage not to exist and therefore to contemplate the blank wall of the
gallery or have its space on the wall filled with, say, Guernica (1937) is quite
irrelevant to our appreciation of the work, if not just absurd or at least aesthetically
perverse. Such consideration is not a proper part of our appreciation of that work; it
is rather just one kind of lack of attention to it. As noted, a work such as Autumn
Foliage would pose the question of its existence only if it were excruciatingly bad,
and in that case perhaps lack of attention is the proper response; but this is yet lack
of attention to the work, not a part of its appreciation.
We can, of course, consider the AT&T Building’s Chippendale top in the same
way we consider Autumn Foliage’s turquoise sky, asking, for example, if perhaps a
domed top or a simple flat top might not have been better. Doing so brings
realizations that enhance our appreciation of that work and are a proper part of that
appreciation. However, unlike Autumn Foliage, the AT&T Building forces Hamlet’s
question upon us and thus opens the door to another level of aesthetically relevant
consideration. As we contemplate the work, we ask ourselves what if, for example,
Johnson had not created it, but instead of it another modernist skyscraper, such as
the classic Seagram Building, which he earlier collaborated on with Ludwig Mies
van der Rohe. We imaginatively consider the alternative aesthetic effect that such a
clean and crisp, glass and steel structure might have had and the ways in which it
might have blended rather than contrasted with a skyline dominated by similar
structures. Since the AT&T Building itself poses the question of its existence, such
consideration of alternatives to its existence are a proper and central part of its
aesthetic appreciation. Moreover, the same is true of our consideration not only of
alternatives to its existence, but also of its simple nonexistence. This is easier to see
concerning works in natural landscapes. Consider Frank Lloyd Wright’s famous
houses such as Falling Water and Taliesin West.
6
The former grows out of a rocky
Pennsylvania ravine scattered with poplar and birch while the latter sprawls across a
stretch of Arizona desert dotted with sagebrush and cactus. In each case the work
candidly asks us to consider the fact of its existence, and thus our experience of the
work rightly involves imaginative contemplation of the landscape without the work.
And this contemplation is a central and proper part of our appreciation of the work;
such appreciation is typically deepened and enriched by the realizations it initiates.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 201
The central place of the question of existence in the appreciation of architecture
raises concerns about how to address it. As noted, the realizations gained from
attempting to answer it are as significant as are those gained from answering
questions about features more internal to the work, such as questions about the
rightness of Autumn Foliage’s turquoise sky or of AT&T’s Chippendale top. This in
turn suggests that the appreciation of architecture is necessarily a more broadly
based and less insular experience than is the appreciation of some other art forms.
The borders between architecture and the world in general and the world’s aesthetic
issues and its ethical, social, political, and even economic issues are not as hard and
fast as are those between, say, landscape painting and such issues. Moreover, given
the central place of the question of existence in the appreciation of architecture, it
seems that there should be some core idea in terms of which to answer it. But
finding this idea initially appears exceedingly difficult in light of the lack of hard and
fast borders between architecture and the concerns of the world in general. In short,
many more kinds of consideration seem relevant to the question of the rightness of
the AT&T’s existence than to the question of the rightness of Autumn Foliage’s
turquoise sky. But in addressing the former question not absolutely everything can
be given attention and it is difficult to see what should be deemed essential.
Concerning this issue, it is illuminating to consider a classic discussion in which
Hamlet’s question is asked about art in general. In one of the most remarkable
passages in the history of aesthetics, Tolstoy launches an aggressive attack on art,
calling on it to justify its own existence.
7
His prime example is a work somewhat
comparable to a work of architecture such as the AT&T Building in that it has
monumental size and involves extensive utilization of resources; it is an opera that
Tolstoy describes as “one of the most gigantic absurdities that could possibly be
devised.”
8
He directly challenges the existence of such works, asking for what
purpose and for whom are they created. Moreover, his concern is not simply with
large and imposing works but with art in general; it focuses on the idea that for “the
production of every ballet, circus, opera, operetta, exhibition, picture, concert, or
printed book, the intense and unwilling labor of thousands of people is needed at
what is often harmful and humiliating work.”
9
Of course, work in the present-day
designing and building disciplines and trades is probably not comparable to the
labor of workers in Tolstoy’s Russia, but it is yet possible to motivate the question
of existence posed by architecture in a way somewhat reminiscent of Tolstoy. And
this is not surprising in light of the previously noted openness in the borders
between architecture and the world at large.
What is especially relevant to architecture, however, is Tolstoy’s approach to
answering the question of existence. He recognizes that what is needed is, as noted
above, some core idea that can determine, given Tolstoy’s interests, “what is good,
useful art—art for the sake of which we might condone such sacrifices as are being
offered at its shrine.”
10
And significantly he finds his answer by casting the question
in functional terms, asking “for what and for whom” does art exist and then
providing a theory of art that gives art a functional role in human life. As is well
known, in Tolstoy’s theory of art, real, noncounterfeit art—the only art that should
202 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
exist—has the function of communicating feelings between people, and “good,
useful art” is the art that unites humankind by communicating feelings of love. We
need not, of course, accept Tolstoys whole theory of art to find relevance in his
general line of thought concerning the question of existence. The relevance is in the
realization that it is necessary to cast our question and its answer in functional terms.
And although doing this would require a functional theory such as Tolstoy’s were
we interested in art in general, since our concern is only with architecture, it does
not. This is because, unlike many art forms, architecture is by its nature a functional
art. Thus, when Hamlet’s question is posed by works of architecture, Tolstoy’s
implicit answer is to emphasize, rather than ignore, their functionality. I return to
this answer, but first it is useful to expand and deepen the question to which it is
addressed.
Here I stand: to fit or not to fit
If Hamlet’s question is an apt way to indicate the first challenge offered by works of
architecture, a second can perhaps be marked by Martin Luther’s famous
affirmation of his faith. In 1521 at his second hearing at Worms, Luther, accused of
heresy and threatened with excommunication and death, is reported to have
concluded his defense with these words: “Here I stand. I cannot do otherwise, God
help me. Amen.”
11
Luther, of course, was defending a theological position, but it is
the way in which he did so that is evocative. This affirmation of his position has a
firmness and finality that suggests the firmness and finality with which works of
architecture, especially large and massive works such as the AT&T, occupy their
physical positions. The AT&T Building, as noted, is monumental in size, encased in
granite, and stands boldly at the street edge. It is not set back and it is not light; it is
imposing and solid. With only a little imagination it is difficult not to perceive it as
strongly affirming its physical position, as an exemplification of “Here I stand. I
cannot do otherwise.” But, of course, a powerful affirmation always offers the
challenge of whether or not this is how it should be, or, in this kind of case, where it
should be. Thus, the second question posed by works of architecture elaborates the
first. They pose not only the question of to be or not to be, but also that of to be or
not to be here?
The “here I stand” question is most obviously raised by works such as the
AT&T, works of size and of imposing nature, especially skyscrapers, office towers,
and large luxury hotels. For example, modernist towers such as the Seagram
Building, the Union Carbide Building, and the Chase Manhattan Bank each pose
the question on the skyline of New York City.
12
In a similar way, the affirmation is
made by cathedrals and temples, castles and capital buildings. Notre Dame de Paris,
the Parthenon, the monastery of Mont St. Michel, and any decent US state capital
building each in its own way proclaims “Here I stand.” However, it would be a
mistake to think that this issue is raised only by substantial structures directly
proclaiming their own “hereness.” Wright’s Falling Water raises the question in
virtue of how it is built into its site, embodying a design absolutely dependent on
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 203
that site. Likewise, at Taliesin West, features that are cited as evidence of Wright’s
so-called “organic” style—such as the use of natural materials, the rough finish of
the timbers, and the way the structure sits on its stepped site—each give the work a
special relationship to that particular site, a relationship underscoring the
importance of where it is. Other kinds of works pose the question of their location
in yet other ways. Le Corbusier’s Villa Savoye perches on the landscape, poised and
alert, like an alien object, the tenuousness of its relationship to its site not so much
making a proclamation as directly asking the question. It seems to say not “Here I
stand” but something like: “Why am I here?”
13
Concerning a work’s location, the comparison with other art forms is again
illuminating. A painting such as Autumn Foliage has, of course, a location. As a
physical object, it must be in some place or other. But as a work of art, it does not
raise the issue of its location, it does not proclaim, or pose the question of, where it
is. Calling its location a site would be at best misleading and considering the work in
its location, whatever that is, is not a part of its appropriate appreciation. Of course,
in attempting to appreciate such a work we may be forced to consider its location, if,
for instance, it detracts from the work, say, with noise or poor lighting or conflicting
color. But such consideration, and the realizations arising from it, are not proper
parts of our appreciation of that work, but rather only distractions from it. The
only relevance such consideration might have to the appreciation of the work would
be in ways such as initiating moving the work to a “neutral” location and thereby
making its full appreciation possible. However, there is one sense in which works
such as Autumn Foliage have a proper place or “site.” This particular work is located
on a wall in the National Gallery of Canada, in one of the rooms of early Group of
Seven and related paintings, alongside a number of other small Tom Thomson
landscapes; and this is a, if not the, proper place for it to be. But, although this
placement of Autumn Foliage may be proper and may even contribute to its
appreciation, this does not make its actual physical location directly relevant to that
appreciation. Its physical location indicates its proper conceptual and art-historical
placement and it is the realization of the latter, not the former, that is a proper part
of its appropriate appreciation.
Not all works of art, however, are location independent in the sense exemplified
by paintings such as Autumn Foliage, and it is revealing concerning architecture to
consider some art forms said to be “site specific.” Site specificness is claimed to be a
feature of some large sculptural works, of most earthworks, and of what are called
placement pieces. Consider Richard Serra’s controversial Tilted Arc (1983), a 12 by
120 foot curved sheet of oxidized steel cutting across a public plaza.
14
Reaction to
the piece resulted in a hearing concerning whether or not to relocate it. In defense
of his piece, Serra claimed: “I don’t make works that can be relocated or site
adjusted. I make works that deal with the environmental components of given
places. The scale, size, and location of my site-specific works are determined by the
topography of the site.” He concluded: “My works become part of and are built into
the structure of the site… To remove Tilted Arc, therefore, would be to destroy
it.”
15
Indeed, in the hearing the relationship of the Arc to the plaza was compared to
204 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
that of a painting to, not “its” wall, but its canvas. As noted in Chapter 10, similar
claims are made for earthworks and other placement pieces. For example, in
reviewing classic works such as Robert Smithson’s Spiral Jetty (1970) and Michael
Heizer’s Double Negative (1969–71) and Complex One (1972–76), Elizabeth Baker,
editor of Art in America, points out that the sites of such works “become places as
vivid as the works themselves—they become concertized, identifiable, specific
locales” and that therefore the “appearance of that place becomes a part of the
content of the work” to such an extent that the works “are not only inseparable from
their sites—they are not really definable at all apart from them.”
16
If such works are “part of the structure of the site” and the site is “part of the
content of the work,” there are important consequences concerning aesthetic
appreciation. It means that to appreciate the work itself is to appreciate its location,
that is, to come to realizations about the relationship, the fit, as it were, between the
part of the work the artist has added and the part of the work that is the site of that
addition. In short, to appreciate such a work is to appreciate its fit, coming to
realizations about whether or not it fits and, if it fits, how it fits. For example,
concerning Heizer’s monumental desert work, Complex One, Baker records the
following realizations:
The frontality of Complex One can be seen as projecting a curiously
pictorializing effect on a portion of the landscape: it is not just that the
presence of the piece re-presents or differentiates this particular place; it is also
that as a distant, planar picturelike entity the work tends to crystallize and
make a panorama of a certain lateral sweep of land that frames the frame of the
piece.
17
In a somewhat similar manner, essentially involved in the dispute over Tilted Arc was
the realization that the additions involved in Serra’s works “often restructure, both
conceptually and perceptually, the organization of the site.”
18
In appreciating Tilted
Arc, viewers came to the realization that part of what the work does is “to alter and
dislocate the decorative function of the plaza, to redefine the space, to change the
viewer’s experience of that plaza.”
19
In fact much of the objection to the work was
based on this realization and the opinion that this was essentially “to destroy the
plaza’s original artistic concept.”
20
In short, some viewers appreciated the work,
including the fit of the arc with its location, and they did not like that fit.
It is not clear that works of architecture relate to their locations in the very strong
way in which works such as Tilted Arc and Complex One do. It seems that the
location of a work of architecture is not always, in any case, “part of the content of
the work.” Nonetheless, works of architecture are certainly closer to these kinds of
works than they are to works such as Autumn Foliage, and thus the way in which the
former kinds of works are appropriately appreciated is illuminating concerning
architecture. Thus, in appreciating architectural works we must appreciate the
relationship of the structure to its site as a part of the total experience. The fact that
works of architecture pose the “Here I stand” issue is in itself sufficient to make the
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 205
fit of a work to its site a central feature of its proper appreciation. Nowhere is this
clearer than with works such as Wright’s “organic” style houses. Taliesin West
“differentiates,” “represents,” and “crystallizes” its desert landscape site in a way
remarkably similar to that which Baker attributes to Heizer’s Complex One. And the
relationship between Falling Water and its ravine is as intimate as that between any
earthwork and its site. Architect and historian Kenneth Frampton says of Falling
Water: “Its fusion with the landscape is total, for…nature permeates the structure at
every turn.
21
Here one is tempted by the claim that the ravine is indeed part of the
work, but even if that does not withstand scrutiny, it is yet obvious that we do not
fully appreciate, if appreciate at all, the work of art called Falling Water unless we
appreciate the rocky treed ravine and the way in which the structure is designed for
and built into it. Here the fit of building and site is an essential, if not the essential,
dimension of the work.
It is a long way, however, from Falling Water to modernist towers such as the
Seagram Building, the Union Carbide Building, and the Chase Manhattan Bank.
Although such structures clearly raise the question of their location, it is initially less
clear that their proper appreciation involves the appreciation of their fit with their
sites. Perhaps they are after all more like Autumn Foliage than like Falling Water.
However, the flaw in this view is made clear by further comparison with examples
such as Complex One and Tilted Arc. Each in its own way demonstrates a different
facet of the proper appreciation of such structures. On the one hand, much as does
Complex One, and, for that matter, Taliesin West, a tower such as the Seagram
Building “differentiates,” “represents,” and “crystallizes” its site. This was especially
evident when this particular work was constructed in 1958: it was Mies van der
Rohe’s first New York building and, with 38 stories of glistening bronze and brown
glass, the largest of its type in the world. And it was set back 90 feet from the line of
the street, both as a way of creating a plaza on the site and, it is said, “as a
complement to the 1817 Racquets Club by McKim, Mead and White on the other
side of Park Avenue.”
22
On the other hand, although some of Seagram’s
“crystallization” of and “differentiating” fit with its site may be in this way positive,
this is not essential for fit to yet be a proper part of a work’s appreciation. As Tilted
Arc demonstrates, some of a work’s fit with its site may be, or at least may be
regarded by many appreciators to be, dislocating and even destructive. Some would
contend that this is the kind of relationship that many modernist towers have to
their sites.
To pursue the issue of a less positive or at least more controversial fit between
work and site, however, it is more illuminating to consider postmodern
architecture. Although the so-called postmodern movement seemingly embraces any
departure from the modernist tradition, it is said by RobertA. M. Stern to involve
three main features: historical allusion, ornamentation, and contextualism.
23
Of
these three, exclusive attention to the first two is sometimes termed postmodernism
of reaction and a focus on the last, postmodernism of resistance.
24
Frampton calls
the latter “critical regionalism,” for it stresses not only the immediate context, the
site, but also local architectural forms, building techniques, and topography and
206 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
even relevant cultural, social, and political factors.
25
By contrast, postmodernism of
reaction seemingly emphasizes historical illusion and ornamentation almost at the
expense of all else. A case illustrating both sides of postmodernism is that of the
Johnson and John Burgee New England Life Building on Boston’s Boylston Street.
This structure, an example of postmodernism of reaction, has been described as “the
party crasher on this block,” an “arrogant intruder in the cityscape,” and a
“Jukeboxlike” tower with “arched windows, urns, columns, a formal forecourt and all
manner of elements that show that its designers flipped through the history
books.”
26
The design caused such a public outcry that a second matching tower was
canceled and its site given to Stern. In contrast to the Johnson and Burgee building,
Stern’s tower, it is said, “is designed for this site and for this site alone, its details
recall the elements that make the older buildings of this neighborhood special, and
its overall form takes into account the larger urban design needs of the entire
neighborhood.”
27
The Stern building, a case of postmodernism of resistance, is
“molded so specifically to the demands of this particular site” and “weaves so
comfortably into the Boston streetscape” that it is claimed to “save” the overall
site.
28
In light of the distinction between postmodernism of resistance and
postmodernism of reaction, it seems clear that the former, in addition to being
perhaps the more promising direction for postmodern architecture to take, presents
no new difficulties concerning the importance of appreciating the fit between work
and site in the appreciation of architecture. The careful attention to site given by the
works such as the Boston Stern building makes them comparable in mode of
appreciation to works such as Taliesin West and Falling Water. In contrast,
however, postmodernism of reaction, as noted, seemingly emphasizes historical
illusion and ornamentation to the exclusion of everything else and thus presents a
serious challenge to the importance of fit in the appreciation of architecture. Less
extreme examples of this side of the movement, such as the AT&T, can perhaps be
treated on the model of Tilted Arc. For example, in creating the AT&T, Johnson is
said to have been attempting to counter some ofthe anonymity and muteness
of the site, which he attributed to the surrounding modernist towers, including his
own Seagram tower. And thus the relationship of the work to the site can be seen as
involving “irony, frivolity, or calculated shock value.”
29
It certainly is an attempt, as
is Tilted Arc, to “restructure, both conceptually and perceptually, the organization
of the site,” although perhaps more a humorous than a destructive attempt. One
author refers to the AT&T as “a standup joke.”
30
Other more eclectic and more solemn works of postmodernism of reaction, such
as certain classic creations by Robert Venturi and Michael Graves, pose more of a
problem. Extreme examples, such as the Johnson and Burgee, have been criticized as
“historical gamesmanship,” “do-it-yourself history,” and “Disneyland Classicism”
that leaves one “floundering between kitsch…and a nostalgia for past grandeur.”
31
In such cases what sense can be made of the aesthetic appreciation of the fit of the work
with its site? It seems there are two alternatives. On the one hand, as suggested
above with the AT&T, we can push the analogy with Tilted Arc as far as possible,
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 207
experiencing exactly how such structures restructure,” “dislocate,” “deconstruct,”
and even “destroy” their sites as a part of our appreciation of the work. After all,
“party crashers” or “arrogant intruders” nonetheless have relationships, and often
very interesting ones, with those on whom they crash or intrude. On the other hand,
if a work of postmodernism of reaction really has no fit with its site, positive or
negative, if its “fit” with where it stands really is comparable to Autumn Foliage’s
“fit” with its wall, then a more extreme alternative suggests itself. This is to deny
such a work the status of the art form of architecture, to demote it, as it were, to simply
a decorated building. This is suggested by some. For example, architect Romaldo
Giurgola speaks against “impositions on the site” contending that the “making of
clear connections with a cultural past and present is very different from the
sophisticated playing” that “passes for architecture today” and is that in terms of
which “a building becomes true architecture.”
32
Others echo such sentiments,
concluding that it “takes a creative act, not clever cannibalism, to turn a building
into art.”
33
However, I suggest that rather than endorsing this radical alternative, it
is more fruitful to pursue the fit of works of architecture in another way.
Form follows function and fit follows function
Concerning the two previously discussed challenges posed by works of architecture,
the issue of existence and the issue of location, together with the auxiliary question
of fit, we considered as examples either modernist or postmodern office towers and
certain works by Frank Lloyd Wright. Thus, it is fitting that a third challenge be
introduced by reference to Louis Sullivan, for Sullivan is sometimes credited with the
first significant instantiations of, if not the invention of, the high-rise office
building, and Wright was his most famous apprentice. In “The Tall Office Building
Artistically Considered,” Sullivan wrote that “the shape, form, outward expression,
design or whatever we may choose, of the tall office building should in the very
nature of things follow the functions of the building.” This is because:
It is the pervading law of all things…,of all true manifestations of the head, of
the heart, of the soul, that life is recognizable in its expression, that form ever
follows function. This is the law… And thus, when native instinct and
sensibility shall govern the exercise of our beloved art; when the known law,
the respected law, shall be that form ever follows function; then it may be
proclaimed that we are on the highroad to a natural and satisfying art, an
architecture that will soon become a fine art in the true, best sense of the
word, an art that will live because it will be of the people, for the people, and
by the people.
34
Sullivan’s remarks dramatically proclaim that architecture is by its nature a
functional art, and thus they remind us of the most obvious question posed by any
work of architecture: the question of what its function is, what does it do?
Moreover, the slogan “form follows function” sums up the significance of this
208 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
question, which is that, as Sullivan put it, “the shape, form, outward expression,
design or whatever we may choose,” of a work of architecture should follow the
functions of the work. Thus, although Sullivan himself was apparently of minor
influence in the architectural developments that followed him, his words yet capture
both the nature of architecture as an art form and the ideas that have dominated the
art in the twentieth century. Not only are these ideas evident in works such as those
of Wright and others directly influenced by Sullivan, but they illuminate the whole
of the modernist movement, noted for its so-called “functionalist” buildings. For
example, Sullivan’s ideas are given concert expression by Mies van der Rohe:
The office building is a house of work…of organization, of clarity, of
economy. Bright, wide, workrooms, easy to oversee, undivided except as the
undertaking is divided. The maximum effect with the minimum expenditure
of means. The materials are concrete, iron, glass.
35
And although Le Corbusier claimed that architecture goes beyond mere needs, he is
more closely associated with the idea that the house is “a machine for living in.”
36
Even postmodernism does not escape the themes to which Sullivan gave voice. In the
design of the AT&T, Johnson returns to the tripartite division of base, shaft, and
capital that Sullivan first justified on the grounds that outer form must reflect inner
function.
37
As with the other questions raised by works of architecture, the question of
function is illuminated by comparison with different art forms. When we confront
Autumn Foliage we do not ask what its function is, nor does it pose the question, for
in an important sense such a work has no function. Of course, if we hold a theory
of art such as Tolstoy’s, then we might ask a question about a particular work’s
function as a way of asking about the function, if any, of art in general.
Alternatively, if we are unclear about the exact nature of the kind of art we
confront, then we might ask about the work’s function as a way of asking what it
does as a work of art—for example, whether or not it is representational and if so,
what it represents. But aside from these kinds of questions, the question of the
particular function of Autumn Foliage has no place in our appreciation of that work.
By contrast, the question of the particular function of a work such as Falling Water
or the AT&T is both posed by the work and relevant to our appreciation of it. It is
essential in our appreciation of a work of architecture to come to the correct
realizations about what it does—to know whether it is an office building or a
temple, a fortress or a cathedral, a house or a mausoleum, all of which, it is worth
noting, are functional categories. Moreover, here architecture differs not only from
works such as Autumn Foliage but also from the earthworks and placement pieces
with which it seemingly has much in common. Although works such as Complex
One and Tilted Arc may raise the question of existence and certainly pose questions
about their location and fit, they do not have a particular function any more than
does Autumn Foliage.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 209
There are, however, other art forms that are more functional in nature. Especially
relevant to architecture is what might be thought of as its poor cousin: the public
monument. Consider the statues of generals or the World War I (WWI) and II
memorials that adorn many city parks; or the Vietnam Veterans Memorial in
Washington, DC.
38
We may wish to withhold the term “work of art” from some of
such pieces, but in many cases that would be a mistake and certainly so with the
latter work. Of many of such works, especially some of the rather abstract WWI
pieces, we appropriately ask questions concerning function as we might ask of
Autumn Foliage, for example, questions about whether or not it is representational
and if so, what it represents. However, unlike Autumn Foliage or even earthworks
and placement pieces, a monument poses another question of function, one that is
not about what it is or does as a work of art, but rather about what it does in
addition to being and acting as art. In addressing this question we typically consider
what war, battle, action, or individuals the piece commemorates, why it does so, and
so on; in short, we are concerned with what cultural, social, or political functions
the monument has. And the realization of these kinds of functions is a vital part of
our appreciation of the piece. Without such realizations when appreciating, for
example, the Vietnam Veterans Memorial we experience only a dark wall with a lot
of names on it, and our appreciation is accordingly both impoverished and
inappropriate. Here both comparison and contrast with architecture is useful. In
comparison, these works bring out clearly the way in which our complete experience
of works of architecture is dependent upon our appreciation of the functions they
have independent of being and acting as art, what might be termed their nonartistic
functions. This is not surprising in light of the above-noted openness in the borders
between architecture and rest of the world.
More illuminating, however, is the contrast between monuments and memorial
pieces and works of architecture. The key difference concerns the nature of the
nonartistic functions and the means by which they are carried out. Monuments and
memorials serve functions such as commemorating, honoring, venerating, and
glorifying; their purposes are to inform, remind, induce, and inspire. Consequently,
such pieces carry out their functions straightforwardly and on their surfaces, and
typically in a direct representational or symbolic manner. The general with horse
and sword or the black granite face of the Vietnam Veterans Memorial with its 58,
132 inscribed names each directly denotes a particular war and those who served
and sacrificed in it. There is nothing hidden, no other way in which or other place
where the function is actually carried out, no alternative mechanism by which or
inner place in which the real work is done. Thus, with such works there is no need
to insist that form should follow function; typically the form itself is what carries
out the function—function is embodied in form. However, works of architecture
serve other kinds of nonartistic functions; they protect, shelter, and comfort,
providing places in which to live, work, and worship. Given the nature of such
functions, they must typically be carried out literally rather than simply
symbolically. Even if a cathedral symbolizes the glory and the power of God, it must
still be a house of, and thereby provide a place in which to, worship. This fact about
210 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
the nature of the functions of architecture in turn explains the importance of the
insistence that concerning architecture form should follow function. This is because
when form does not directly embody function, as it does in the symbolic case, then
it is seemingly possible for form to not follow function, but to, as it were, go its own
way. And this possibility is accentuated by a second significant feature of
architecture’s functional nature, which is related to the way in which works of
architecture, in contrast to monuments, typically carry out their functions: works of
architecture have insides.
The fact that works of architecture, unlike almost any other works of art, have, by
their natures, insides, inner space as well as outer place, seemingly follows directly
from their functionality and the particular kinds of functions they perform, for such
functions are typically performed inside the works. In fact, if a structure has no inside
either because it has no function of the relevant kind, such as with most artistic
earthworks or because its function is carried out exclusively on its outside, as with
some Central American temple mounds, it is somewhat difficult to see the structure
as a work of architecture at all. This “insidedness” of architecture means that, as an
auxiliary question to that of function, works of architecture pose the question of the
nature of their inner space. And unlike any of the other previously considered art
forms, realizations about the insides of works of architecture are a significant
dimension of their appreciation. We may speculate about what the inside of
Complex One or even, with more difficulty, of Autumn Foliage is like or about what
it looks like, but such speculation is not a significant part, if a part at all, of our
proper appreciation of such works. However, realizations about, and if possible the
direct experience of, the inside of, for example, Falling Water is an essential part of
its proper appreciation. It is not surprising that books on architecture have diagrams
and illustrations of the insides of structures as well as of their outsides. Nor is it
surprising that there is something essentially frustrating about appreciating the
exterior of, for example, a cathedral or a small country church and then discovering
that it is locked, that we are barred from appreciating the inside—and thus unable
to complete our appreciation of the work.
The appreciative significance of the “insidedness” of works of architecture has two
related ramifications. First, it further elaborates the importance of “form follows
function”; it makes explicit that this slogan typically spans the gap, as it were,
between inside and outside, for, as noted, although function is typically carried out
inside a work, much of its most appreciable form is outside. Second, it raises a
further question of fit in the appreciation of architecture. In addition to the issue of
the fit of the work with its site, there is also that of the fit of the inside of the work
with its outside. The upshot of these two ramifications is that the question of fit is
really a question of a three-way fit, among inside, outside, and site, and, since much
of the fit is accomplished by form, this larger question of fit may be characterized as
whether or not fit follows function.
39
Some examples illuminate aspects of this larger
question. We previously considered cases of lack of fit between the outside of an
architectural work and its site, such as with certain postmodern buildings. There are
similar examples of lack of fit between outside and functional inside, and the most
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 211
dramatic kinds of cases are the most revealing. Consider the disconcerting
experience of entering an old city-center post office or a grand railroad station only
to find that it has been gutted and filled with trendy new boutiques and restaurants.
Such expediencies may be necessary to save the “building,” but what is saved is only
the shell, half a work of architecture that can no longer be fully appreciated due to
the lack of any real fit between the outside and the functional inside. An equally
disconcerting but in a sense reverse experience can be had in the National Gallery of
Canada, where deep inside, surrounded by rooms of Canadian and international
paintings, one can enter and appreciate the complete and completely intact interior
of Ottawa’s old Rideau Street Convent Chapel. This is the egg without the shell.
Function, location, existence: the path of appreciation
In the preceding three sections, we considered three challenges posed by works of
architecture but not typically by other art forms: the question of existence, the
question of location, and the question of function. Each requires us to come to
realizations about and to thus make appreciable a certain dimension of works of
architecture: the first, the very existence of the work, the second, the fit of the work
with its site, and the third, the fit of the site and the outside of the work with its
functional inside. The conclusions of these three sections can now be brought
together to outline a general way of meeting these challenges. In the first section, the
discussion of Tolstoy’s concerns about art suggests that the core idea necessary for
addressing the question of existence involves the functional nature of architecture.
This suggestion is elaborated and reinforced in the following two sections. In the
second section, the question of existence—to be or not to be—is expanded and
deepened to that of to be or not to be here, and thus it is aligned with the question
of fit. In the third section, the issue of fit is similarly expanded and deepened into a
three-way fit, and the idea that form must follow function is developed so as to
suggest that fit must follow function. The upshot is a proposition that Tolstoy,
Sullivan, and others would have endorsed: that the functionality of works of
architecture is the key to all three concerns. In short, realizations about the function
of a work of architecture are among the most significant means by which to make
appreciable, first, the fit of the inside of the work with its outside, second, the fit of
the work to its site, and, last, the very existence of the work.
Demonstrating how the appeal to the function of a work of architecture
facilitates the appreciation of its three-way fit and its existence is relatively easy with
works such as Falling Water. Perhaps this is because Falling Water is the creation of
Wright, who, as a disciple of Sullivan, apparently designed the work such that, in
Sullivan’s words, “the shape, form, outward expression, design or whatever we may
choose” follows the function of the building. Thus, it is easily and straightforwardly
appreciable in light of its function. After all, Falling Water is a weekend “cottage,” a
place for a leisurely retreat, for a return to nature. From this function its causal yet
intimate blending of inner and outer spaces, its “almost total fusion” with the
natural rocky and wooded site, and its very existence on that site in the first place all
212 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
follow smoothly. Moreover, it is not surprising that many twentieth-century
modernist works lend themselves to a similar treatment, as do classic earlier works,
especially the religious and public buildings that make up much of the history of
architecture. However, works that strongly confront us with their existence and
their apparent lack of fit, such as some of the postmodern towers considered
previously, are more difficult cases. As noted, Johnson’s AT&T Building leaves us
pondering the desirability of its existence and, as we saw at the end of the third
section of this chapter, buildings of the postmodernism of reaction, such as
Johnson’s and Burgee’s New England Life Building, leave many observers
pondering their status as works of the art of architecture.
To establish the importance of function concerning such hard cases,
consideration of another postmodern work is worthwhile. Especially illuminating is
Michael Grave’s fortress-like Portland Building.
40
Even more so than some other
postmodern structures, this work has been questioned concerning both its existence
and its status as architecture.
41
Initially the building strikes many observers as
fantastical, if not preposterous. Along with other flamboyant features, it was
designed to have two multistoried rectangular, false columns on the main facades, a
representational sculpture, Portlandia, over the main entry, and numerous garlands
adorning the side facades. In such a case, the appeal to function may not make the
work more appreciable on all counts. However, it does somewhat enhance our
appreciation to know that the structure is the Portland City Public Services
Building. This realization helps us to appreciate, in light of the building’s overall
function, the role of the above-mentioned seemingly self-indulgent features. Thus,
for example, we come to appreciate the columns as an invocation of public gates,
the sculpture as a reinterpretation of a motif on the city seal, and the garlands as
traditional symbols of welcome. In short, although the realization of function may
not address all aspects of such cases, it yet appears to deepen and enrich appreciation
of even the most difficult examples. And in the last analysis, approaching works in
this way is perhaps more fruitful than attempting to exclude them from the art of
architecture.
In light of these observations, it is now possible to draw some very general
conclusions about the appropriate aesthetic appreciation of works of architecture: to
outline in a general way what might be called the path of appreciation for a work of
architecture; and in doing so, hopefully to shed some light on some of those things
that are especially rewarding in the appreciation of architecture. Consider the
following scenario. We confront a particular work; it proclaims “Here I stand,
posing for us the three challenges of its existence, its location, and its function. It
calls on us to consider, as it were, why is it standing at all, why is it standing here,
and what is it, quite literally, doing here? A significant and proper part of our
appropriate appreciation of it, therefore, must involve coming to realizations that
will answer these questions, solve these problems. However, we cannot address these
questions as we might address the questions posed by a work such as Autumn
Foliage, that is, by responding to “Here I stand” with the naive question “Where do
I stand?” and after determining the right spot proceeding to contemplate the work
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 213
from that spot. Basically this is because, if what has been previously noted is correct,
the key to all three questions posed by a work of architecture is the answer to the
last, the question of its function. And the function of a work of architecture is not
readily and straightforwardly, if at all, realizable by simply contemplating the work
from a particular spot in front of it.
That the function of a work of architecture is not typically easily realizable simply
by static contemplation relates to a number of the features of architecture noted in
the preceding sections. For example, given that appreciation of architecture is not an
insular experience and that a work’s function is typically nonartistic, the function of
the work is unlikely to be found simply in its contemplation. In this sense the
function of architecture is unlike the function Tolstoy attributes to art in general. It
is not a function that acts directly on the appreciator, and thus it is not realizable by
simple static contemplation of the work by the appreciator. Rather it is the kind of
function that the appreciator must realize by experiencing the function itself.
Moreover, it is not completely adequate simply to know the function of the work
and to contemplate it in light of that knowledge. Aesthetic appreciation involves
realizations achieved in experiencing the work: to appropriately appreciate Autumn
Foliage it is not sufficient to simply know that it is a representational work and what
it represents; rather this knowledge must be essentially involved in our experience of
it. Similarly, with architecture our realizations about the function of a work must be
involved in our experience of it. Thus, it is not in fact sufficient just to know that a
structure is, for example, a cathedral in order for its functionality to fully facilitate
our appreciation of it as a work of architecture. Ideally, appropriate appreciation
would involve the realization of its religious function by direct experience of that
function in action, for instance, by experiencing, although not necessarily taking
part in, a mass within the cathedral itself.
However, the main reason that the function of a work of architecture is not easily
realizable by static contemplation is not simply that its function is nonartistic in
nature nor that its function must be experienced in action. Rather it is that this
nonartistic action normally takes place within the structure. The function of a work
is typically performed and thus typically experienced inside the work. It follows that
the appreciation of architecture is ideally a process, a path of appreciation that leads
to the experience of the function inside the work. Such appreciation is in this way
somewhat similar to the appreciation of a literary or dramatic thriller or to the
appreciation of a symphony, each of which leads to a climax. Perhaps this is why
architecture is sometimes called frozen music. However, with architecture the path
of appreciation is not as fully specified by the work as it is in the case of these other
art forms. Rather appreciators must make their own way from the initial
confrontation with the work to the experience of the work’s inner function.
Typically, appreciators move from the outside to the inside: first, approaching the
work from a distance, second, closing with it and perhaps circling it, and, only last,
entering the work. And in one sense this is the natural path of appreciation in that
on confrontation with a work the questions of existence, location, and function
logically arise in that order. Thus, in approaching, we experience a work’s existence,
214 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
in closing and circling, we experience its outer form and its fit with its site, and,
lastly, upon entering, we experience the fit between its outer and inner space and
experientially realize its function. As with the thriller or the symphony, the climax
comes near the end of the path of appreciation.
There is, however, a further complication concerning architecture’s path of
appreciation, somewhat of a paradox that contributes to the special nature and
richness of the aesthetic experience of works of architecture. It is that although on
confrontation with a work the questions of its existence, location, and function
naturally arise in that particular order, in our experience of the work the key
realizations for addressing these questions—that is, those realizations concerning its
function—typically come last. As noted, the physical path of appreciation typically
runs from outside to inside. Thus, while the physical path flows in one direction,
the path of appreciative application of the realizations gained from following that
physical path flows in the opposite direction. This latter path, in one sense the real
path of appreciation, involves a series of realizations running from the work’s
function back to, one after the other, the fit of its inner with its outer space, the fit
of the work with its site, and, lastly, the very existence of the work. In short, the
aesthetic appreciation of a work of architecture is an experiential process that is not
only not completed until the end is reached, but also not completed until that end
is read back into the whole process such that the overall experience is thereby
deepened, enriched, and completed. This kind of convoluted and somewhat self-
reflective mode of aesthetic appreciation, although not unique to the experience of
architecture, is a facet of what makes such experience especially rewarding.
Notes
1 I do not defend this notion of aesthetic appreciation here, but see my “Appreciating
Art and Appreciating Nature,” in Salim Kemal and Ivan Gaskell (eds) Landscape,
Natural Beauty and the Arts, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 199–
227 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 7) and “Between Nature and Art” (in this
volume, Chapter 8).
2Tom Thomson, Autumn Foliage, 1916, 10 ½ by 8 ½ inches, The National Gallery of
Canada, Ottawa, Canada.
3 William Shakespeare, Hamlet, Act III, scene I, lines 56–88 [1601], in G.B.Harrison
(ed.) Shakespeare: Major Plays and the Sonnets, New York, Harcourt, Brace & World,
1948, p. 626.
4 Ibid., p. 626.
5 Philip Johnson, the American Telephone and Telegraph Building, 1980–83, New
York. I think that in general works of architecture are perhaps less well known than are
those of many other major art forms. Consequently, throughout this chapter I attempt
to employ examples that, due to either their location, historical significance, or notoriety,
have attained widespread recognition. Also, in accompanying footnotes I indicate the
locations and construction dates of all the works discussed in the chapter.
6 Frank Lloyd Wright, Falling Water (The Kaufmann House), 1935–37, Bear Run,
Pennsylvania; Taliesin West, 1934–38, Phoenix, Arizona.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 215
7Leo N. Tolstoy, What is Art? [1896], Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill, 1960, see especially
Chapter 1.
8 Ibid., p. 13.
9 Ibid., p. 15.
10 Ibid., p. 150.
11 Martin Luther, as quoted in Roland H.Bainton, Here I Stand: A Life of Martin Luther,
New York, Mentor, 1955, p. 144.
12 Ludwig Mies van der Rohe, with Philip Johnson, Seagram Building, 1958, New York;
Gordon Bunshaft (Skidmore, Owings and Merrill), Union Carbide Corporation
Building and Chase Manhattan Bank, 1960, New York.
13 Le Corbusier [Charles Edouard Jeanneret], Villa Savoye, 1929–31, Poissy, France.
14 Richard Serra, Tilted Arc, 1983, Jacob Javits Federal Building Plaza, New York.
15 Richard Serra, transcript of the New York City hearing [1985], reprinted from
Harper’s, July, 1985, in Margaret Battin, John Fisher, Ronald Moore, and Anita
Silvers (eds) Puzzles About Art: An Aesthetics Casebook, New York, St Martin’s, 1989,
p. 182.
16 Elizabeth C.Barker, “Artworks on the Land,” Art in America, 1976, vol. 64, pp. 92–6
reprinted in Alan Sonfist (ed.) Art in the Land: A Critical Anthology of Environmental Art,
New York, Dutton, 1983, p. 75. The three works are Robert Smithson, Spiral Jetty,
1970, Great Salt Lake, Utah; Michael Heizer, Double Negative, 1969–71, Virgin River
Mesa, Nevada; Complex One, 1972–76, South-central Nevada. I discuss other
ramifications of the relationships of such works to their sites in “Is Environmental Art
an Aesthetic Affront to Nature?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1986, vol. 16, pp.
635–50 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 10).
17 Barker, op. cit., p. 79.
18 Serra, transcript of the New York City hearing, op. cit., p. 182.
19 Judge Dominick DiCarlo, transcript of the New York City hearing, op. cit., p. 183.
20 Ibid., p. 183.
21 Kenneth Frampton, Modern Architecture: A Critical History, New York, Oxford
University Press, 1980, p. 189.
22 Ibid., p. 237.
23 Robert A.M.Stern, quoted in Ada Louise Huxtable, “The Troubled State of Modern
Architecture,” New York Review of Books, May 1, 1980, pp. 22–9.
24 See, for example, Steven C.Bourassa, The Aesthetics of Landscape, London, Belhaven,
1991, pp. 136–9, or Hal Foster, “Postmodernism: A Preface,” in Hal Foster (ed.) The
Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture, Port Townsend, Bay Press, 1983, p. xii
25 See Kenneth Frampton, “Towards a Critical Regionalism: Six Points for an
Architecture of Resistance,” in Foster, op. cit., pp. 16–30.
26 Paul Goldberger, “A Tale of Two Towers on Boston’s Boylston Street,” New York Times,
January 24,1988, p. (H)31. This excellent example and Goldberger’s treatment of it
were brought to my attention by Bourassa.
27 Ibid., p. (H)31.
28 Ibid., p. (H)31.
29 Mary McLeod, “Architecture,” in Stanley Trachtenberg (ed.) The Postmodern Moment,
London, Greenwood, 1985, p. 34.
30 Huxtable, op. cit., p. 26.
31 Goldberger, op. cit., p. (H)34, Huxtable, op. cit., p. 26 and Mcleod, op. cit., p. 42.
216 EXISTENCE, LOCATION, AND FUNCTION
32 Romaldo Giurgola, “Architecture: More Than a Building,Architecture Australia,
1987, vol. 76, pp. 43–6; quoted in Bourassa, op. cit., p. 144.
33 Huxtable, op. cit., p. 26.
34 Louis Sullivan, “The Tall Office Building Artistically Considered” [1896], reprinted in
Tim and Charlotte Benton (eds) Form and Function: A Source Book for the History of
Architecture and Design 1890–1939, London, Open University Press, 1975, pp. 13–14.
I apply Sullivan’s ideas to other matters in “On Appreciating Agricultural Landscapes,”
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1985, vol. 43, pp. 301–12 (reproduced in this
volume, Chapter 12).
35 Ludwig Mies van der Rohe, quoted in Frampton, Modern Architecture, op. cit., p. 163.
Likewise Walter Gropius proclaims: “We want…an architecture whose function is
clearly recognizable in the relations of its form.” In general see the “First Proclamation
of the Weimar Bauhaus,” in H. Bayer (ed.) Bauhaus; 1919–1928, New York, Museum
of Modern Art, 1938; reprinted in Larry L.Ligo, The Concept of Function in Twentieth-
Century Architectural Criticism, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Research Press,
1984, p. 12.
36 Le Corbusier, “The New Spirit in Architecture” [1924], reprinted in Benton, op. cit.,
pp. 132–3.
37 Sullivan, op. cit., pp. 11–13.
38 Maya Ying Lin and Jan Scruggs, Vietnam Veterans Memorial, 1982, Washington, DC.
39 I develop a related notion, that of functional fit, in “Reconsidering the Aesthetics of
Architecture,” The Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1986, vol. 20, pp. 21–7.
40 Michael Graves, City of Portland Public Services Building, 1980–83, Portland,
Oregon.
41 For example, architectural critic Alan Colquhoun states: “What the building is saying,
with a power and intensity that are almost unique and not at all banal, is that
architecture, as it has come down to us from history, is now impossible. See Kurt
Forster, Arthur Drexler, Vincent Scully, Alan Colquhoun, Allan Greenberg, Philip
Johnson, and John Burgee, “The Portland Building,” Skyline, January, 1983, p. 19.
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 217
218
14
LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
Hillerman’s landscapes and aesthetic relevance
In this concluding chapter, I revisit some of the themes introduced and discussed
throughout this volume: themes such as formalism, aesthetic relevance, scientific
knowledge, functional descriptions, postmodern appreciation, as well as others. I do
so in order to suggest an overall framework for the aesthetic appreciation of both
our natural and human environments. I approach the construction of this
framework by way of the landscape descriptions we find in literature, asking about
the relevance of such descriptions to the aesthetic appreciation of the landscapes so
described. I focus on one particular example: the landscape descriptions of
contemporary mystery writer Tony Hillerman.
The Tony Hillerman Companion introduces Hillerman’s work with the following
remark: “For more than twenty years, Tony Hillerman has been painting with his
words, a vivid landscape of the beautiful, but enigmatic American Southwest and its
native peoples.”
1
Hillerman’s best-known works, of course, are modern-day, murder
mystery novels featuring Navajo Tribal Policemen, Lieutenant Joe Leaphorn and
Officer Jim Chee. However, it is no surprise that The Hillerman Companion
mentions the landscape first and foremost. The desert landscape of the American
Southwest is as much a player in Hillerman’s novels as are Navajo Policemen
Leaphorn and Chee. Hillerman himself observes: “Quite a few people read me for
the landscape… They live in New York or some other place…and it reminds them
of that great southern Utah and northern Arizona and Four Corners country.”
2
In this chapter I use what one Hillerman commentator calls “Hillerman’s
trademark desert setting” as an example for the study of landscape appreciation.
3
I
consider Hillerman’s vivid descriptions of the landscapes of the Four Corners
country of Utah, Arizona, Colorado, and New Mexico, reflecting on how these
descriptions enliven our aesthetic appreciation of the desert landscape itself. There
can be little doubt that Hillerman’s writings do in fact engender and enhance
landscape appreciation. His landscape descriptions are universally praised by his
reviewers for their power and appeal and characterized with words and phrases such
as “overpowering,” “breathtaking,” “mesmerizing,” “shimmering with realism,” and
“making the desert come alive.”
4
One reviewer even extols them as “so evocative of
the land around the Four Corners area…that even if you’ve never been there, you’ll
think you have!”
5
The philosophical issue for which I use Hillerman’s landscape descriptions as case
studies is one of the central problems in aesthetics: the question of aesthetic
relevance. As noted in Chapters 7 and 8, it is the question of what is relevant to the
appropriate aesthetic appreciation of any particular object of such appreciation. Of
course, aesthetic appreciation by its nature focuses on that which the object of
appreciation presents to the senses. Thus, the question of aesthetic relevance is more
precisely the question of what, if anything, of that which the object itself does not
present to the senses is relevant to its appropriate aesthetic appreciation. One of the
architects of modern aesthetic theory puts the issue as follows: “Is it ever ‘relevant’ to
aesthetic experience to have thoughts or images or bits of knowledge which are not
present within the object itself? If these are ever relevant, under what conditions are
they so?”
6
Hillerman’s landscape descriptions bring the issue of aesthetic relevance sharply
to a head. Consider this example:
…the sun was just dipping behind the Chuskas now. On the vast, rolling
prairie that led away from the highway toward the black shape of Ship Rock
every clump of sagebrush, every juniper, every snakeweed, every hummock of
bunch grass cast its long blue shadow—an infinity of lines of darkness
undulating across the glowing landscape. Beautiful. Chee’s spirit lifted…
[the] earth sloped away to the south—empty, rolling gray-tan grassland with
the black line of the highway receding toward the horizon like the mark of a
ruling pen. Miles to the south, the sun reflected from the windshield of a
northbound vehicle, a blink of brightness. Ship Rock rose like an oversized,
free-form Gothic cathedral just to the right, miles away but looking close. Ten
miles ahead Table Mesa sailed through its sea of buffalo grass, reminding
Chee of the ultimate aircraft carrier. Across the highway from it, slanting
sunlight illuminated the ragged black form of Barber Peak, a volcanic throat
to geologists, a meeting place for witches in local lore.
7
Initially, we might have a mixed reaction to such a landscape description. On the
one hand, much of the information contained in it seemingly cannot but enhance
and enrich our aesthetic appreciation of the particular landscape it describes. Yet on
the other hand, it is in large part comprised of “thoughts or images or bits of
knowledge which are not present within” the landscape itself. Is any of this “outside
information” really relevant to the appropriate aesthetic appreciation of the
described landscape? Or is all of it perhaps relevant? How or how not? Why or why
not?
8
220 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
Classic formalism and postmodern landscape appreciation
To address such questions, it is useful to briefly reiterate some of the background to
the issue of aesthetic relevance elaborated in Chapter 8. The above-noted classic
formulation comes from the mid-twentieth century and thus from the heyday of
modern analytic aesthetics. As such, it stands, somewhat as a fulcrum, between
earlier formalist approaches to the problem and later postmodern approaches. As
elaborated in Chapter 8, these two alternatives illustrate the extremes in answering
the question of aesthetic relevance.
9
On the one hand, the classic formalist view is
essentially purist, characteristically holding that only that which an object presents
to an appreciator’s senses is relevant to its aesthetic appreciation. All “outside
information” is at best irrelevant and at worse harmful interference with pure
aesthetic experience. On the other hand, there are the excesses of the postmodern
approach, which seemingly holds that anything and everything that an appreciator
brings to an object is relevant to its aesthetic appreciation, for in an important sense
the object of appreciation is created anew in light of that which the appreciator
contributes to it.
Of course, we live in an increasingly postmodern world. Thus, it seems that the
relevance of Hillerman’s landscape descriptions to our aesthetic appreciation of
landscapes should pose no problem. Hillerman simply provides us with “evocative”
and “mesmerizing” new “thoughts or images or bits of knowledge” about a landscape,
and such thoughts, images, and knowledge, although “not present within” the
landscape itself, yet enhance our appreciation of it. His descriptions, as noted,
“shimmer with realism” and “make the desert come alive.” In this way, they
seemingly constitute resources in light of which each of us can recreate the
landscapes of the Southwest for ourselves. Indeed, as also noted, these descriptions
are “so evocative…that even if you’ve never been there, you’ll think you have.” The
implication seems to be that Hillerman’s landscape descriptions are so powerful and
compelling that they allow us to create for ourselves and appreciate a landscape
without even seeing it!
Should we then simply embrace the postmodern alternative and forget any
concerns about aesthetic relevance? Should we simply sit back and enjoy
Hillerman’s assistance in creating anew the landscapes of the American Southwest?
Such an approach is tempting, especially in light of the compelling and evocative
nature of Hillerman’s descriptions. However, it may be hasty. There are two
considerations that should give us pause. The first is that, as noted in Chapter 8, we
need not simply accept the either/or situation suggested by the two alternatives of
formalism and postmodernism. There is, of course, a spectrum of possible positions
concerning the question of aesthetic relevance running between these two extremes.
Perhaps the correct view lies somewhere on this spectrum. Thus, I propose to
consider the question of aesthetic relevance by beginning with formalism and, by
means of examining a number of Hillerman’s descriptions, moving toward
postmodernism. How far such an examination takes us may indicate the most
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 221
plausible position—and, as an added benefit, suggest somewhat of a general
framework for landscape appreciation.
The second reason for not hastily embracing the postmodern alternative has to do
with Hillerman’s descriptions themselves. As noted, they are widely acclaimed for
their power and appeal. Moreover, much of their power and appeal is a function of
their richness and diversity. Hillerman’s landscape descriptions are not simply one-
dimensional; they operate on many different levels and incorporate many different
themes. Consider again the passage quoted above. It mentions beauty, of course,
but it also speaks of ragged black forms, undulating lines, long blue shadows, and
slanting sunlight. It refers to sagebrush, juniper, snakeweed, and buffalo grass, to
Ship Rock, Table Mesa, Barber Peak, and the Chuskas, and to highways, ruling
pens, Gothic cathedrals, and aircraft carriers. And it alludes to the volcanic throats of
geologists, the meeting places of Navajo witches, and the feelings and associations of
Navajo Tribal Policeman Jim Chee. Given this richness and diversity, it is quite
probable that although some of the themes of such a description are aesthetically
relevant to the appreciation of the landscape described, others are not. Thus, I
proceed from formalism toward postmodernism by examining the different kinds of
descriptive themes that can be identified in a selection of passages from Hillerman’s
novels.
Formal descriptions and ordinary descriptions
I identify nine different themes in Hillerman’s landscape descriptions, which I initially
divide into three general groups: what I call, although I do not want anything in
particular to depend upon these labels, the formal, the factual, and the cultural.
First, consider the formal; by this I mean the component of these descriptions that
focuses primarily on forms, that is, on the shapes, lines, and colors that are
traditionally favored by formalists. For example, the previously quoted passage
characterizes the landscape in terms of “ragged black shapes” and “undulating lines.”
Consider another illustration:
North, over Sleeping Ute Mountain in Colorado, over Utah’s Abajo
Mountains, great thunderheads were reaching toward their evening climax.
Their tops, reflecting in the direct sun, were snowy white and the long
streamers of ice crystals blown from them seemed to glitter. But at lower
levels the light that struck them had been filtered through the clouds over the
Chuskas and turned into shades of rose, pink, and red. Lower still, the failing
light mottled them from pale blue-gray to the deepest blue. Overhead, the
streaks of high-level cirrus clouds were being ignited by the sunset. They
drove through a fiery twilight.
10
Concerning the formal component of this and similar descriptions, I suggest that two
points are quite obvious. The first is in concert with classic formalism. It is that,
insofar as indicating such formal aspects of any landscape is possible, doing so seems
222 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
clearly relevant to the aesthetic appreciation of the landscape in question.
11
For
example, describing thunderheads from their top to their bottom in descending
levels of color, from snowy white, through shades of rose, pink, and red, to mottled
pale blue-gray and deep blue certainly draws our appreciation to a dimension of the
landscape that is seemingly at the very centre of aesthetic experience. What could be
more paradigmatic of the aesthetic appreciation of landscapes than the appreciation
of a fiery sunset?
The second point, however, is contra formalism. It is that aesthetic appreciation
of landscapes cannot be limited to this formal level. Classic formalism, as noted, is
essentially purist, holding that only that which is presented to the senses is
aesthetically relevant. Thus, the formalist typically limits aesthetic appreciation to
the formal dimensions of objects of appreciation, contending that when and insofar
as appreciation is informed by reference to anything beyond the formal it is no
longer aesthetic in nature. However, as argued in Chapters 2 and 3, such purism
cannot be maintained. This is particularly evident when we consider landscape
descriptions that are as rich and as complex as are Hillerman’s. In such descriptions
it is clear that their formal components are inextricably intertwined with the second
group of the three previously distinguished groups of descriptive themes, what I
term the factual. To illustrate this, I turn to this component.
I suggest that at least four different descriptive themes can be distinguished within
the factual component of Hillerman’s landscape descriptions: the ordinary, the
scientific, the historical, and the functional. By the first, the ordinary, I mean simply
the characterization of landscapes with commonplace descriptive terms such as, in
the previously example, “mountain,” “cloud,” and “sunset.” This aspect of
Hillerman’s descriptions is sufficient to illustrate the point that aesthetic
appreciation of landscapes cannot be limited to formal dimensions. Consider again
the two previously quoted passages. In each Hillerman describes the basic features of
a landscape as they are illuminated by a sunset. In considering these descriptions, it
becomes clear that what is described and what we in our aesthetic experience of
landscapes appreciate is not simply, for example, black shapes or shades of rose,
pink, and red or fiery colors. Rather what is described and what we appreciate are the
black shapes of mountains, rose, pink, and red clouds, and fiery sunsets. Hillerman’s
descriptions bring out the fact that the shapes, shades, and colors are inseparably
connected to the mountains, clouds, and sunsets of which they are predicated.
Indeed, this gives his descriptions a sense of solidity and concreteness, which
contributes to the way in which they “make the desert come alive,” and “shimmer with
realism.”
This line of argument is developed in more general terms in Chapter 2 and as
such can be put as follows: we do not simply appreciate lines, shapes, and colors,
but rather the lines, shapes, and colors of particular things. This is in part because the
very identity and the specification of that which we appreciate at the formal level is
in large measure a function of factual descriptions of at least the ordinary kind. We
cannot access the former without the latter and, thus, the appreciation of the former
brings with it the appreciation of the latter. Therefore, since the former are
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 223
aesthetically relevant so too are the latter. Concerning the problem of aesthetic
relevance, this means that at least mundane and commonplace “outside information
such as that we are viewing mountains, clouds, and sunsets is relevant to aesthetic
appreciation, and is not, contra formalism, at best irrelevant and at worse harmful
interference with pure aesthetic experience. In short, the dependence of the formal
aspects of landscapes on ordinary descriptive terms takes us on the first step away
from classic formalism and toward a position of the postmodern kind.
Other factual landscape descriptions
What about the other three themes that make up the factual component of
Hillerman’s landscape descriptions, that is, scientific, historical, and functional
descriptions? Do they constitute irrelevant “outside information” that only
interferes with aesthetic appreciation of landscapes, or are they, like ordinary
descriptions, inextricably involved in such appreciation? I suggest that these other
kinds of factual descriptions are, just as ordinary descriptions, importantly
aesthetically relevant. This is in part because, since these different kinds of
descriptions are all factual in a more or less straightforward sense, there is no hard
and fast line that can be drawn between ordinary descriptions and the other three
kinds. Ordinary descriptions blend into scientific, historical, and functional
descriptions in such a way that the aesthetic relevance of the former necessarily
bestows such relevance on the latter. If the former are aesthetically relevant so too
are the latter.
In Hillerman’s writing, the continuum from ordinary to the other kinds of
factual descriptions is especially clear concerning scientific descriptions, that is,
characterizations of landscapes in the terminology of the natural sciences.
12
For
example, Hillerman’s passages frequently involve geological characterizations of the
landscape. Consider the following:
The sun was almost on the horizon, shining through a narrow slot not closed
in the west between cloud and earth. The slanting light outlined every
crevasse in shadowy relief, making apparent the broken ruggedness of the ridge.
It rose, ragged and tumbled shapes in black and gray, out of a long sloping
hummock—what a million years or so of erosion had left of the mountain of
volcanic ash that had once buried the volcano’s core… It wasn’t really a
mountain. Technically it was probably a volcanic throat—another of those
ragged upthrusts of black basalt that jutted out of the prairie here and there
east of the Chuskas.
13
This example illustrates the way in which Hillerman’s descriptions blend the
ordinary and the scientific. The geological characterization given in terms such as
“erosion,” “volcanic ash,” “volcanic throat,” and “basalt,” is simply an extension of
the ordinary description using terms such as “crevasse,” “ridge,” “hummock,” and
“mountain.” The scientific description is more technical, somewhat finer-grained,
224 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
and certainly theoretically richer than is the ordinary description, but it is not
essentially different concerning its relevance to aesthetic experience. For purposes of
aesthetic appreciation, a term such as “volcanic throat” performs the same function
as a term such as “mountain,” provided, of course, that the appreciator is familiar
with geological terminology. Moreover, given such familiarity, insofar as the
scientific description alters appreciation, it does not change it from aesthetic
appreciation to something else, but rather only from a shallower to a deeper
appreciation. In this sense scientific descriptions are not only not aesthetically
irrelevant, they actually enrich and enhance appreciation. Indeed, Hillerman’s
frequent use of geological as well as biological, meteorological, and other kinds of
scientific information in his landscape descriptions is one of the factors contributing
to their widely acclaimed power and appeal.
Concerning the remaining two themes that constitute the factual component of
Hillerman’s landscape descriptions, that is, historical and functional descriptions,
much the same can be said. They, like the scientific, blend with ordinary
descriptions, and, rather than being irrelevant, actually enrich aesthetic
appreciation. Consider the following example:
The Indian Health Service Hospital at Gallup is one of the prides of this huge
federal bureaucracy—modern, attractive, well located…the view from
[Leaphorn’s] window…was superb. The Health Service had located the
hospital high on the slope overlooking Gallup from the south. Over the little
hump in the sheet produced by his toes, Leaphorn could see the endless
stream of semitrailers moving along Interstate 40. Beyond the highway,
intercontinental train traffic rolled east and west on the Santa Fe main trunk.
Above and beyond the railroads, beyond the clutter of east Gallup, the red
cliffs of Mesa de los Lobos rose—their redness diminished a little by the blue
haze of distance, and above them was the gray-green shape of the high
country of the Navajo borderlands, where the Big Reservation faded into
Checkerboard Reservation.
14
Although this example is in many ways unlike the three previously quoted “sunset”
passages, it is yet a landscape description of power and beauty. Its main difference
from those descriptions is that it characterizes the landscape not with scientific
terminology and not simply with formal and ordinary words and phrases. Rather it
describes the landscape with historical and functional terms, using words and
phrases such as “semitrailers,” “Interstate 40,” “highway,” “intercontinental train
traffic,” “Santa Fe main trunk,” “railroads,” “east Gallop,” “Navajo borderlands,”
and “Checkerboard Reservation.” These terms capture the landscape in historical
and functional categories, which are, of course, completely appropriate given the
landscape in question. Moreover, given that landscape, this description, in moving
beyond ordinary descriptions, performs the same service as do scientific
descriptions, that is, it enriches and enhances appreciation. One need only consider
contemplating the landscape of east Gallop and the hills beyond without the factual
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 225
information contained in the functional and historical components of Hillerman’s
description to realize the extent to which this is the case.
The analogy with art argument
The contention that historical and functional landscape descriptions, as well as
scientific ones, rather than being irrelevant, actually enhance aesthetic appreciation
does not follow solely from the fact that descriptions in scientific, historical, and
functional terms blend with those in ordinary terms. This contention also finds
support in a line of argument that is implicit throughout much of this volume and
may be called the Analogy with Art Argument. This line of argument involves two
basic assumptions. The first is that at the most fundamental level the nature of
aesthetic appreciation is essentially uniform across the appreciation of different
kinds of objects and, thus, that at this level the aesthetic appreciation of landscapes
and that of works of art mirror one another. The second basic assumption is that in
the aesthetic appreciation of works of art certain kinds of historical, cultural, and
artistic information is aesthetically relevant and enhances appreciation. The specific
information concerns answers to questions such as why the work was produced, how
it was produced, and why it was produced in the way in which it was. The relevance
of this kind of information to the aesthetic appreciation of works of art is argued for
in Chapter 8, where it is termed the “history of production” of the work. In short,
then, the second assumption is that the history of production of any work of art is
importantly aesthetically relevant.
It follows from the two premises of the Analogy with Art Argument that in the
aesthetic appreciation of a landscape, the analogue of a work of art’s history of
production is aesthetically relevant and enhances appreciation. But what is a
landscape’s history of production? As noted in Chapter 8, at the basic level, this
analogous history of production for any landscape is the information given in
scientific descriptions of the formation and the development of the landscape, such
as, for instance, Hillerman’s geological descriptions. However, landscapes,
somewhat unlike works of art, do not have a final completion point; they are
inherently unfinished. Therefore, their ongoing development is also a part of their
histories of production. This ongoing development is recorded not only in scientific
descriptions but also in historical and functional descriptions, such as Hillerman’s
description of the landscape of east Gallop. The history of production of the
landscape of Gallop continues into the present and is recorded in the descriptions of
its recent history and its currents uses. Thus, historical and functional descriptions
that tell of this history of production are aesthetically relevant and enhance aesthetic
appreciation.
The way in which the history of production of a landscape is ongoing and in
particular how historical and functional descriptions of it enhance aesthetic
appreciation is especially evident in the case of agricultural landscapes. Consider the
following example:
226 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
On the north side of Highway 44, the ocean of sagebrush stretched away into
the Angel Peak badlands. On the south side of the highway where the NAI
[Navajo Agricultural Industries] held domain, the black-gray-silver of the sage
had been replaced by mile after mile of green, the shade depending on the
crop and the season. Dense stands of cornstalks alternated with thousands of
acres of potato fields, followed by great circles of kelly green alfalfa, and
incredible expanses of onions, watermelons, cantaloupes, cucumbers, sugar
beets, whatever crop the market demanded. And all of this had been made
possible by a rare and seemingly small Navajo victory over white
landgrabbers… While the whites had taken nearly all the good bottom land,
the Navajos still owned the water [of the San Juan River] and an infinity of
worthless high desert hills. Now, from planting season until harvest, that water
was showered out over the desert through elaborate mobile sprinkler systems.
It turned the hills lush and green and produced jobs for hundreds of
Navajos.
15
This passage describes a particular agricultural landscape in a number of aesthetically
relevant ways having to do with the function to which that landscape is currently put
as well as the history that made this function possible. Much of the passage is a
functional description in terms of the crops—corn, potatoes, alfalfa, onions,
watermelons, cantaloupes, cucumbers, sugar beets—which the Navajo Agricultural
Industries grow on the desert landscape by means of irrigation from the San Juan
River. However, there is also reference to the history that made this project possible
—a history of confrontation with and ultimately victory over white settlers who
attempted to encroach on this land during the last century. Moreover, the way in
which this history and use of the land has shaped this agricultural landscape is
underscored by the contrast with the natural sagebrush landscape to the north of
Highway 44. Such functional and historical descriptions record and recount the
history of production of the landscape in question and thus, according to the
Analogy with Art Argument, are not simply aesthetically relevant but also enhance
and enrich the appreciation of that landscape.
Returning now to the general question of aesthetic relevance, in light of the
foregoing observations, I tentatively conclude that mundane and commonplace
information, such as that we are viewing mountains, clouds, and sunsets, is not all
the “outside information” that is relevant to aesthetic appreciation. Equally relevant,
and perhaps even more so if appreciation is to be rich and deep, is that we are
contemplating, for example, a basalt volcanic throat exposed by a million years of
erosion or intercontinental train traffic rolling east and west on the Santa Fe main
trunk. Similarly relevant is information such as that we are viewing the
Checkerboard Reservation in the high country of the Navajo borderlands or the
expanses of onions, watermelons, cantaloupes, cucumbers, and sugar beets made
possible by the irrigation projects of the Navajo Agricultural Industries. Such
examples of “outside information,” just as the more mundane and commonplace
instances, are both factual and descriptive, that is, all such “outside information”
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 227
involves factual information that describes the landscape in ways that influence how
we see it. We might say that such information meets a descriptive condition, which
we can formulate as follows: to be aesthetically relevant to the appreciation of a
landscape, “outside information” contained in a landscape description must be
descriptive of the actual landscape and descriptive in such a way that awareness of it
affects and directs perception of that landscape. Such a descriptive condition might
constitute part of a more general answer to the question of aesthetic relevance, for
although it is clearly not sufficient for aesthetic relevance, it is seemingly a necessary
condition. I return to this point below.
The conclusion that in light of their factual and descriptive natures all of the
different components that we have so far considered are aesthetically relevant is a
long way from classic formalism. Its assumption, as noted, is that all such
information, with the exception of the formal, is at best irrelevant and at worst harmful
interference with pure aesthetic experience. However, this conclusion is not yet close
to the extravagances suggested by postmodernism. Moreover, perhaps we are here
nearing the outer limits of relevant “outside information.” However, to determine
these limits and thus to see clearly the full extent of the move away from formalism,
as well as to ultimately test the plausibility of the postmodern approach, I turn now
to the remaining components of Hillerman’s descriptions—those which I label
cultural.
Nominal descriptions
Within the cultural component of Hillerman’s landscape descriptions, as within the
factual, at least four different descriptive themes can be distinguished: what I call the
nominal, the imaginative, the mythological, and the literary. It should be noted that
in general the cultural component of landscape descriptions frequently includes
additional dimensions that are not clearly captured within these groupings, but
these four themes are those most evident in Hillerman’s descriptions and are,
moreover, sufficient for present purposes.
16
The first, the nominal, refers to what are
perhaps the most basic means by which we culturally characterize landscapes, the
proper names with which we label them. Consider this example:
Jimmie Yellow’s place…seemed to have been selected more for the view than
for convenience. It was perched near the rim of the mesa, looking down into
the great empty breaks that fell away to the Rio Puerco. To the west, across the
Laguna Reservation, the snowy ridges of Turquoise Mountain reflected the
light of the rising moon. To the east, the humped ridge of the Sandia
Mountains rose against the horizon, their base lit by the glowing lights of
Albuquerque. To the north, another line of white marked the snowcap on the
Sangre de Cristo Mountains, and the bright smudge of yellow light below
them was Santa Fe, one hundred miles away. A spectacular view, but no
water.
17
228 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
Like the points of light that sparkle in the described view, this description itself is
highlighted by proper names: not only “Jimmie Yellow,” but also “Rio Puerco,”
“Turquoise Mountain,” “Sandia Mountains,” “Albuquerque,” “Sangre de Christo
Mountains,” and “Santa Fe.” How do such names function in aesthetic
appreciation? In one sense names are typically very different from the previously
discussed ordinary, scientific, historical, and functional descriptions. Names, unlike
these descriptions, do not necessarily provide factual information about a landscape
nor do they necessarily describe it. Thus, they do not necessarily enhance aesthetic
appreciation. Rather they frequently act only as pointers, picking out and directing
attention to certain landscape features. In this, they function like the most basic
descriptions of landscapes, ones in which features are not identified by descriptive
terms, such as “mountain,” “cloud,” and “sunset,” but rather only with indexical
words, such as “this” and “that.” Such words, although they facilitate directing and
focusing of aesthetic appreciation, do not, in that they have no descriptive content,
contribute to it. The same is true of many proper names.
Not all proper names are without descriptive content, however. Many have such
content in the sense that they have a specific meaning. For example, in the
previously quoted passage, “Puerco” means pig, “Sandia,” watermelon, “Sangre de
Christo,” blood of Christ, “Santa Fe,” holy faith, and “Turquoise,” of course,
turquoise, although apparently “Albuquerque” has no such literal meaning. Likewise
consider the names for the two butte’s referred to in the following description:
Now [Agnes Tsosie] was looking away, out across the gentle slope that fell
away from Tesihim Butte and then rose gradually toward the sharp dark
outline of Nipple Butte to the west. The sage was gray and silver with autumn,
the late afternoon sun laced it with slanting shadows, and everywhere there
was the yellow of blooming snakeweed and the purple of the asters. Beauty
before her, Leaphorn thought. Beauty all around her.
18
Compare the impact of the name “Nipple Butte” with that of the name “Tesihim
Butte.” The difference in impact makes evident that when proper names, such as “Rio
Puerco,” “Turquoise Mountain,” “Sandia Mountains,” “Sangre de Christo
Mountains,” “Santa Fe,” and “Nipple Butte,” and unlike “Albuquerque” or
“Tesihim Butte,” have meaning, then they have the potential to be descriptive of the
landscape, just as do the descriptive terms of ordinary, scientific, historical, and
functional descriptions. And when names are descriptive in this way, they, in
meeting the previously indicated descriptive condition, can enhance aesthetic
appreciation much as do factual descriptions. However, two qualifications to this
claim need to be noted. First, the fact that a proper name has meaning does not
guarantee that it is actually descriptive of the landscape that it names. The names
for the Sandia Mountains and for Nipple Butte are in fact descriptive in the relevant
sense, but it is not clear that the name for the Rio Puerco or for the Sangre de
Christo Mountains or for Santa Fe is. However, if such names are in fact descriptive
of what they name, seeing that they are and how they are can be a significant
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 229
dimension of aesthetic appreciation.
19
Second, and more important, simply the fact
that a name, or any other cultural attribution, is descriptive is not sufficient to
enhance appreciation of a landscape. To be relevant to aesthetic appreciation, a
cultural landscape description, in addition to meeting the descriptive condition,
must also meet at least one other condition. To make this clear it is useful to
consider the second of the cultural themes in Hillerman’s descriptions, the
imaginative.
Imaginative descriptions and cultural embeddedness
The imaginative theme of Hillerman’s landscape descriptions is evident in the
following example:
Shiprock stuck up like a blue thumb on the western horizon seventy miles
away. Behind it, the dim outline of the Carrizo Mountains formed the last
margin of the planet. The sagebrush flats between were dappled with the
shadow of clouds, drifting eastward under the noon sun.
20
What I call the imaginative component is also well illustrated in the passage quoted
at the outset of this chapter. Parts of that description read as follows: “Ship Rock
rose like an oversized, free-form Gothic cathedral” and “Table Mesa sailed through
its sea of buffalo grass, reminding Chee of the ultimate aircraft carrier.”
21
In these passages there are two proper names, Ship Rock and Table Mesa, both of
which, due to their descriptive content, contribute, at least minimally, to the
aesthetic appreciation of the landscape features they name. However, there are also
three other descriptions of these same features, descriptions of the kind I label
imaginative. These are the characterizations of Ship Rock as “a blue thumb” and “an
oversized, free-form Gothic cathedral” and of Table Mesa as “the ultimate aircraft
carrier.” Such imaginative descriptions are equally as descriptive as, indeed even
more so than, names such as Ship Rock and Table Mesa. However, the former do
not, as the latter, contribute to appreciation, for they fail to meet a condition that is
met by the latter. This is that in order to be aesthetically relevant, a cultural
component of a landscape description must not simply be descriptive of the feature
in question, but must also be what I term “culturally embedded” and thereby more
generally available. Although it is difficult to state this embeddedness requirement
precisely, it can be put somewhat as follows: to be aesthetically relevant to the
appreciation of a landscape, cultural “outside information” contained in a landscape
description must be embedded in a cultural framework and embedded in such a way
that it is accessible within that particular framework and thereby accessible
independent of the particular description. It is evident, I think, that proper names
such as Ship Rock and Table Mesa are so embedded, while various possible
imaginative characterizations, such as looking like a huge blue thumb or an
oversized, free-form Gothic cathedral or as being reminiscent of the ultimate aircraft
carrier, are not.
230 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
The justification for the embeddedness condition has to do with the way in
which culturally embedded descriptions connect to the landscapes to which they
apply. The previously considered factual descriptions, whether ordinary, scientific,
historical, or functional, are aesthetically relevant and able to enhance appreciation
because they are both descriptive and straightforwardly factual. Consequently, they
connect to the landscapes they describe in such a way that, if they are true, then it is
simply the case that the feature is that which it is described as. For example,
Turquoise Mountain is a mountain, Ship Rock is a volcanic throat, and the rail line
beyond Interstate 40 is the Santa Fe main trunk. This is, of course, part of what is
meant by calling such descriptions factual. However, cultural descriptions, for
instance, attributions such as proper names, can attain a certain kind of factuality if
they are sufficiently culturally embedded. Thus, given the cultural embeddedness of
the names “Ship Rock” and “Table Mesa,” it is simply the case that Ship Rock is
Ship Rock and Table Mesa is Table Mesa. These are, we might say, cultural facts.
By contrast, Ship Rock is neither a blue thumb nor a Gothic cathedral and Table Mesa
is not the ultimate aircraft carrier. To attribute such descriptions, we must use
phrases such as “looks like,” or “is reminiscent of.” The importance of the
embeddedness condition can be underscored by noting that, for instance, were
“Thumb Rock” or “Cathedral Rock,” rather than “Ship Rock,” the culturally
embedded name for Ship Rock, then it would simply be the case that Thumb Rock
is Thumb Rock or that Cathedral Rock is Cathedral Rock and that it is only
reminiscent of a ship. And the attributions that characterize the rock as a thumb or
as a cathedral, and not that which likens it to a ship, would then be the ones that
would be aesthetically relevant.
These observations concerning the nominal and the imaginative themes
of Hillerman’s descriptions have obvious ramifications for the general question of
aesthetic relevance. Of these two kinds of cultural attributions, the former enhance
aesthetic appreciation if and when they meet each of two conditions, the descriptive
condition and the embeddedness condition, while the latter, insofar as they fail to
meet at least one of these conditions, are typically not aesthetically relevant. This
suggests that these two conditions may provide a partial answer to the question of
aesthetic relevance, the question, again, as the classic formulation puts it: “Is it ever
‘relevant’ to aesthetic experience to have thoughts or images or bits of knowledge
which are not present within the object itself? If these are ever relevant, under what
conditions are they so?” Perhaps such “outside information” is aesthetically relevant
only if it, on the one hand, meets the descriptive condition and, on the other,
provided that it is not straightforwardly factual in nature, meets the embeddedness
condition as well as the descriptive condition. The two conditions are thus
necessary, although, of course, not necessarily jointly sufficient for aesthetic
relevance. If this is correct, it would mean we may be near the end of the slippery
slope that begins with formal descriptions, continues through ordinary, scientific,
historical, and functional descriptions, and leads now to the boundary between
nominal and imaginary descriptions. It would also mean that the journey from
classic formalism and toward postmodernism may likewise be near an end. These
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 231
two conditions may constitute constraints on how much of a postmodern approach
is acceptable. However, these conclusions are only tentative. To examine them more
fully it is useful to turn to the remaining two cultural themes in Hillermans
descriptions, the mythological and the literary.
Mythological landscape descriptions
The mythological theme of Hillerman’s landscape descriptions typically involves
references to the rich Navajo mythological tradition. Consider the following
example:
It was cold here, frost still rimming the roadside weeds, and the snowcapped
shape of the San Francisco Peaks twenty miles to the south looked close
enough to touch in the clear, high-altitude air. The winter storm being held
at bay by the Utah high in last night’s weathercast was still hung up
somewhere over the horizon. The only clouds this morning were high altitude
cirrus so thin that the blue showed through them. Beautiful to Chee. He was
back in Dine’ Bike’yah, back between the Sacred Mountains, and he felt easy
again—at home in a remembered landscape… This was one of those places for
Chee—this desert sloping away to the hills that rose to become
Dook’o’oosli’id, Evening Twilight Mountain, the Mountain of the West, the
mountain built by First Man as the place where the holy Abalone Shell Boy
would live, guarded by the Black Wind yei.
22
Hillerman’s use of Navajo mythology in his landscape descriptions is another factor
that, like his use of scientific information, contributes significantly to their power
and appeal. As illustrated in this passage, references to the four sacred mountains
that indicate the four corners of Navajo Country, together with allusions to the
mighty deeds performed there by the Navajo mythological heros, such as First Man,
animate his descriptions. However, although such mythological dimensions
obviously enrich the descriptions themselves, do they also enhance aesthetic
appreciation of the landscapes described? Initially the answer to this question seems
negative. On the one hand, mythological descriptions of landscapes are not factual,
as are ordinary, scientific, historical, and functional descriptions, nor do they seem
as substantially culturally embedded as are, for example, proper names. And on the
other hand, with the exception of certain names that are parts of the mythology,
such asTsodzil, that is,Turquoise Mountain, they are seemingly not very
descriptive of landscapes. Thus, at first glance it appears that the mythological
component of these descriptions meets neither the embeddedness condition nor the
descriptive condition.
Nonetheless, the conclusion that the mythological allusions in Hillerman’s
landscape descriptions are not relevant to the aesthetic appreciation of the
landscapes in question seems somewhat paradoxical in light of their obviously
significant role within the descriptions themselves. I suggest that this paradox may be
232 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
resolved by considering what I call the scope of such mythological descriptions.
These particular mythological descriptions are limited in scope in that, first, they,
like proper names, apply to particular landscape features and, second, these features
exist within a specific, circumscribed framework. The previously quoted
mythological description is of one particular landscape—that of Dine’ Bike’yah, the
landscape between the Sacred Mountains. The specificity and the significance of
this landscape is made evident in the following passage:
Winding down the east slope of the Chuskas, Leaphorn stopped at an
overlook. He pointed east and swept his hand northward, encompassing an
immensity of rolling tan and gray grasslands. Zuni Mountains to the south,
Jemez Mountains to the east, and far to the north the snowy San Juans in
Colorado. “Dinetah,” he said… “Among the People.” The heartland of the
Navajos. The place of their mythology, the Holy Land of the Dinee.
23
What this quote brings out is that the mythological component of Hillerman’s
descriptions applies to a very particular landscape: the landscape that is the heartland
of the Navajos. This is a landscape specified and limited both geographically and
culturally. Moreover, it is, as the passage puts it, the Holy Land of the Navajos, the
place of their mythology. Consequently, I suggest that concerning this specific
framework, Hillerman’s mythological descriptions are as deeply and as solidly
culturally embedded as are proper names. In the same sense in which within a less
limited framework Ship Rock simply is Ship Rock, within this geographically and
culturally more limited framework, Evening Twilight Mountain simply is Evening
Twilight Mountain. Moreover, since it is Evening Twilight Mountain, it is also the
mountain built by First Man as the place where the holy Abalone Shell Boy would
live. The point is that, provided they are attributed to particular landscape features,
as are proper names, mythological attributions can be, within a specific framework,
culturally embedded just as substantially as are proper names. Thus, in the same way
in which the cultural fact that Ship Rock is Ship Rock enhances the aesthetic
appreciation of the landscape feature so named, the cultural fact that Evening
Twilight Mountain is the mountain built by First Man for Abalone Shell Boy may
potentially enhance the appreciation of the specific landscape feature in question.
If a mythological description of a landscape can be, just as a proper name,
adequately culturally embedded so as to open the possibility that it is aesthetically
relevant, this still addresses only half the problem. There is yet the worry that, with
the exception of names, such as “Turquoise Mountain,” that may constitute a part of
a mythological description, these so-called descriptions are seemingly not very
descriptive of landscapes. To address this worry, it is useful to consider the ways in
which some of the previously considered descriptions are in fact descriptive of the
landscapes to which they are attributed. It may be argued that in one basic sense
only formal descriptive terms, such as “turquoise,” and some ordinary descriptive
terms, such as “mountain,” are straightforwardly descriptive of landscapes.
However, even if this is the case, this basic sense clearly does not indicate the limits
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 233
of aesthetic relevance. As noted previously, scientific, historical, and functional
descriptions, all of which are descriptive of the landscape in a more extended sense,
are aesthetically relevant. That a landscape feature is a basalt volcanic throat exposed
by a million years of erosion or intercontinental train traffic rolling east and west on
the Santa Fe main trunk is as aesthetically relevant as that it is a mountain or a
train, or this or that color or shape.
If more complex scientific, historical, and functional factual descriptions
adequately satisfy the descriptive condition, however, then there would seem to be
no grounds for excluding mythological descriptions on the basis of this condition,
provided, of course, that they meet the embeddedness condition. The comparison
of mythological descriptions with scientific descriptions is especially revealing since
both frequently involve, as an integral part of the description, an explanation of the
origin or the nature of landscape features. For example, if the fact that a specific
feature is the result of a million years of erosion is descriptive in the required sense,
then so too is the cultural fact that it is the result of First Mans desire to accommodate
Abalone Shell Boy. Indeed, Hillerman’s landscape descriptions frequently illustrate
this comparison. Consider these two parallel observations about the “Long Black
Ridges” landscape surrounding Ship Rock. First: “…the volcanic action that formed
Ship Rock lasted for tens of thousands of years. The pressure formed a lot of
cracking in the earth’s surface and every thousand years or so…there would be
another bubbling up of melted rock and new ridges would form.” And second:
“According to Navajo mythology…those lava flows are the dried blood of the
monsters killed by the Hero Twins.
24
Although we may judge the latter
explanation to be less straightforwardly factual than the former, we are seemingly not
justified in judging it any less descriptive of the landscape in question.
234 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
In light of these observations it seems plausible to conclude that mythological, as
well as some other cultural descriptions of landscapes, at least within properly
circumscribed frameworks, are aesthetically relevant and enhance aesthetic
appreciation of landscapes in much the same manner as do scientific, historical, and
functional descriptions. This conclusion greatly expands the quantity of aesthetically
relevant “outside information.” However, it does not yet get us to the postmodern
view, which contends that anything and everything that an appreciator brings to a
landscape is relevant to its appreciation, for the landscape is essentially created in light
of that which the appreciator contributes to it. To test this contention it is useful to
turn to the last of the cultural themes of Hillerman’s landscape descriptions, the
literary. This component is especially relevant to the postmodern view, for it may be
argued that Hillerman’s literature itself constitutes resources with which each of us
Illustration 10 Ship Rock and the Long Black Ridges, New Mexico.
Literary landscape descriptions
As an illustration of the literary theme in Hillerman’s landscape descriptions,
consider the following passage, in which this component is interwoven with a
number of previously discussed themes:
Finding Joseph Joe proved simple enough… Chee rolled his patrol car
southward across the San Juan bridge with the north wind chasing him, then
west toward Arizona, and then south again across the dry slopes of snakeweed
and buffalo grass toward the towering black spire of basalt that gave the town
of Shiprock its name. It was the landmark of Chee’s childhood—jutting on
the eastern horizon from his mother’s place south of Kayenta, and a great
black thumb stuck into the northern sky during the endless lonely winters he
spent at the Two Gray Hills Boarding School. It was there he’d learned that
the Rock with Wings of his uncle’s legends had, eons ago, boiled and bubbled
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 235
can create the landscape for him or herself. It is even suggested, as noted at the outset
of this chapter, that his novels make the landscape of the Southwest come alive to
such a degree that an appreciator can seemingly create and appreciate these landscapes
without ever actually experiencing them. Thus, the literary component of Hillerman’s
descriptions is a pivotal example for those who would promote a postmodern approach
to landscape appreciation.
as molten lava in the throat of an immense cinder cone. The volcano had died,
millions of years had passed, abrasive weather—like today’s bitter wind—had
worn away cinders and ash and left only tough black filling. In today’s bleak
autumn light, it thrust into the sky like a surreal gothic cathedral, soaring a
thousand feet above the blowing grass and providing—even at five miles’
distance—a ludicrously oversized backdrop for Joseph Joe’s plank and
tarpaper house.
25
As in other passages previously considered, this description focuses on Ship Rock
and the surrounding landscape. On the one hand, this landscape feature is referred
to in a number of different aesthetically relevant ways. It is described in formal and
ordinary terms as “a towering black spire of basalt,” it is characterized in scientific
terminology as the remains of “molten lava in the throat of an immense cinder
cone,” and it is alluded to in one of its Navajo mythological guises as “the Rock with
Wings.” On the other hand, it is also characterized in imaginative ways similar to
those discussed previously, as “a great black thumb” and as “a surreal gothic
cathedral.” As noted, these latter descriptions are not relevant to aesthetic
appreciation. However, this description also has another dimension, the literary, for
in it two literary characters, Navajo Tribal Policeman Jim Chee and one of his
potential witnesses, Joseph Joe, enter the scene. We learn that Ship Rock “was the
landmark of Chee’s childhood—jutting on the eastern horizon from his mother’s
place south of Kayenta” and that it “stuck into the northern sky during the endless
lonely winters he spent at the Two Gray Hills Boarding School.” We also learn that
it is “a ludicrously oversized backdrop for Joseph Joe’s plank and tarpaper house.
Are these descriptions of Ship Rock aesthetically relevant?
The question of the aesthetic relevance of the literary component in Hillerman’s
landscape descriptions is perplexing. On the one hand, that Ship Rock was the
significant landmark of Jim Chee’s childhood is seemingly no less factual than is the
cultural fact that the lava flows surrounding it were formed by the dried blood of
the monsters killed by the Hero Twins. Moreover, both characterizations are
adequately descriptive. Thus, perhaps the former should be judged as aesthetically
relevant as is the latter. On the other hand, such literary allusions seem similar to
the imaginative characterizations of Ship Rock as looking like a great black thumb
or a surreal Gothic cathedral. Thus, perhaps the literary component, as the
imaginative, should not count as aesthetically relevant. In response to this quandary,
I admit that in many ways literary descriptions are much like mythological ones.
Indeed, we might contemplate a genus of cultural facts with two species,
mythological facts and literary facts, and this proposal would seemingly find favor in
certain approaches to the philosophy of art and literature. Nonetheless, I suggest that,
in spite of their similarity to mythological descriptions, literary descriptions, just as
imaginative ones, are not adequately culturally embedded to be deemed aesthetically
relevant. To satisfy the embeddedness condition requires a cultural status that no
literature, as long as it remains only literature, can easily attain. Consequently,
although the literary “fact” that Ship Rock was a significant landmark in Navajo
236 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
Tribal Policeman Jim Chee’s childhood is a important fact within Hillerman’s
novels, it is not relevant to the aesthetic appreciation of this landscape feature as it
exists in the real world.
This conclusion has far-reaching ramifications for the general significance of
literature to the aesthetic appreciation of landscapes. If it is correct, it applies not
simply to Hillerman’s mystery novels, but to all those literary works, such as the
novels of, to mention only two classic examples, Thomas Hardy and John Steinbeck,
that embellish and enrich various landscapes with a host of fictional characters and
events. As such, the conclusion strikes many who appreciate this literature as
counter-intuitive, for it seemingly runs counter to their experiences of such
literature. In this respect Hillerman’s work constitutes an especially nice example.
As noted at the outset of this chapter, Hillerman himself observes that many people
read his novels for the landscape descriptions. Moreover, people not only read his
novels for the descriptions, they also travel to the Southwest to experience for
themselves the landscapes he describes. However, frequently these individuals do
not want to experience simply Ship Rock and the lava flows surrounding it or only
the fiery sunsets over the Chuskas or even only the Holy Land of the Navajos. They
also want to experience the landscapes travelled by Lieutenant Joe Leaphorn and
Officer Jim Chee; they want to see the places where Leaphorn pursued “thieves of
time” and where Chee encountered “skinwalkers” or “the people of darkness.”
26
Fodor’s travel guide to the American Southwest even informs tourists that in the
Four Corners area the “Navajo tribal lands are patrolled by the Navajo Tribal Police
(the same force that employs the fictitious protagonists of Tony Hillerman’s
detective series: Officer Jim Chee and Lieutenant Joe Leaphorn)!”
27
In short, the
idea that the literary component of landscape descriptions is aesthetically relevant to
the landscapes described has both general significance and great intuitive appeal.
Therefore, in light of this significance and appeal, the conclusion that it is not
aesthetically relevant should not rest solely on the embeddedness condition. Thus, I
return to the Analogy with Art Argument, from which this conclusion gets
additional support.
The analogy with art argument again
Previously I employed the Analogy with Art Argument to demonstrate that a
landscape’s history of production, as recorded and recounted in scientific, historical,
and functional descriptions of that landscape, is importantly aesthetically relevant,
just as is the history of production of a work of art. Here I employ it to support the
conclusion that literary descriptions of a landscape are not relevant to its aesthetic
appreciation. In this regard, the relevant premise of the Analogy with Art Argument
is the presupposition that at the most fundamental level the nature of aesthetic
appreciation is essentially uniform across the appreciation of different kinds of objects
of appreciation and, thus, that the aesthetic appreciation of landscapes and the
aesthetic appreciation of works of art mirror one another. Thus, to pursue the
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 237
ramifications of this line of thought, a literary description of a work of art is useful.
Consider the following:
Leaphorn spent the rest of the afternoon prowling through the Museum of
Modern Art. He sat, finally, where he could see the patio of sculpture, the
rain-stained wall behind it, and the rainy sky above,…and watched the water
run down the bricks, drip from the leaves, form its cold pools on the
flagstones, and give a slick shine to Picasso’s goat… The goat was Leaphorn’s
favorite. When they were young and he was attending the FBI Academy, he
had brought Emma to see New York. They had discovered Picasso’s goat
together… Emma had laughed…and said: “Look. The mascot of the Navajo
Nation.”… “Perfect for us Dineh”… “It’s starved, gaunt, bony, ugly. But
look! It’s tough. It endures.” … And of course, it was true. That gaunt goat
would have been the perfect symbol. Something to put on a pedestal and
display. Miserable and starved, true enough. But it was also pregnant and
defiant—exactly right to challenge the world at the entrance of the ugly
octagonal Tribal Council meeting hall at Window Rock. Leaphorn
remembered their having coffee at the museum cafe and then walking out and
patting the goat. The sensation came back to him now—wet, cold metal slick
under his palm—utterly real.
28
In this passage Hillerman’s most famous literary character, Navajo Tribal Policeman
Lieutenant Joe Leaphorn, contemplates an equally famous real work of art, Picasso’s
She-Goat (1950).
29
He recalls the initial reaction that he and his late wife, Emma,
had to the work. The incident described is both touching and significant within
Hillerman’s novel. Moreover, the description itself contains a number of interesting
observations about the work of art. Some of these observations are aesthetically
relevant. For example, it is clearly aesthetically relevant that the work, when in the
rain, is shiny, cold, and slick to the touch and that the goat is represented, if it is, as
starved, gaunt, bony, ugly, and yet pregnant and defiant. It is likewise relevant that
it expresses toughness and endurance. Moreover, we might also accept the relevance
of the observation that the work could be a perfect symbol for the Dineh, a mascot
for the Navajo Nation. And perhaps we might even consider relevant the suggestion
that it would pose exactly the right challenge to the world were it to be put on a
pedestal and displayed at the entrance of the Tribal Council meeting hall at
Window Rock. However, these last two observations reach and probably exceed the
limits of aesthetic relevance. Seemingly they are more like the imaginative
component of Hillerman’s landscape descriptions and not in fact aesthetically
relevant. Be that as it may, however, what is clearly beyond the limits of aesthetic
relevance is the literary fact that Picasso’s work of art is a favorite of Navajo Tribal
Policeman Joe Leaphorn and that he and his wife, Emma, when they were young
and he was attending the FBI Academy, discovered it together.
As this example illustrates, with works of art the outer limits of aesthetic relevance
are, although somewhat fuzzy, yet clear enough to undoubtedly exclude the literary
238 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
component of a passage such as Hillerman’s description of Leaphorn’s encounter
with Picasso’s goat. This conclusion is reinforced by the following thought
experiment: imagine a volume of art history and art criticism on Picasso’s
sculpture.
30
Were such a study to describe Picasso’s goat only in term of its formal
and representational features, we would find it quite properly scholarly, although
perhaps a bit boring. Were it to characterize the work in terms of its expressive and
symbolic features, we might find it somewhat more interesting; and were it to then
go on to consider various potential symbolic uses the piece could have, we might find
it, although imaginatively interesting, perhaps somewhat too imaginative. However,
were it to go even further and point out that She-Goat is one of Joe Leaphorn’s
favorite pieces, we would find it absolutely crazy! The ramifications for the
appreciation of not simply art but also of landscapes are clear enough: since the
literary fact that Picassos goat is one of Navajo Tribal Policeman Joe Leaphorns
favorite works of art is clearly not aesthetically relevant to that work’s appreciation,
it follows by the Analogy with Art Argument that the literary fact that Ship Rock
was an important landmark of Navajo Tribal Policeman Jim Chee’s childhood is
likewise aesthetically irrelevant to the appreciation of that landscape feature.
Conclusion
The literary theme is the last of the nine descriptive themes I distinguish in
Hillerman’s landscape descriptions. Thus, its consideration marks the end of our
examination of aesthetic relevance and of the path running from formalism to
postmodernism. Concerning the nine themes, I summarize as follows: Formal
descriptions together with ordinary descriptions are clearly aesthetically relevant.
Other factual descriptions, such as the scientific, the historical, and the functional,
are also relevant to and enhance and enrich aesthetic appreciation. Similarly
relevant, at least within their properly circumscribed frameworks and provided that
they are adequately culturally embedded, are cultural descriptions such as the
nominal and the mythological. What is excluded as aesthetically irrelevant “outside
information” are cultural descriptions such as the imaginative and the literary.
These conclusions not only demonstrate that classic formalism provides much too
restrictive an answer to the question of aesthetic relevance, but also suggest that not
just anything and everything that an appreciator happens to bring to a landscape is
relevant to its aesthetic appreciation. Thus, these conclusions also limit the extremes
to which postmodern landscape appreciation can reasonably be taken. The limits, as
suggested earlier, are roughly marked by the descriptive and the embeddedness
conditions. What these conditions exclude from the sum total of aesthetically
relevant information are exactly those imaginative and literary allusions frequently
favored by the postmodern point of view.
I conclude with one more landscape description from Hillerman—one that
brings together much of that which is aesthetically relevant not simply for appropriate,
but also for deep and rich appreciation of the landscape described:
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 239
The sun was in its autumn mode, low in the southwest, and shadows slanted
away from every juniper. They formed zebra stripes where the slopes ran
north and a polka-dot pattern where they slanted. The grass was never really
green in this land of little rain. Now it was a golden autumn tan with streaks
of silver and white where the sickle-shaped seeds of grama were waving, tinted
blue here and there by distance and shadow. Miles away, beyond the hills, the
vertical slopes of Chivato Mesa formed a wall. Above the mesa stood the
serene blue shape of Tsodzil, the Turquoise Mountain which First Man had
built as one of the four sacred corner posts of Navajo Country. And over all
that, the great arching multilayered sky—the thin translucent fan of ice
crystals still glittering in the full sun. Thousands of feet lower, a scattering of
puffy gray-white cumulus clouds—outriders of the storm the weatherman had
been predicting—marched eastward ahead of the wind.
31
Notes
1 Martin Greenberg (ed.) The Tony Hillerman Companion: A Comprehensive Guide to
His Life and Work, New York, Harper, 1994, endpiece.
2 Tony Hillerman, quoted in Brandon Griggs, “Hillerman Trades Southwest for
Vietnam,” The Salt Lake Tribune, November 5, 1995, p. E3.
3 Griggs, ibid., p. E3.
4 These phrases are gathered from a number of different reviews of Hillerman’s novels.
5 An anonymous reviewer for the Chicago Tribune, quoted in Greenberg, op. cit., p. i.
6 Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Criticism: A Critical Introduction,
Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 1960, p. 53. In his formulation of the question, Stolnitz
uses the traditional idea of “aesthetic experience.” In contrast, I employ the notion of
“appropriate aesthetic appreciation,” although to avoid this rather cumbersome
phrase, I typically write only “aesthetic appreciation” or even only “appreciation.” I
prefer the notion of “appropriate aesthetic appreciation” to that of “aesthetic
experience,” for the former makes more explicit the implications both that aesthetic
experience is active rather than passive and that it can, concerning an object of
appreciation, be appropriate or not. I discuss these issues as well as Stolnitz’s position
and the question of aesthetic relevance more fully in “Appreciating Art and
Appreciating Nature,” in S.Kemal and I.Gaskell (eds) Landscape, Natural Beauty and
the Arts, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 199–227 (reproduced in
this volume, Chapter 7) and in “Between Nature and Art” (in this volume,
Chapter 8).
7Tony Hillerman, Coyote Waits, New York, Harper, 1990, pp. 101–2.
8 In addition to these questions concerning the aesthetic appreciation of the landscape
described in such a passage, there are also, of course, questions about the aesthetic
appreciation of the description itself. I take these to be distinct issues in the aesthetics
of literature and do not address them here.
9 I spell out these matters in more detail in “Between Nature and Art” (in this volume,
Chapter 8).
10 Hillerman, Coyote Waits, op. cit., pp. 103–4.
240 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
11 I discuss the problem of indicating the formal qualities of landscapes as well as other
problems with formalism concerning the natural environment in “Understanding and
Aesthetic Experience” (in this volume, Chapter 2) and in “Formal Qualities in the
Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1979, vol. 13, pp. 99–114
(reproduced in this volume, Chapter 3).
12 I consider in greater detail and give additional arguments for the aesthetic relevance of
scientific descriptions to landscapes in the first part of this volume, especially in
“Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
1979, vol. 37, pp. 267–76 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 4) and in “Nature and
Positive Aesthetics,Environmental Ethics, 1984, vol. 6, pp. 5–34 (reproduced in this
volume, Chapter 6). I also address these issues in “Saito on the Correct Aesthetic
Appreciation of Nature,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 1986, vol. 20, pp. 85–93 and
in “Nature, Aesthetic Appreciation, and Knowledge,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 1995, vol. 53, pp. 393–400.
13 Hillerman, Coyote Waits, op. cit., pp. 315–17.
14 Tony Hillerman, Skinwalkers, New York, Harper, 1986, pp. 173–4.
15 Tony Hillerman, Sacred Clowns, New York, Harper, 1993, pp. 224–6. I discuss the
role of functional descriptions in the aesthetic appreciation of agricultural landscapes
in more detail in “On Appreciating Agricultural Landscapes,” Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism, 1985, vol. 43, pp. 301–12 (reproduced in this volume, Chapter 12).
16 Other kinds of cultural characterizations of landscapes, such as, for example, the more
general symbolic significance given to certain landscapes or the much-discussed “sense
of place,” are, of course, interesting cases for consideration. However, I think that
much of what can be said of such cases is similar to what can be said concerning
nominal and mythological descriptions. I think that the role of nominal descriptions
in aesthetic appreciation is especially revealing, and yet it is almost totally ignored. For
excellent backgrounding on this topic, see George R.Stewart’s classic study, Names on
the Land: A Historical Account of Placenaming in the United States [1945], San
Francisco, Lexikos, 1982.
17 Tony Hillerman, The Ghostway, New York, Harper, 1984, pp. 262–3.
18 Tony Hillerman, Talking God, New York, Harper, 1989, p. 29.
19 The way in which a descriptive name enhances aesthetic appreciation of a landscape
differs depending on the descriptive content of the name in question. On the one
hand, seeing that Turquoise Mountain, for example, is appropriately named and how
it exemplifies its name is seemingly a dimension of its aesthetic appreciation somewhat
analogous to appreciation in light of formal descriptions. On the other hand, if
knowledge of a name such as “Santa Fe” enhances appreciation, the way in which it
does is perhaps more similar to the enhancement affected by historical and functional
descriptions of the landscape. Santa Fe was named by Don Juan de Onate who arrived
in the area in 1598 with the power from King Philip of Spain “to conquer and hold.”
Stewart, op. cit., p. 26, reports:
As his capital Onate founded a city in a high valley between mountains.
To fit with its dignity and his own love of pomp, he named it
sonorously La Villa Real de la Santa Fe de San Francisco, ‘The Royal
AESTHETICS AND THE ENVIRONMENT 241
City of the Holy Faith of Saint Francis,’ but it was shortened to Santa
Fe.
20 Tony Hillerman, A Thief of Time, New York, Harper, 1988, p. 148.
21 Hillerman, Coyote Waits, op. cit., p. 102.
22 Hillerman, The Ghostway, op. cit., pp. 224–5.
23 Hillerman, Coyote Waits, op. cit., pp. 202–3.
24 Ibid., pp. 105–6.
25 Hillerman, The Ghostway, op. cit., pp. 44–5.
26 These quotes are derived from the titles of the following: Hillerman, A Thief of Time,
op. cit., Hillerman, Skinwalkers, op. cit., and Tony Hillerman, People of Darkness, New
York, Harper, 1980.
27 Nancy Zimmerman and Kit Duane (eds) The American Southwest, Oakland, Fodor’s
Travel Publications, 1996, p. 158.
28 Hillerman, A Thief of Time, op. cit., pp. 192–3.
29 Pablo Picasso, She-Goat, 1950, Bronze, after found objects, 46• by 56• by 27¾ inches,
Museum of Modern Art, New York.
30 I have in mind works such as, for example, Roland Penrose’s classic The Sculpture of
Picasso, New York, Museum of Modern Art, 1967 and Werner Spies’s Picasso
Sculpture, London, Thames and Hudson, 1972. Interestingly enough, critics do not
seem very excited about the features of She-Goat that impress Joe and Emma Leaphorn.
Critical comments tend to focus either on the fact that the work is “almost entirely
composed of found objects (Spies, ibid., p. 179) or that the goat hasgrotesquely
detailed sexual organs.” See, for example, Alan Bowness, “Picasso’s Sculpture,” in
Roland Penrose and John Golding (eds) Picasso in Retrospect, New York, Praeger, 1973
(the last quote in the previous sentence is from p. 153). Moreover, such observations
as there are that are of roughly the same nature as those of Joe and Emma seem to
contradict theirs, describing the goat as “docile” rather than “defiant.” See, for
example, Roland Penrose, Universe Sculpture Series: Picasso, New York, Universe
Books, 1961 (the short quotes in the previous sentence are from p. 12).
31 Hillerman, Sacred Clowns, op. cit., p. 131. Earlier versions of this chapter were
presented at The International Association for Philosophy and Literature, Irvine,
California, May, 1998; The Association for the Study of Literature and Environment,
Missoula, Montana, July, 1997, The Canadian Society for Aesthetics, St. John’s,
Newfoundland, June, 1997, The American Society for Aesthetics, Rocky Mountain
Division, Santa Fe, New Mexico, July, 1996 and at several universities in New
Zealand and Australia during April and May of 1997. I thank those present, as well as
Arlene Kwasniak and Alex Neill, for valuable suggestions.
242 LANDSCAPE AND LITERATURE
INDEX
Note: page numbers in bold indicate chapters
action painting 110–12, 120
active aesthetic appreciation 35, 47–9, 103–
6, 195–6, 213
acts of aspection 40–2, 47, 49–1, 88, 105–6
Addison, J. 3, 4
aesthetic appreciation see appreciation
aesthetic environment see environmental
aesthetics
aesthetic experience and understanding 15
27, 103;
disinterestedness 23–6;
formalism and 18–23;
Mississippi see under Twain;
see also knowledge and cognitive
experience
aesthetic judgment 5371;
correct categories of nature 62–8, 70–1;
critical 168–9;
culture and nature 58–8, 70;
objectivity and nature 53–5;
see also Walton
aesthetic necessity 130–3
aesthetic relevance 104, 129–35;
in Hillerman’s novels 217–25, 231, 236
aesthetic value(s) 28–9, 46–8
agricultural landscapes, appreciation of 134,
175–93, 226;
difficult aesthetic appreciation and
novelty 183–5;
new 178–82, 186–9;
traditional 175–7, 179
Alison, A. 24–5
Amarillo Ramp (Smithson) 156
analogy with art argument 225–5, 237–7
anthropocentrism see under human
anti-art 111–14
applied aesthetics 10
appreciation 101–25;
concept of 101–7;
experiments in 111–14;
of nature 114–21;
see also appreciation of art;
appreciation of nature;
architecture;
design appreciation;
Japanese gardens;
order appreciation
appreciation of art 40–2, 107–14;
and agricultural landscapes 183–5;
and disinterestedness 101–8
appreciation of nature/natural environment
4052, 114–21;
appropriate 87–90, 99, 240;
art appreciation 40–2;
artistic models for 41–7;
and disinterestedness 114–15, 119, 123;
environmental models for 46–50, 51;
and Japanese gardens 169–70;
as non-aesthetic 76–8, 97;
and science 85–7, 98–9
appropriate aesthetic appreciation xi, 87–90,
99, 240;
see also objectivity
architecture 29, 185217;
agricultural 181, 186, 192–2;
and art 195–6;
existence 198–202;
function 208–11, 213;
243
location 202–6, 213
Armory Show 184–5, 192
arousal model of appreciation 6, 9, 13
Arp, H. 111–12, 118, 120
art:
and aesthetic judgment 53–9;
aesthetics of 75;
and architecture 195–6;
Armory Show 184–5, 192;
artistic appreciation of nature 41–7;
as bad 91–2;
categories see Walton;
critics 18, 19, 22, 27, 30–1, 34–5, 68,
72–3, 85–6, 95, 116;
design appreciation of 107–9;
formalism 18–23, 25, 30, 33;
and Hillerman’s novels 225–5, 237–7,
241;
“junk” 147;
and nature, difference between 34–5;
nouveau 140;
order appreciation of 109–14;
perception and science 85–6, 88–9, 91–
2, 93–4;
see also appreciation of art;
between nature and art;
environmental art;
paintings;
subjectivity
artifactualization 8, 166–7, 170–1
artificial nature 141, 147, 148
artist/designer x, 108, 113, 120–1;
environmental art 149–60 passim;
God as see theism;
intentions and category 58;
lack of 78
(see also nature)
Asian Floodwork (Humphrey) 151
aspection see acts of aspection
Asphalt Rundown (Smithson) 152,
illustrated 153, 158
assimilation of nature appreciation into art
appreciation 114–16
AT&T Building (Johnson) 214;
existence 198–9;
function 209, 213;
illustrated 199;
location 203, 207
attitude, aesthetic 101–5;
see also disinterestedness
attribution of aesthetic properties 57, 60–1
Audubon, J.J. 68
automatic writing 111–12, 118
Autumn Foliage (Thomson) and architecture
195–6;
existence 200, 201;
function 209, 210, 211, 213;
illustrated 197;
location 203–2, 206, 207, 213
awe and wonder 74, 80, 85
bad 29, 91–2, 112;
taste 139–46 passim
Bailey, W. 182
Baker, E. 149, 204–3
Beardsley, A. 20–3
Beardsley, M.C. 123, 139, 140, 147, 192
beauty see positive aesthetics
Bell, C. 18, 19, 22, 27, 30–1
between nature and art:
aesthetic necessity and objects of
appreciation 130–3;
aesthetic relevance 129–35;
appreciation of other things 132–5;
see also eyesore;
Japanese gardens
Biese, A. 86
biology 5, 85, 86, 95, 120
Bird in Space (Brancusi) 41
“blandscape” 183–3, 187
Bowness, A. 241
Branded Hillside (Oppenheim) 155
Branusci, C. 41–3
Breleant, A. 13
Buddhism 173–4
Bullough, E. 123
Bull’s Head (Picasso) 147
Burgee, J. 199, 206–5
Burke, E. 78–9
Burnet, Bishop T. 84
Butler, J. 107
camp sensibility 139–46 passim
Canada see North America
Carroll, N. 13
244 INDEX
categories of art 51;
see also Walton
Cezanne, P. 156
Chamberlain, J. 147
chance 120;
poetry 111–12, 118
Chase Manhattan Bank 203, 206
Christo (Javacheff) 149–1, 155–6, 159, 160,
165, 168
“Claude-glass” 32, 33, 35, 44
“cleaning up environment” see eyesore
“coarseness of detail” 180, 183
cognitive experience see knowledge
Coleman, F. 168, 169
Collage with Squares… (Arp) 112
Colquhoun, A. 217
Complex One (Heizer) 204–3, 206, 209, 211
Conder, J. 166, 171
confusion in nature see ugliness
conservation 73–4
Constable, J. 72, 85–6, 95
consummatory experience 49
contemplation 103–4
context model see engagement
contra-standard perceptual properties 56,
61–2
Crawford, D. 151, 165, 167
critics/critical 75, 168–9;
see also under art
cubism 184–5;
see also Guernica
culture:
embeddedness in Hillerman’s novels
222, 225, 227–35 passim, 239, 241;
and nature 58–9, 70
Dada 111–12, 114, 120
Dali, S. 112, 118, 154
Danto, A. 42
Darwin, C. 85, 100
David (Donatello) 53
David (Michelangelo) 154–5
De Maria, W. 152
desert landscape see Hillerman
design appreciation 120–1;
of art 107–9;
of nature 114–17
design qualities see formal qualities
designer see artist
Dewey J. 4, 47, 49
dialectical appreciation of Japanese gardens
164–7
Dickie, G. 70, 97, 101, 103–5, 112, 116,
123
difficult aesthetic appreciation 133, 165,
167–8, 171–2;
and novelty 183–5
disinterestedness 4, 6, 129;
and aesthetic experience 23–6;
and appreciation of art 101–8;
and appreciation of nature 114–15, 119,
123
Displaced-Replaced Mass (Heizer) 155, 156
Donatello 53
Double Negative (Heizer) 149, 152, 154,
156, 204
Duchamp, M. 42, 112, 147, 154–5, 156–7,
160, 185, 186;
see also L.H.O.O.Q.
earthworks see environmental art
Eaton, M. 129–1, 131
ecology 5, 85, 86, 100, 132
education, aesthetic 114;
dilemma see camp sensibility
Elevated Surface, Depressed (Heizer) 160
Elliot, R. 75, 76, 77, 86, 87, 95–7, 116
emotional experience 15–18, 19
engagement model of appreciation 5–6, 8,
13
enjoyment 68
environment:
being in 37, 46–8;
defined 46–8;
see also architecture;
environmental;
landscape;
nature
environmental aesthetics:
defined nature of x–x;
scope of xi-xii;
views see objectivity;
subjectivity;
see also art;
INDEX 245
nature
environmental art 165, 167, 168–9, 204;
as affront to nature 149–63
essence of nature 170, 173–4
Essex (Chamberlain) 147
ethics/morality 82;
of aesthetic judgment 67–8, 146–8;
of environmental art 151, 162;
of landscape model 45
Euclid 8, 170
Evernden, N. 77
evil, problem of 82
evolution 85, 100, 120
experience see aesthetic experience
experiments in appreciation 111–14
“expressive beauty” 142–3
eyesore argument (and roadside clutter) 137
49, 165;
and life values 143–6, 148, 149;
see also camp sensibility;
ugliness
factual themes in Hillerman’s novels 222–23,
226, 239
Falling Water (Wright) 205;
existence 201, 203;
function 209, 211, 212
false judgments 53, 58, 59
Fels, L. 74
fences 180–80
field sizes 178, 180, 184, 197–6
First Gate Ritual series (Singer) 159–60
“fit” 206;
following function 208–11
forestry 29
Forge, A. 95
form:
and content distinction 18–23, 118–20;
and function in architecture 210–10
formal descriptions in Hillerman’s novels
222, 235, 239
formal qualities in natural environment 28
40;
in current work 29–30;
and formalism 28–9;
significance of 30–8
formalism 129;
and aesthetic experience and art 18–23,
25, 30, 33;
and formal qualities 28–9;
in Hillerman’s novels 222–20, 239
found objects see objects, natural
Fountain (Duchamp) 42, 147
framing landscape 35–7, 44–6, 160;
see also landscape painting;
scenery cult
Frampton, K. 205, 206
Fry, R. 18, 30
Fuller, P. 116
function/functional 134;
architecture 208–11, 213;
landscapes 187–8;
themes in Hillerman’s novels 222, 223,
224–3, 239
futurism in art 184–5
geography 29, 85, 86, 95
geology 5, 120, 132, 224, 227;
and positive aesthetics 83–4, 85, 86, 95
Gilpin, W. 4
Ginevra de Benci (Leonardo) 77
Giurgola, R. 208
Glueck, G. 160
God see theism
Godlovitch, S. 13
Gombrich, E.H. 51, 108, 109, 111, 120–1
good 29, 112;
see also positive aesthetics
Gould, S.J. 100
graffiti 158
Grand Tetons 53,
illustrated 55, 58
Graves, M. 207, 213
Gropius, W. 217
Group of Seven 195, 204
Guernica (Picasso) 5, 53–5, 56–7, 154, 186,
200
Haack, H. 160
Haftmann, W. 110, 111, 112
Hamlet 198–9
Hardy, T. 236
Harlan, J.R. 190
246 INDEX
harmony and calm in gardens 164, 165–6,
169–70
Hart J.F. 178, 181
Hegel, G. 4
Heizer, M. 149, 152, 154–60 passim, 204–3,
206, 209, 211
Hepburn, R.W. 4, 14, 34–5, 39, 46, 52, 60–
1, 63, 71, 89, 114
Hick, J. 98
Hillerman, T. themes/descriptions of
landscape in novels of 217–40;
aesthetic relevance 217–25, 231, 236,
237–7;
art, analogy with 225–5, 237–7, 241;
classic formalism and postmodern
appreciation 220–20, 234–3, 239;
descriptive themes 227–35;
factual 222–23, 226, 239;
formal and ordinary 222, 222, 223, 224,
235, 239;
historical 222, 223, 224–3, 226, 239;
imaginative and cultural embeddedness
222, 225, 227–35 passim, 239, 241;
literary 227, 235–5, 239;
mythological 227, 231–33;
nominal 227–7, 230, 233, 241;
scientific 222, 223–2, 235, 239
history:
of aesthetic experience and
understanding 24–5;
of nature, aesthetics of 3–4, 83;
of production 132, 225–4;
themes in Hillerman’s novels 222, 223,
224–3, 226, 239;
traditional agriculture 175–7, 179
Hospers, J. 142–3
human beings and nature 4–4, 72–4, 83;
anthropocentrism 11, 116–18, 121–2;
“Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic” 13,
116–18, 121;
see also artist;
ugliness
Humboldt, A. von 100
Humphrey, P. 151, 162
Hutcheson, F. 3, 24, 25
imaginative themes in Hillerman’s novels
227, 229–9, 239
indifference, visual 112
information see knowledge
“insideness” of architecture 211–10
intentional, nature not 77–8
Jackson, J.B. 180, 182
James, W. 48, 175, 178, 183, 184, 190
Janson, H.W. 108–9, 110–12
Japanese gardens, aesthetic appreciation of
164–74;
dialectical 164–7;
paradox of 167–71, 173
Johnson, P. 116, 198–9, 206–5, 213;
see also AT&T;
New England Life;
Seagram
Johnson Pit #30 (Morris) 157
judgment see aesthetic judgment
“junk art” 147
justifications for positive aesthetics 76–84,
94, 97, 98, 121
Kant, I. 4, 51, 78, 130
Keene, D. 173
Kinnunen, A. 75, 86
kitsch art see camp
knowledge and cognitive experience 18, 24,
26, 49, 130–4, 227;
see also science
landscape:
literary see Hillerman;
model 5, 10, 12, 41, 44–7;
see also nature
landscape painting 5, 44–6;
rise of 31–2;
and science 85–6;
technique 37;
viewing nature as see scenery cult
Las Vegas Piece (De Maria) 152, 156
LeCorbusier 203, 209
Leonardo da Vinci 77, 106, 154, 158
Leopold, A. 14, 52, 68, 71, 193
Lewis, P. 181, 183
INDEX 247
L.H.O.O.Q. (Duchamp’s Mona Lisa) 154–9
passim
life values 143–6, 148, 149
Lily Pond Ritual Series (Singer) 149, 159–60
literary themes in Hillerman’s novels 227,
235–5, 239
location of architecture 202–6, 213
Lorrain, C. 44
Lowenthal, D. 73
Luther, M. 202
McFadden, D. 173
Mannison, D. 116
Maria, W. de 157
Marsh, G. 4, 11, 73, 85
measurement of aesthetics of nature 30
mechanized agriculture 178, 180, 182, 184,
187
Meeker, J. 75, 86, 95
metaphysical model of appreciation 10, 14
Michelangelo 154–5
Mies van der Rohe, L. 201, 203, 206, 209
Mississippi see under Twain
models of nature appreciation 4–14;
arousal 6, 9, 13;
artistic 41–7;
engagement 5–6, 8, 13;
environmental 46–50, 51;
landscape 5, 10, 12, 41, 44–7;
metaphysical 10, 14;
mystery 7, 8, 13;
natural environmental 5–6, 9, 10–12,
13, 50;
non-aesthetic 7–8, 13, 76–8, 97, 116;
object 5, 12, 41–5;
pluralist 9–10, 13–14;
postmodern 8–9, 13
Mona Lisa (Duchamp) see L.H.O.O.Q.
Mona Lisa (Leonardo) 154, 157, 158
monoculture 180
monuments, public 209–8
morality see ethics/morality
Morris, R. 149, 157, 160
Morris, W. 73
mountains 36, 53–5, 58, 83
Muir, J. 4–4, 11, 52, 68, 73
mystery model of appreciation 7, 8, 13
mythological themes in Hillerman’s novels
227, 231–33
National Gallery of Canada 204, 212
natural order 120
nature/natural environment x, 314;
affront to see environmental art;
and art, difference between 34–5;
artificial 141, 147, 148;
contemporary positions see models;
design appreciation of 114–17;
essence of 170, 173–4;
history 3–4;
incorporated in art see environmental art;
indeterminate 37, 39;
not intentional 77–8;
model of appreciation 5–6, 9, 10–12,
13, 50;
and objectivity 53–5;
order appreciation of 117–21;
untouched see virgin nature;
see also aesthetic experience;
aesthetic judgment;
appreciation of nature;
between nature and art;
formal qualities;
framing;
landscape;
objectivity;
positive aesthetics;
ugliness
necessary landscapes 189–9
necessity, aesthetic 130–3
new agricultural landscapes 178–82, 186–9
New England Life Building (Johnson and
Burgee) 206–5, 213
Nicolson, M.H. 85
nominal themes in Hillerman’s novels 227–
7, 230, 233, 241
non-aesthetic appreciation of nature 76–8,
97, 116;
model 7–8, 13;
see also Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic
non-art objects as “pure forms” 30–1
non-representational sculpture 41–3
North America:
conservation 73;
248 INDEX
forestry 29;
mountain views 36, 53–5, 58;
wilderness protection 5;
see also agricultural landscapes;
environmental art;
Hillerman
novels see Hillerman
novelty and difficult aesthetic appreciation
183–5
Nude Descending a Staircase (Duchamp)
185, 186
object:
of appreciation and aesthetic necessity
130–3;
of appreciation, immersion in x–x;
-focused approach 105–7, 123, 129–35;
intentional artifact, appreciation of 116–
17;
model of appreciation 5, 12, 41–5;
objects, natural:
aesthetic properties attributed to 57, 60–
1, 77;
found and selected 42–4, 112, 113–14,
118, 120–1
objectivity 3–4, 11;
and aesthetic judgment 58, 59;
and appreciation 106–7;
and nature 53–5;
objectivist view xi–xi;
see also aesthetic judgment
Oceanfront Project for Covering Cove at King’s
Beach (Christo) 159
One (Pollock) 110–11
Oppenheim, D. 149, 155–6
order appreciation:
of art 109–14;
of nature 117–21
ordinary xi;
themes in Hillerman’s novels 222, 223,
224, 235, 237
Osborne, H. 76
paintings:
action 110–12, 120;
and aesthetic judgment 53–7;
appreciation 40–2;
representational see Autumn Foliage;
and science 85–6, 88;
see also landscape painting
paradox of appreciation of Japanese gardens
167–71, 173
Partially Buried Woodshed (Smithson) 158
Peacock Skirt (Beardsley) 20–3,
illustrated 21
Penrose, R. 242
perception:
of categories see aesthetic judgment;
Walton;
perceptual properties 56, 61–2;
and science 85–6, 88–9, 91–2, 93–4
Petrarch 3
photography 30, 32, 33, 34, 35, 45
Picasso, P. 140, 147, 155, 238, 241;
see also Guernica
picturesque 4, 10, 44, 45
Piene, O. 157
placement pieces see environmental art
pluralist model of appreciation 9–10, 13–14;
see also culture, embeddedness in
Hillerman’s novels
Pollock, J. 110–11, 112, 120
Portland Building (Graves) 213
positive aesthetics 4, 10–11, 12, 72–9;
justifications for 76–84, 94, 97, 98, 121;
and science 85–95, 98–101;
see also good
postcards 32, 45
postmodernism 130–3, 206–5;
appreciation of Hillerman’s novels 220–
19, 234–3;
model of appreciation 8–9, 13
Potter, N. 81, 82, 115–16, 119
Prall, D.W. 142
presumptiveness 80–1
Price, U. 4
Projects for Tailings (Smithson) 152
prospect in landscape painting 44–6
psychological claim, Walton’s 59–62, 70
purism 222;
see also formalism
reaction, postmodernism of 206–5
Rees, R. 45, 83–4, 86
INDEX 249
relativism 53, 57, 58, 59, 68
relevance, aesthetic 104, 129–35, 217–17,
226–5, 239
religion see theism
representational art 19;
see also Autumn Foliage
resistance, postmodernism of 206
roadside clutter see eyesore
Rock Monument of Buffalo (Sonfist) 160
Rolston, H. 74, 86, 87, 95, 95, 100
Romanenko, V. 84, 85, 100
Romantic Movement 4, 4, 45
Routley, V. 87
Running Fence (Christo) 149–1, 160
Ruskin, J. 68, 72–3, 85–6, 95, 116
Russow, L.–M. 74
Sagoff, M. 40
Saito, Y. 173
Sangam Ritual series (Singer) 159–60
Santayana, G. 4, 13, 37–8, 143
scenery cult 32–7, 44–6
Schelling, F.W.J. von 4
science and nature, aesthetics of 3–4, 5, 11,
29, 119, 120;
and aesthetic judgment 63;
appreciation 85–90, 91–3, 98–9;
Hillerman’s themes 222, 223–3, 235,
239;
model see model under nature;
positive 85–95, 98–101;
see also knowledge
scope xi–xii, 103
sculpture 108–9;
non-representational 41–3;
object model 5, 12, 41–5
Seagram Building (Mies van der Rohe &
Johnson) 201, 203, 206
selected objects see object, natural
sensory/sensuous quality 28, 47–49;
model see engagement
Sepanmaa, Y. 13–14, 97
Serra, R. 204, 205, 206, 207, 209
Shafer, E.L. 30, 33
Shaftsbury, Anthony Cooper, 3rd Earl of 24
5
She-Goat (Picasso) 238, 241
Shepard, P. 45
Ship Rock 219, 222, 229–8, 233–2,
illustrated 234, 235–1, 239
significance 18;
of formal qualities 30–8
Simonsen, K. 74, 79, 80, 81–2
Singer, M. 149, 159–60, 169
size of environments xi, 178, 180, 184, 197
6
Smith, R.A. and C.M. 39–40, 51
Smithson, R. 149, 152, 153, 155–9, 165,
168, 204
Sonfist, A. 160–1, 169
Sontag, S. 139, 140, 144, 145
Sparshott, F. 42, 46–8, 52
Spies, W. 241
Spiral Jetty (Smithson) 149, 156, 204
Spray of Ithaca Falls… (Haack) 160
standard perceptual properties 56, 61–2
Starry Night (Van Gogh) 88–9, 91, 101
Steam Piece (Morris) 160
Steinbeck, J. 236
Stern, R.A.M.:
tower 206–5
Stewart, G. 241
Stokes, A. 37
Stolnitz, J. 24, 97, 101–5, 106, 123, 135,
148, 240
subjectivity 4, 53, 58;
subjectivist (skeptical) view xi;
see also relativism
sublimity 4, 78–81, 98
Sullivan, L.H. 193, 208–7, 212
surrealism 112, 114, 118
Surrounded Islands (Christo) 151, 155
sympathy 104, 105
Taliesin West (Wright) 201, 203, 205, 206
theism/religion 3;
and appreciation of nature 115–16, 117,
119, 122;
and positive aesthetics 81–4, 94, 98;
and ugly nature 3, 83–4, 95;
see also mystery model
“thin” and “thick” sense of aesthetic 142–6
Thomson, Tom see Autumn Foliage
Thoreau, H.D. 4, 11
250 INDEX
Thorn Puller (bronze) 108–9
Tilted Arc (Serra) 204, 205, 206, 207, 209
Time Landscape (Sonfist) 160–1,
illustrated 161
Tolstoy, L. 201–202, 209, 212
topiary 166, 171
towns, rural 182–2
traditional agricultural landscapes 175–7,
179
true judgments 53, 58, 59;
see also objectivity
Tuan, Y.-F. 47–9, 49–1, 189
Twain, Mark:
on Mississippi 15–18, 19, 20, 22–7
passim
two-dimensional views 5, 10, 12, 32–7, 41,
44–7
Tzara, T. 111
ugliness of nature:
environmental art as improvement 157–
8;
humans causing 4–4, 72–4, 83, 175;
religious view of 3, 83–4, 95;
see also eyesore
understanding see aesthetic experience
Union Carbide Building 203, 206
United States see North America
utilitariansim and disinterestedness 24
“vacant and unemployed” state of mind,
disinterestedness as 24–5
Valley Curtain (Christo) 155–6
value(s):
aesthetic 28–9, 46–8;
life 143–6, 148, 149;
“wild” 86
Van Gogh, V. 88–9, 91, 101
variable perceptual properties 56, 61–2
Venturi, R. 207
Vietnam Veterans Memorial 209–8
“viewpoints, scenic” 32, 44–6
Villa Savoye (Le Corbusier) 203
virgin nature:
affronted see environmental art;
beautiful see positive aesthetics
visual indifference 112
Walton, K. (on categories of art) 53–71, 88–
9, 99;
nature and culture 58–9, 70;
nature and objectivity 53–5;
position 55–7, 69;
psychological claim 59–62, 70;
and science/knowledge 88, 91–2
Wechsler, J. 99
West, T. 44
Wilde, O. 20
Wimsatt, W.K. Jr 123
Wollheim, R. 130
wonder and awe 74, 80, 85
worship see theism/religion
Wrapped Coast (Christo) 159
Wright, F.L. 186, 192–2, 201, 203, 205,
206, 208, 209, 211, 212
Zen Buddhism 131, 173–4
Ziff, P. 40–2, 49, 77, 78, 88, 89, 105–6,
123, 131
INDEX 251